0
(0)
Book Cover

Republic – Read Now and Download Mobi

Comments

Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.

From Elizabeth Watson Scharffenberger’s Introduction to Republic

The conversation in Republic begins simply enough. Socrates, who has plainly been on familiar terms with Polemarchus’ family for a long time, forthrightly asks Cephalus about old age. His response, that aging is not as difficult as it is often reported to be, prompts Socrates to wonder out loud whether Cephalus’ easygoing attitude is in part facilitated by his wealth. The old man’s response is affirmative. The wealthy, he asserts, face death without fear; their resources enable them to satisfy their debts to gods and men and also to avoid lying and cheating, and thus they can die with the confidence that they will not be punished in the afterlife. These remarks are what precipitate the discussion of just behavior and moral conduct, which Socrates introduces as he asks his elderly friend whether “justice” (dikaiosynê) simply consists of paying debts and telling the truth. Cephalus politely bows out of the conversation, leaving his son Polemarchus to argue that justice—meaning “right behavior” in general—does indeed consist of paying debts and giving “what is due,” as poets such as Simonides claim. Socrates, however, quickly leads Polemarchus to realize that there are serious logical problems with this traditional conception of justice, in which “what is due” is defined in terms of “help” to “friends” and “harm” to “enemies,” and the young man is left perplexed.

At this point, Thrasymachus leaps into the discussion, asserting that justice is simply “the advantage of the stronger,” by which he clearly means that “justice” is relative—that is, “right behavior” is whatever those in power determine it to be. With a series of questions that recall those he just posed to Polemarchus, Socrates uncovers logical problems in Thrasymachus’ definition as well. Thrasymachus, however, does not give up. Exploding in frustration at Socrates’ naive assumptions about the responsibilities that the powerful bear to those who are under their control, he reformulates his ideas with a bold new emphasis evocative of Antiphon’s thinking in “On Truth.” “Justice”—that is, the circumspect avoidance of doing “wrong” to others and obedience to social rules—is doing what is advantageous to another, who is stronger and more powerful than oneself. “Injustice,” on the other hand, is doing what is to one’s own advantage by taking what one wants regardless of social rules and by aggrandizing oneself at the expense of others. It is what leads to “happiness,” provided that one is not penalized for one’s exploitations. Tyrants who kill and confiscate and rape at will, according to Thrasymachus, are the happiest men of all.

Although Socrates is able to poke holes through the logic of this new formulation with questions that hark back once again to those he has already posed, Thrasymachus’ sulky concessions leave him unconvinced that he has made an effective case for the connection between justice, which through all has not been adequately defined, and “happiness.” Nor are Glaucon and Adeimantus convinced, and it is their persistence at the beginning of book 2 that launches the more systematic and extensive inquiry into the nature of justice and its relationship to happiness that occupies the rest of Republic. In particular, the brothers ask Socrates to explain how justice is in itself the source of happiness, regardless of whether it is recognized and rewarded, and how the just man can be happy, regardless of his material circumstances.

The challenges of defining justice and understanding its effects on long-term happiness, fulfillment, and well-being—all of which are conveyed by the Greek word eudaimonia—lead to the discussion of the ideal city-state, which is posited as a large-scale vehicle for apprehending the operations of justice in the individual. Socrates, Glaucon, and Adeimantus spend a good deal of time and energy discussing how the ideal state will be organized, and how its classes of warriors and leaders will be selected, educated, and provided for; they are especially concerned in books 2 and 3 with the training and acculturation of guardian children, whose exposure to poetry (Iliad and Odyssey in particular) is to be severely curtailed lest they learn harmful values and patterns of behavior.

Yet the three never lose sight of the goals of their examination. By the end of book 4, they arrive at a working (and, in several regards, striking) definition of justice as the condition, or state of being, in which each person in the community—and each element of the individual human soul (psyche)—minds his/her/its own business and does his/her/its own “work.” Since it has been determined that there is in the human soul, as in human society, a natural ruling element, justice is thus equated with the unencumbered rule of these elements: the “gold” class of guardians in the ideal state, which holds sway over the silver and bronze/iron classes, and, in the individual, the rational part of the soul that ought to be master of both “spirit” and appetites.

Author
Plato, Prof. Benjamin Jowett, Elizabeth Watson Scharffenberger

Rights
NONE

Language
en

Published
1880-01-02

ISBN
9781593080976

Read Now

How useful was this post?

Click on a star to rate it!

Average rating 0 / 5. Vote count: 0

No votes so far! Be the first to rate this post.


FROM THE PAGES OF REPUBLIC

... but as concerning justice, what is it?—to speak the truth and pay your debts—no more than this? And even to this are there not exceptions? (1.331c)

 

Is the attempt to determine the way of man’s life so small a matter in your eyes—to determine how life may be passed by each one of us to the greatest advantage? (1.344d)

 

For my own part I openly declare that I am not convinced, and that I do not believe injustice to be more gainful than justice, even if uncontrolled and allowed to have free play. (1.345a)

 

I propose therefore that we inquire into the nature of justice and injustice, first as they appear in the State, and secondly in the individual, proceeding from the greater to the lesser and comparing them. (2.368e—369a)

 

... I am myself reminded that we are not all alike; there are diversities of nature among us which are adapted to different occupations. (2.370a—b)

 

Then it will be our duty to select, if we can, natures which are fitted for the task of guarding the city? (2.374e)

 

But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned, however, not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man: for the just man does not permit the several elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the work of the others—he sets in order his own inner life, and is his own master and his own law, and at peace within himself ... (4.443c—d)

“Until philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy, and political greatness and wisdom meet in one, and those commoner natures who pursue either to the exclusion of the other are compelled to stand aside, cities will never have rest from their evils—no, nor the human race, as I believe—and then only will this our State have a possibility of life and behold the light of day.” (5.473d—e)

 

 

... for you have often been told that the idea of good is the highest knowledge, and that all other things become useful and advantageous only by their use of this. (6.505a)

 

—You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners.—Like ourselves, I replied; and they see only their own shadows, or the shadows of one another, which the fire throws on the opposite wall of the cave. (7.515a)

 

He who is the real tyrant, whatever men may think, is the real slave, and is obliged to practise the greatest adulation and servility, and to be the flatterer of the vilest of mankind. He has desires which he is utterly unable to satisfy, and has more wants than anyone, and is truly poor, if you know how to inspect the whole soul of him: all his life long he is beset with fear and is full of convulsions and distractions, even as the State he resembles: and surely the resemblance holds ... (9.579d—e)

 

These, then, are the prizes and rewards and gifts which are bestowed upon the just by gods and men in this present life, in addition to the other good things which justice of herself provides ... And yet, I said, all these are as nothing either in number or greatness in comparison with those other recompenses which await both just and unjust after death. ( 10.613e—614a)

Published by Barnes & Noble Books
122 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10011

 

www.barnesandnoble.com/classics

 

Plato is thought to have composed Republic sometime
during the 380s to the 350s B.C.E.
Benjamin Jowett’s translation first appeared in 1871.

 

Published in 2004 by Barnes & Noble Classics with new Introduction,
Notes, Biography, Chronology, A Note on Conveyances, Comments & Questions,
and For Further Reading.

 

Introduction, Note on the Translation, Notes, and For Further Reading

Copyright @ 2004 by Elizabeth Watson Scharffenberger.

 

Note on Plato, The World of Plato and Republic, Inspired By, and
Comments & Questions Copyright © 2004 by Barnes & Noble, Inc.

 

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or
transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical,
including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and
retrieval system, without the prior written permission of the publisher.

 

Barnes & Noble Classics and the Barnes & Noble Classics colophon are
trademarks of Barnes & Noble, Inc.

 

Republic

ISBN-13: 978-1-59308-097-6 ISBN-10: 1-59308-097-2

eISBN : 978-1-411-43303-8

LC Control Number 2003116604

 

Produced and published in conjunction with:
Fine Creative Media, Inc.
322 Eighth Avenue
New York, NY 10001

 

Michael J. Fine, President and Publisher

 

Printed in Mexico
QM
3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4

PLATO

Plato was born into a wealthy, aristocratic Athenian family in 428 or 427 B.C.E., and he lived until 348 or 347. He had kinship ties on both sides of his family with many prominent men in Athens. His father, Ariston, died when he was a child, and his mother, Perictione, was subsequently married to Pyrilampes. Plato was raised in Pyrilampes’ household along with his older brothers (Glaucon and Adeimantus), a stepbrother (Demos), and a half-brother (Antiphon). As young men, Plato and his brothers were close to Socrates.

Plato’s familial connections and wealth would have made it easy for him to embark on a political career in Athens. But he did not become politically active, perhaps because he became disillusioned with politics after witnessing, first, the brutal oligarchic regime of the Thirty Tyrants, who seized control of Athens at the end of the Peloponnesian War in 404 B.C.E., and then the execution of Socrates, who was condemned to die in 399 under the restored democratic government for “not recognizing the gods recognized by the city and corrupting the youth.”

Plato traveled in the years after Socrates’ death, and he almost certainly spent time in Megara (near Corinth) and Syracuse (on Sicily). He became close friends with Dion, a kinsman of the tyrant of Syracuse, Dionysius I. Plato probably traveled to Syracuse three times during the period from the early 380s to the late 360s. He and Dion evidently planned to educate the tyrant’s son, Dionysius II, in the hopes that, upon succeeding his father, he would put into practice the political ideals they cherished. But these hopes were never fulfilled. Upon taking power in the early 360s, Dionysius II broke with both his kinsman and his tutor.

In the early 380s, Plato began teaching what he called “philosophy” at a place near the grove of the hero Academus on the outskirts of Athens. The school came to be called the “Academy” because of its location, and Plato remained at its head until his death, when his nephew Speusippus took over its administration. After Plato’s death, the Academy continued to be an important center of research and study for many centuries, attracting students from all over the Mediterranean world.

Plato probably started to compose dialogues before he established the Academy. All but a few of his dialogues feature Socrates as the main interlocutor, and most are peopled with figures who would have been well known, especially in Athens’ elite circles, during the fifth century. A large body of writing attributed to Plato survives from antiquity, including Apology (a recreation of Socrates’ defense speech), numerous dialogues, and a series of letters. Most of these works are considered to be truly by Plato, although the authenticity of some texts (including some of the letters and a handful of dialogues) has been doubted at various points in the last 2,400 years.

THE WORLD OF PLATO AND REPUBLIC


 508  Cleisthenes, son of Megacles, introduced sweeping polit 
 B.C.E.  ical reforms to the Athenian constitution, marking the beginning of democratic government in Athens. 
 490  At the battle of Marathon (26.3 miles from Athens in At tica), Greek land forces, under the command of the Athe nian Miltiades, son of Cimon, defeated an invading army of Persians. Most of the Greek troops who fought at Marathon came from Athens. 
 480  At the battle of Thermopylae (a mountain pass in northeast ern Greece), Persian land forces fought against elite Spartan soldiers under the command of Leonidas, one of the Spar tan kings. The entire Spartan force was killed in the battle. 
 480  At the battle of Salamis (an island near the port city Piraeus in Attica), Greek naval forces, under the leadership of the Athenian Themistocles, son of Neocles, defeated the Persian navy. 
 479  In the battle of Plataea (in Boeotia), Greek land forces deci sively defeated the Persian army, which subsequently with drew from Greece. Under the leadership of the Spartans and then the Athenians, city-states in Greece banded to gether in the fight to free Hellenic city-states on the coast of Asia Minor from Persian dominion. This alliance was soon called the Delian League, because its treasury was kept on the sacred island of Delos; it eventually came un der the total control of the Athenians. 
 c.469  Socrates, son of Sophroniscus, was born. 
 462  Ephialtes, son of Sophronides, and Pericles, son of Xan thippus, introduced reforms to the democratic constitu tion, which expanded the franchise of Athenian citizens and provided more opportunities for political involvement to greater numbers of men, regardless of economic class. 
 458  Aeschylus of Eleusis (in Attica) produced his Oresteia tetralogy (the tragedies Agamemnon, Libation Bearers, and Eumenides,  and the satyr-drama Proteus) in the annual theatrical competition held at the Greater Dionysia festival in the Theater of Dionysus on the southern slope of the Athenian Acropolis.
 454  The treasury of the Delian League was transferred from the island of Delos to Athens. Under the leadership of Pericles, funds from the treasury were used to finance the construction of buildings on the Acropolis, including the Parthenon, which had been destroyed by the Persian inva sion of 480. 
 450s—440s  The relationships between Athens and other prominent city-states (notably Sparta, Corinth, and Thebes) dete riorated as Athens expanded its influence throughout the Aegean area. 
 c.450  The astronomer and natural scientist Anaxagoras (from Clazomenae), who was closely associated with Pericles, is said to be prosecuted on the charge of impiety. Sources reporting this event claim that Anaxagoras fled Athens with Pericles’s assistance and went to Lampsacus (on the eastern entrance to the Hellespont). 
 c.432  Protagoras of Abdera (in Thrace), a “sophist” and profes sional teacher of rhetoric, visited Athens. 
 431  Full-scale hostilities broke out between the Pelopon nesian alliance, led by Sparta, and Athens and its allies, marking the beginning of the Peloponnesian War. Euripi des, son of Mnesarchides (or Mnesarchos), produced Medea in a tetralogy with two other tragedies (Philoctetes and Dictys) and a satyr-drama (Theristai)  at the Greater Dionysia festival in Athens.
 c.429?  Sophocles, son of Sophilus, produced Oedipus Tyrannus (Oedipus the King)  in a tragic tetralogy at the Greater Dionysia festival in Athens.
 429  Pericles dies during the plague that falls upon Athens in the first years of the Peloponnesian War. Cleon, son of Cleaenetus, became the leading politician in Athens until his death in battle at Amphipolis in 422. 
 428 or 427  Plato was born into a wealthy and influential family. His father, Ariston, died when Plato was a boy; his mother, Perictione, was subsequently married to her uncle Pyril ampes, who was politically prominent and closely associ ated with Pericles. 
 427  Gorgias (from Leontini on Sicily), a professional teacher of rhetoric, visited Athens. 
 423  At the Greater Dionysia festival, Aristophanes, son of Philippus, produced his comedy Clouds,  in which Socrates is portrayed as a professional teacher of rhetoric and natu ral science who runs a “Think Factory.” The comedy was awarded third prize (out of three).
 415—413  Under the leadership of Alcibiades, son of Clinias and former ward of Pericles, Athens sent an armada to attack the city of Syracuse on Sicily. After Alcibiades’ defection to Sparta and other major setbacks, the Athenian forces were defeated and the Sicilian expedition ends with many lives lost and almost all ships in the armada destroyed. 
 411—410  During an oligarchic coup in Athens, democratic political in stitutions were temporarily dissolved. Resistance by loyalists led to the restoration of the democratic constitution in 410. 
 405  The Spartans defeated the Athenian navy at Aegospotami off the coast of Asia Minor. 
 404  The Peloponnesian War ended as Athens surrendered to the Spartans. The Spartans imposed strict terms of surren der upon the Athenians, including the destruction of the Long Walls connecting Athens to the port city Piraeus. They also fomented another oligarchic coup and installed in power a group of men, led by Plato’s kinsman Critias, who came to be known as the Thirty Tyrants. 
 403  Democratic loyalists, who took refuge in Piraeus, defeated the Thirty Tyrants and their supporters, and the demo cratic constitution was once again restored. To reduce lin gering factional strife between loyal “democrats” and those who supported the second coup, a general amnesty was declared in 403. Only those deemed directly involved with the Thirty Tyrants were liable for prosecution for crimes against the demos  (people).
 399  Socrates, who had been closely associated with Alcibiades and other men known for their hostility to the democratic constitution, was charged with impiety and corrupting youth. He was convicted of both charges and ordered to commit suicide by drinking hemlock. 
 390s  Plato, along with other members of the Socratic circle (An tisthenes, Phaedo, Eucleides, Aristippus, Aeschines, and Xenophon) began to write “Socratic dialogues.” Athens reemerged as an important naval power in the Aegean area. 
 early 380s  Plato traveled to Syracuse in or around 387, when he be friended Dion, a kinsman of Dionysius I, the tyrant of Syra cuse. It was probably upon his return to Athens from this trip that he began teaching “philosophy” near the grove of the hero Academus on the outskirts of Athens, in a school that came to be known as the Academy. 
 384  Aristotle, son of Nicomachus, was born at Stageira (in Chalcidice). He studied at the Academy from 367 until Plato’s death. 
 378  In Thebes, the general Gorgidas formed an elite force of 300 men that legendarily comprised pairs of lovers. The corps, known as the Sacred Band, reportedly remained un defeated until the battle at Chaeronea in 338. 
 360s  After the death of Dionysius I of Syracuse (in 367), Plato is said to have made two trips to Sicily in order to facili tate the restoration of Dion, who had been exiled by Dionysius I. He and Dion apparently hoped to exert po litical influence on Dionysius II, the tyrant’s son and suc cessor. Plato probably visited Syracuse for the last time in 361 or 360. 
 354  Dion was assassinated. 
 348 or 347  Death of Plato. Speusippus (the son of Plato’s sister Potone) became head of the Academy, and Aristotle left Athens, eventually arriving at the court of King Philip II of Mace don, where he served for a few years as the tutor to Philip’s son, Alexander. 
 344  Dionysius II was exiled to Corinth. 
 339  Speusippus died. 
 338  In the battle of Chaeronea (in Boeotia), the Macedonians under the leadership of Philip II defeated the combined forces of the Athenians and Thebans. The defeat brought Athens, Thebes, and other Greek city-states under the sway of Macedon. 
 335  Aristotle returned to Athens and founded a school near a grove outside the city that was sacred to Apollo Lyceius. The school will come to be known as the Lyceum. 
 323  Alexander the Great died in Babylon. Anti-Macedonian feeling ran high in Athens after Alexander’s death, causing Aristotle to leave the city and take up residence in Chalcis (on Euboea). Upon his departure, his pupil Theophrastus took over leadership of the Lyceum. 
 322  Aristotle died in Chalcis. 

INTRODUCTION

Plato’s Republic has long been recognized as a timeless philosophical masterpiece. Its timelessness results from many factors: its artful composition, its vivid characterizations, its thematic sophistication, and—perhaps most important—the breadth of its interests. As it seeks a definition of “justice” and inquires into the relationship between “right behavior” and “happiness,” the work delves into basic questions of ethics and psychology. In the course of this inquiry, it offers up a striking blueprint for an ideal city-state and thus makes a significant contribution to political philosophy. While making the case for the rule of “philosopher-kings,” it presents influential arguments concerning the very nature of reality and the means by which we human beings might apprehend what is real and distinguish it from what we see and experience in the world around us; with compelling logic and arresting images, it encourages our interest in the fields of metaphysics and epistemology.

It also explores the psychological and social impact of popular forms of cultural discourse and, as part of its delineation of the ideal state, makes a strong—and controversial—case for the censorship of the arts and the tight control of entertainments. Lastly, it paints an awe-inspiring picture of what happens to the soul after the body’s death.

Plato himself was well aware of the fundamental importance of the subjects in his dialogue. He has its interlocutors assert more than once that their conversation, whatever its shortcomings, deals with the most significant issues that human beings can discuss. Yet, timeless as Republic’s concerns are, it is nonetheless the product of a particular era and a particular place. The era is the fourth century B.C.E., and the place is the city-state (polis) of Athens, where Plato was born (most likely in 428 or 427 B.C.E.) and lived most of his life, and also where he founded his philosophical school, the Academy. To appreciate the scope and contours of the far-ranging conversation represented in Republic, it helps to know something about the city in which Plato lived and the cultural milieu in which he composed his dialogues.

Athens in the Fifth and Fourth Centuries B. C. E.:
A Political Overview

Until 338 B.C.E. (about ten years after Plato’s death), Athens was an independent city-state, as were the other major cities of Greece (or Hellas, as it was known in antiquity), such as Sparta, Thebes, Corinth, and Argos. For centuries, each community issued its own currency, used its own calendar, and developed its own system of government and social institutions. Territorial disputes and similar grievances frequently caused wars between city-states and their neighbors; the history of such wars and alliances is long and complicated. Yet, despite their differences, Greeks (Hellenes) throughout the Mediterranean were united by a common language and culture and system of religious beliefs and practices that, they felt, made them distinct from other peoples, whom they commonly called “barbarians.”

Athens resembled other Greek city-states in that it had a predominantly agricultural economy. As in most communities in the ancient world, the work force in Athens and its surrounding territory (Attica) consisted largely of slaves who were either prisoners of war, captives bought from pirates, or their descendants. Political enfranchisement in Athens, as in all other Greek city-states, was limited to sons of enfranchised men. Participation in the government and legal system was completely closed to women. It was virtually impossible for foreigners to become naturalized citizens of Athens, although resident aliens, who were called metics and were almost always from other Greek city-states, were liable for military service and were generally expected to contribute, financially and otherwise, to the community. Women (that is, the wives, daughters, and sisters of citizens) and slaves, both male and female, lived totally under the control of the male head of the household.

Moreover, many of the public institutions that we take for granted, such as hospitals and law enforcement agencies, did not exist in the ancient world generally or in Athens particularly. The cultivation of homoerotic attachments between men (as “lovers,” or erastai) and youths (as “beloveds,” or erômenoi) in the upper echelons of Athenian society—an important backdrop to several Platonic dialogues (notably Symposium and Phaedrus)—further indicates the cultural differences between Athens and contemporary Western civilizations.

Athens differed from other Hellenic city-states in certain important social and political institutions. Unique policies implemented in the sixth century B.C.E. had far-reaching consequences for the development of the city’s famous democratic form of government. Unlike in many Greek communities, the rules determining citizenship in Athens did not require a free-born native man to own land in order to be considered a citizen with some political rights. All citizens, no matter how modest their means, were eligible to attend meetings of the Assembly and scrutinize the performance of magistrates.

In 508 B.C.E., after a difficult period in the late sixth century when men who held power illegitimately (the “tyrant” Peisistratus and his sons Hippias and Hipparchus) controlled Athens, the democratic government was officially established. Its constitution was liberalized during the fifth century so that opportunities to participate directly in the political system were gradually made available to larger numbers of men. Citizens were still divided, as they were in the early sixth century, into four economic classes determined by the amount of property they owned, and they were also divided into ten “tribes.”

Every year men from the highest economic classes were chosen as magistrates, some by lot and some by election. The ten elected magistrates (called strategoi, or “generals”) exercised authority in military as well as civic matters and assumed the political leadership of the polis; most of Athens’ famous statesmen—Pericles, Themistocles, Miltiades, Aristides, Cimon, Cleon, and Alcibiades—were strategoi. The Assembly retained the power to hear debates and vote on all domestic and foreign policies, and it scrutinized magistrates at the end of their terms in office. In addition, fifty men were chosen from each tribe every year by lot to form the Council of 500, the body that prepared business for the Assembly and in essence ran the government on a daily basis.

The average Athenian citizen, especially in the later years of the fifth century, could also exercise political power through the system of courts that tried cases ranging from murder to treason to private suits. These courts always had large juries (a minimum of 250 men, again chosen by lot), and all citizens were eligible for service. Jury duty became especially attractive to many poorer citizens after payment for such service was instituted. Since prominent men were often embroiled in legal disputes, sitting in the courts became an effective way for average people to influence the fortunes of the powerful.

As its democracy developed in the fifth century, Athens was also becoming powerful and cosmopolitan. Indeed, the development of its democracy was inextricably linked to the growth of its military influence in the Aegean Sea. This brought great wealth to the city and empowered its lower economic classes, since they furnished the majority of rowers and soldiers on warships.

Success in the Persian Wars (at the battle of Marathon in 490 B.C.E. and the battle of Salamis in 480) put Athens at the head of the Delian League, an alliance of Greek city-states that was formed to further weaken the influence of the Persians in the Mediterranean. The Athenians, however, gradually monopolized power in the League and used it to advance their own commercial and strategic interests. In the 460s, to protect the maritime trade routes vital to the growing city, Athens began to treat allies on the islands and coasts of the Aegean Sea as if they were subjects, not partners, and interfered in their affairs.

In 454, the League’s treasury was transferred from the island of Delos to Athens, and allies were subsequently required to bring tribute directly to the city. In the 440s, the Athenians, led by Pericles, began using this treasury to finance buildings and extensive public works, including the Parthenon and other edifices on the Athenian Acropolis that are still standing today.

Other leading city-states in Greece, particularly Sparta, Corinth, and Thebes, became alarmed by the development of the Athenian “empire” in the Aegean Sea. Throughout the mid-fifth century, the Athenians clashed with those who opposed their maritime hegemony. In 431, the Spartans and their allies from the Peloponnese (the southern portion of Greece, then dominated by Sparta) declared war on Athens to end its control over the island city-states and coastal areas in northern Greece and Asia Minor. In the series of wars that came to be known as the Peloponnesian War, both sides gained and lost ground over several years, until the defeat of Athens in 404. As a consequence of its defeat by the Peloponnesian alliance, Athens permanently lost its exclusive influence over the Aegean islands. It had to contend for power with other city-states, particularly Thebes and Corinth, throughout the fourth century. Nonetheless, Athens remained the preeminent cultural center of Greece, and when Plato founded his Academy in the 380s, he was able to attract students from all over the Aegean area.

Democracy in Athens also survived the Peloponnesian War, but not without serious challenges. Most Athenians doubtless looked on the wealth and power of their city-state as great assets and saw themselves as the liberators and protectors, and not the oppressors, of their allies. They were also proud of their city’s culture, especially of the freedom of speech and opportunities for political involvement that their constitution notionally afforded to every citizen. Even so, a small but significant percentage of men from Athens’ wealthy aristocratic families considered themselves wrongly dispossessed of political power that, in their view, ought to have been their exclusive prerogative. They felt the democratic constitution left them vulnerable to exploitation and extortion, especially in the courts, where informers (“sycophants”) seeking to get rich constantly threatened to bring them to trial. They also resented the prominence of politicians such as Cleon, who did not use the established “old boy” network of connections and appealed directly to the demos, or common people, for his power.

Wealthy Athenians also tended to disagree with the aggressive military policies that the democratic government pursued, especially the disastrous Sicilian expedition of 415-413 B.C.E., in which a good part of the Athenian navy was destroyed. While many disaffected aristocrats sought to withdraw as much as possible and live quiet lives of “noninvolvement” (apragmosyne), the conflict between oligarchic and populist ideologies caused increasing friction as the Peloponnesian War continued, and the disaster in Sicily galvanized some malcontents and set the stage for radical action. In 411 a short-lived oligarchic coup suspended the constitution and dissolved the Council of 500 and the Assembly. Resistance by loyalists led to the relatively quick and bloodless restoration of both institutions in 410.

After the Athenians surrendered to the Peloponnesian alliance in 404, the Spartans helped the surviving leaders of the coup of 411 overthrow the democracy once again and install another oligarchic government. This new regime suspended the constitution once again, dissolved democratic political institutions, and severely limited political franchise. It also gained renown for its brutality, and, like the government that came into power in 411, lasted only a year. Many men loyal to the democratic constitution took refuge in the port city of Piraeus, which was only a few miles from Athens and a populist stronghold. After a series of battles with supporters of the coup, the loyalists restored democracy to Athens in 403.

To reduce lingering factional strife between loyal “democrats” and those who had supported the second coup, a general amnesty was declared in 403. Only those deemed directly involved with the Thirty Tyrants, as the leaders of the coup of 404 came to be called, were liable for prosecution. Tensions and suspicions remained elevated for many years afterward, however. Although there were no further coup attempts in the fourth century, Athenian democracy continued to generate and, to its credit, tolerate critics. Among these critics, Plato is often counted as the most forceful and articulate.

Religion and Religious Traditions

Athenians were fully invested in the established traditions of Hellenic culture. Religion, and therefore religious rituals and celebrations, were central to this culture. Like other Greeks, the Athenians believed in an array of divinities, from the Olympian gods and goddesses who had Zeus as their king, to the chthonic powers of the underworld, such as the Furies, to local deities, such as river gods. They also deified phenomena that we would consider abstractions, such as Justice, Persuasion, Fear, Madness, and Necessity. The sustained welfare of the community was thought to reside in divine favor, which could be withdrawn if the gods were slighted in any way. Accordingly, every resident was expected to participate in rituals and celebrations in honor of the gods.

In addition to the festivals of individual city-states, Greeks also participated in major biennial and quadrennial religious festivals, such as those at Delphi (the oracular shrine of Apollo) and Olympia (the shrine of Zeus). Even in times of war, men from all over the Hellenic world attended these festivals and competed in their well-known athletic contests. Mystery cults whose members worshiped particular deities—such as the cults devoted to the grain-goddess Demeter and her daughter Persephone at Eleusis in Attica—required their participants to undertake special rites of initiation and keep cultic rituals secret from non-initiates.

The Greeks envisioned the principal Olympian gods and goddesses as members of an extended family who were virtually omnipotent and, although capable of disguise, looked like human beings and were frequently influenced by jealousy and other strong passions. Overall, the gods were thought of as guarantors of justice, rewarding those who uphold laws and customs and punishing those who transgress. But they were also considered capable of adversely affecting human lives in what might strike us as capricious, cruel, and unfair ways. This ambivalent understanding of divine behavior is reflected in Greek poetry and literature, beginning with the Homeric epics (Iliad and Odyssey). In these, deities interfere freely in human affairs and regularly assist their favorite mortal men and women while wreaking havoc upon their “enemies” and competing with their fellow deities.

Religious life was centered on the proper fulfillment of rites in the home and in official public ceremonies. The Greeks put comparatively little emphasis on orthodoxy beyond the very basics of belief, and they had no sacred scriptures equivalent to the Bible or Qur‘an. This lack of orthodoxy accounts in part for the variety in the myths about the gods that have been handed down, often with contradictory details. In the absence of orthodoxy, the Greeks were generally tolerant of special religious sects and schools, such as those of the Pythagoreans and Orphics, and sometimes of foreign religious rites, as long as these could be accommodated to existing beliefs and practices. Because of such tolerance, the poet Xenophanes was able in the late sixth century B.C.E. to question with impunity the accuracy of the representation of the gods in the Homeric epics, and to suggest that popular anthropomor phized conceptions of the gods were mere projections of the human imagination.

As Athens grew in power and prominence during the fifth century, the city attracted intellectually active individuals who sometimes entertained skeptical attitudes toward traditional understandings of the gods. But such attitudes never became popular. Even as Athenians grew more sophisticated and self-conscious about the constructs of their society and culture, most seem to have remained attached to the beliefs and practices of their ancestors. Throughout the classical period (that is, the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E.), it remained possible to prosecute individuals for “impiety” and “not recognizing the gods recognized by the city.” Such was one of the charges faced in 399 B.C.E. by Socrates, Plato’s friend and mentor and the chief interlocutor of most of the Platonic dialogues.

Poetry and Poetic Traditions

By the fifth century, several poetic works enjoyed enormous popularity and achieved quasi-canonical status. Foremost among these were Iliad and Odyssey, two of the epic poems that the Greeks attributed to Homer, although most modern scholars view them as results of centuries of oral storytelling and poetic improvisation rather than as the work of one person. The epics Cypria, Iliupersis (“The Destruction of Troy”), and a series of poems collectively referred to as Returns (Nostoi), which all dealt with the Trojan War and its aftermath and which survive only in fragments, were widely known as well, as were Theogony, an epic dealing with the origins of the gods, and the didactic poem Works and Days, both composed by Hesiod in the late eighth century B.C.E. Memorizing extensive passages of poetry was a standard educational practice in the classical period. Most Athenians would have thus been well acquainted not only with the works of Homer and Hesiod, but also with those by such lyric poets as Sappho, Simonides, Pindar, and Stesichorus, and they would have known other poems in a variety of styles.

Choruses performed hymns and songs at familial rites, such as marriages, and at public festivals throughout the Hellenic world. In Athens, choral performances in honor of Dionysus gave rise during the sixth century to more sophisticated presentations featuring solo respondents. These were the precursors to the tragedies and comedies performed during the classical period at festivals in the Theatre of Dionysus on the southern slope of the Acropolis. The Dionysian festivals were “high holidays” when public and private business was suspended, and the dramas produced in them were of enormous cultural importance in democratic Athens. Although modern scholars debate whether playwrights attempted directly to influence decision-making by their fellow citizens, there is no doubt that these festivals, which intertwined civic and religious functions, helped create a sense of political identity for the Athenians.

Dramas were composed for a single performance. Nonetheless, many were circulated and memorized, and some quickly achieved quasi-canonical status in their own right. It is not surprising, then, that Plato liberally quotes passages from tragedies by Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides as well as other poetic works, most notably Iliad and Odyssey. He cites comedies far less often, but this does not mean that they did not interest him. Plato was particularly concerned with Aristophanes’ Clouds, which was performed in 423 B.C.E. and featured Socrates as a main character; even though Clouds was not the only comedy in which a “Socrates” appeared, Apology 18d-19d indicates that, in Plato’s view, it fostered particularly insidious prejudices against his mentor.

As readers of Republic and other dialogues discover, Plato has Socrates express deep reservations about relying on poetry to educate children and to foster senses of community and social identity among adults. In Republic especially, Socrates repeatedly professes his fondness for the Homeric poems while voicing serious criticism of their contents and ethical and social effects. His refrain concerning tragedy and lyric poetry is similar; they are said to be “charming” and “pleasing” but also dangerous. Comedy, as might be expected, receives almost no compliments in the Platonic dialogues. Yet Republic’s critique of poetry—especially dramatic poetry—is not free of ironies, since Plato is himself something of a dramatist whose dialogues are masterfully constructed “plays” in prose. Moreover, as Jacob Howland observes (The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy, pp. 28-29), he is also something of a comedian who delights, just as Aristophanes does, in exposing the foibles of prominent and self-important men.

Intellectual Innovations:
“Scientists,” “Sophists,” and Rhetoricians

The most self-important person we meet in Republic is Thrasymachus, a diplomat and professional rhetorician from the Greek city-state of Chalcedon on the Bosporus near the Black Sea. He does not play much of a role in the dialogue beyond its first book, but his activities as a rhetorician and, as some would say, a “sophist” lead us to consider another set of cultural, intellectual, and political phenomena that are significant in Plato’s work. The systematic study of effective public speaking, and the teaching of the theory as well as the practice of rhetoric, were innovations of the fifth century; they were impelled in part by the demands that democratic institutions such as public assemblies and courts, first in Athens and then elsewhere in the Hellenic world, created. To attain political prominence and power in a democratic setting, men had to be able to persuade large crowds and hold their own in heated debates. Even those who had more modest ambitions could find themselves needing the services of a teacher of rhetoric or a professional speechwriter when they went to court, whether as plaintiffs or defendants. Thus Athenian men—especially young and wealthy ones—began to study rhetoric and techniques of argumentation in ad hoc arrangements with professional and at times highly paid instructors.

The formal study of rhetoric and argumentation was also linked to a broader set of intellectual trends that originated in the Greek city-states of Ionia (the coastal area of Asia Minor) during the seventh and sixth centuries B.C.E. The driving force behind these trends was the desire to comprehend the workings of the cosmos and all its constituent parts in systematic terms, which was fueled by a spirit of inquiry and skepticism about received truths. Xenophanes, an Ionian émigré to the Greek colonies in Italy, challenged Homer’s and Hesiod’s conceptions of the gods, and Pythagoras, another Ionian emigre to Italy, studied the mathematical bases of music and theorized about the reincarnation of the human soul. Others in Ionia and elsewhere became interested in studying the movements of celestial bodies and explaining astronomical phenomena such as eclipses, in discovering the causes for change and movement in physical objects, and in speculating about the nature of matter. By the fifth century, there were many “pre-Socratic philosophers,” as they are known today, active throughout the Greek world. Among them were Heraclitus, Empedocles, Zeno, Anaxagoras, Democritus, Leucippus, and—especially important to the development of Plato’s thought—Parmenides of Elea (in the northwest Peloponnese). In the early fifth century, Parmenides posited proto-metaphysical concepts of “Being” (or “That Which Is”—to on in Greek) that challenged the assumption that any physical object in the phenomenal world “is” in the absolute sense of the verb.

Although these sorts of speculation never became popular among ordinary people, they were nonetheless culturally influential in the fifth century. This was especially true in Athens, because the city’s prosperity and relative openness to foreign visitors and residents attracted itinerant teachers and intellectuals. Theorizing about natural phenomena gave rise to speculation in other fields, and human society, human behavior, and human nature were among the subjects of such observation and speculation. The development of social institutions, laws, customs, belief systems, and other cultural practices was of particular interest; the Athenian experiment with democracy arguably contributed to an increasing self-consciousness about the roles that human perception and choice, on both individual and communal levels, played in shaping society. In addition to theories about the development of civilization and the degrees of its success in molding human nature, there arose ideas about how the model society should be formed, as well as formulations concerning the correct responses by individuals to the pressures and demands of their societies.

Some of these theories seem quite bold. At the end of the fifth century, a rhetorician named Antiphon wrote a treatise titled “On Truth,” in which he asserts that the laws and customs of society are by nature’s standards “unjust,” and that it is consequently “just”—by nature’s standards—to disregard them, provided one is able to do so without being punished. Rational theories concerning the organization of the cosmos inevitably challenged traditional understanding of the roles played by the gods in ordering the world. These theories gave rise to speculation about the role of the gods in human affairs and, in turn, led some individuals to ponder whether the truth about the gods can be apprehended by the human mind. Less daring but still important were experiments with city planning undertaken in communities such as Thurii, the Athenian colony in southern Italy founded under the leadership of Pericles in 444 B.C.E., which drew on the skills of geometers (literally, “earth measurers”) as well as experts on law and social relationships.

Most of the itinerant intellectuals who gravitated to Athens during and after Pericles’ day—including famous figures such as Protagoras, Hippias, Prodicus, and Gorgias—integrated their study and instruction of rhetoric with broader interests in fields that we today might label psychology, sociology, social theory, anthropology, linguistics, language theory, epistemology, music theory, theology, and cosmology. Many of them also investigated astronomy, physics, and the other sciences, as well as mathematics and medicine. These men and their homegrown Athenian counterparts became known as “sophists” (that is, “men who profess wisdom”), although it is not clear that the term was commonly used in the fifth century.

In some regards, the sophists were not wholly unlike the traveling poets and professional performers of Homeric epic (“rhapsodes”) who had been received in Greek city-states for generations. Many of them performed official services for their home cities and, like Thrasymachus and the Sicilian rhetorician Gorgias (from Leontini in Sicily), served as ambassadors to Athens. Yet the presence of these intellectually adventurous and personally ambitious men would have inevitably struck many Athenians as an alarming sign that times were changing, and not necessarily for the better. Indeed, the activities of the sophists seem to have compounded anxieties about economic and social changes that the developments of democracy and “empire” had brought about. The sophists’ fees were typically so high that only wealthy men could afford to hire them to instruct their sons, and their direct influence was thus limited. Their ideas and modi operandi were generally if vaguely known, however, and the public tended to see their activities, not always fairly, as threats to the traditional norms and practices that were thought to guarantee stability and prosperity in Athenian society.

The fact that the sophists appropriated the family’s role in preparing young men for adult life and, moreover, charged fees for their efforts, very likely made them appear all the more suspect in the eyes of average Athenians. If Aristophanes’ comedy Clouds can be trusted for this kind of information, the lightning rod for popular misgivings about the sophists’ activities was the teaching of rhetoric. Rhetorical education, in the worst-case scenario presented by Clouds, could supply the means for young men to “make the weaker argument stronger” and justify their antisocial behavior; it could enable them to cast out all the received wisdom they had absorbed about the gods, society, and family.

Nonetheless, for all this apparent controversy and anxiety concerning the sophists’ newfangled ideas, the changes and upheavals of Athenian society in the late fifth century had less to do with their influence than we might suppose. These upheavals, leading up to the oligarchic coups of 411-410 and 404-403, are better understood as consequences of the Peloponnesian War and the ongoing transformation of the institutions and practices of democracy. Modern scholars are in a position to see how various theories expounded by intellectuals valorized the positions taken by both proponents and detractors of Athenian democracy, but it is unclear how frequently or how keenly average Athenians concerned themselves with the ideological implications, per se, of the sophists’ ideas. In addition, even though sophists were not popular in fifth-century Athens, there was relatively little backlash against them. It is true that the astronomer Anaxagoras was prosecuted on the charge of impiety in, perhaps, 450 B.C.E., and that Socrates was convicted on the charges of impiety and “corrupting the youth” in 399. Anaxagoras, however, was likely attacked because of his closeness to Pericles, and, as we shall soon discuss, there were probably political motivations behind the charges brought against Socrates as well.

The market for the higher education of young men with wealth and aspirations to political prominence did not abate in the fourth century. Various individuals, some of them native Athenians like Isocrates (436-338 B.C.E.), established schools in which rhetoric and other subjects were taught. Thus, after only a generation or so, the novel and at times controversial educational offerings of the fifth-century sophists and rhetoricians were well on their way to becoming institutionalized and mainstreamed. Plato was a direct beneficiary of this process of institutionalization and, in something of a paradox, he was indirectly beholden to the sophists. To be sure, Plato’s portrayals of men like Protagoras, Hippias, and Prodicus (in Protagoras), Polus and Gorgias (in Gorgias), Euthydemus and Dionysodorus (in Euthydemus), and Thrasymachus (in Republic) are not flattering. He dismisses the claims to knowledge and expertise and educational proficiency that such “professors of wisdom” had staked for themselves, and discredits the ways in which these men and their successors—notably Isocrates—taught rhetoric and the “art” of public persuasion. Nonetheless, Plato’s Academy capitalized upon the desire and demand for higher education that Protagoras, Gorgias, and others had cultivated during the preceding decades. Without the fertile field the sophists planted, Plato might never have had the opportunity to found his Academy—or write his dialogues.

Socrates

It is impossible to conceive of Plato apart from Socrates. A native Athenian who lived from approximately 470 B.C.E. until his execution in 399, Socrates committed nothing to writing. What we know of his activities comes largely from the dialogues of Plato and Xenophon, in which Socrates is very often the primary interlocutor. The other intact source—and the sole one dating to Socrates’ lifetime—is Aristophanes’ Clouds, which antedates Plato’s and Xenophon’s works by twenty-five years at the minimum and was composed when Socrates was not yet fifty years old. There are fragments of other comedies from the 420s that mention Socrates, and a very few fragments of works by other “Socratics” who, like Plato and Xenophon, took to writing about the man after his death and using him as a figure in dialogues.

Aristophanes presents an image of Socrates very different from those of Plato and Xenophon. In Clouds, Socrates is portrayed as a professional sophist running a “Think Factory.” His students pay to learn rhetoric (that is, how to “make the weaker argument the stronger”) and other language arts, as well as absurd “scientific” techniques (for example, how to measure the leaps of fleas) and a novel cosmology positing that Zeus “is not.” This Socrates has no scruple about taking on a pupil who wants to cheat his creditors in court, and he is indirectly responsible for a young man’s beating of his aged father.

According to Plato and Xenophon, however, Socrates was in no way a professional; he had no pupils and took no fees. Plato takes particular pains to distance Socrates from Aristophanes’ caricature and from the sophists. He has him disavow all interest in rhetoric and admit to only a youthful and unsatisfying flirtation with the cosmological theories of Anaxagoras (for example, in Phaedo 96a-100a). The Socrates of Plato’s works professes an exclusive commitment to making his fellow Athenians “better” by urging them to examine their values and actions systematically, on the grounds that “the unexamined life is not worth living” (Apology 38a). He exhorts them to think and act in consistently virtuous, just, temperate, and courageous ways, even if such behavior endangers material prosperity and life itself (for example, Apology 29c-30b); he argues that the welfare and health of the soul are more important than any consideration of material comfort. The Platonic Socrates is depicted, moreover, as a paragon of this consistently virtuous way of life, always electing to do what is truly beneficial over what is immediately convenient and gratifying. So consistent is his devotion to the pursuit of the “good life,” for himself and others, that he is willing to permit himself to be killed for its sake (Apology 35c; Gorgias 522d-e).

Plato may well have crafted his representations of Socrates to suit his own purposes, just as Aristophanes doubtless shaped the portrayal in Clouds in accordance with his comic agenda. If we prefer to believe that Plato’s depiction is the more accurate, it is still possible to understand how Aristophanes could have proffered such a disparate perspective on Socrates’ activities. According to Plato, Socrates’ self-appointed mission of spurring his fellow citizens toward self-examination—he describes himself as a gadfly sent to “rouse” Athens, as if it were a large and lazy horse, in Apology 30e—necessitated challenges to their most cherished values and assumptions—including their own presumptions to wisdom. As a result, he may well have irritated, infuriated, and at times humiliated them. For all the distance that Plato strives to create between his mentor and the sophists, we may imagine that, to the average Athenian, the differences between the challenges to traditional conceptions of just behavior offered by Socrates and someone like Antiphon might not have seemed so great. Socrates could have come across as just another sophist who was relentlessly critical of the traditional and the time-honored.

If Plato’s depiction is reliable, Socrates was also highly critical of Athens’ democratic government. We know that he traveled in the elite circles of Athenian society and was closely linked to prominent men from aristocratic families. He was particularly friendly with Pericles’ ward, the charismatic and ambitious Alcibiades (450-404 B.C.E.), whose extravagant behavior and defection to the Peloponnesian alliance in 415 left his associates under a cloud of suspicion. He also knew Critias, the infamous leader of the Thirty Tyrants of 404-403, and other men who harbored open hostilities to democracy. Socrates was almost certainly not actively involved with the Thirty, but his past associations with Critias and Alcibiades may have caused unease in the tense years immediately after the democratic government was restored in 403. The general amnesty obviated his prosecution on political charges, and it is likely that the charges of impiety and corrupting youth that were officially laid against him in 399 were efforts to drive him into exile because of his political associations and views.

Socrates, however, did not go into exile, even though he could have done so after his conviction. On orders from the court that convicted him, he committed suicide by drinking hemlock. He left behind a band of friends and followers who, because of their dedication to preserving Socrates’ legacy, came to be known as “Socratics.” By the late 390s B.C.E., several texts purporting to contain the speeches of prosecution and defense given at Socrates’ trial were in circulation; two texts by Plato and Xenophon, both titled Apology (which literally means “Defense”), are the only extant examples of the latter, and none of the former survives. Dialogues featuring Socrates as an interlocutor remained popular throughout the fourth century, so much so that Aristotle’s Poetics identifies Socratic dialogues as “examples of imitation.” How scrupulously any of these works—including those of Plato—aimed to represent the actual views and activities of Socrates remains an open question.

Plato

We know the names of several Socratics active during the fourth century B.C.E. in Athens and elsewhere: Antisthenes, Phaedo, Eucleides, Aristippus, Aeschines, as well as Plato and Xenophon. Only works by Plato and Xenophon survive intact, and, of these two authors, Plato is by far the more philosophically significant.

Plato was born into a wealthy, aristocratic Athenian family in 428 or 427 B.C.E., and he lived until 348 or 347. (A note in passing: “Plato” was a nickname according to one tradition, but it is now generally accepted as his given name.) He had kinship ties with many prominent men, including the notorious Critias. A large body of writing attributed to Plato survives from antiquity, including Apology (a recreation of Socrates’ defense speech), Republic and a number of other dialogues, and a series of letters. Most of these works are considered genuinely Platonic, although the authenticity of some texts (including some of the letters and a handful of dialogues) has been doubted at various points in the past 2400 years.

The Seventh Letter, which many scholars today view as authentic, offers an autobiographical account explaining how the vicious abuse of power by the Thirty Tyrants and the subsequent trial and execution of Socrates under the restored democracy persuaded Plato to eschew a political career in Athens. It also details his association with the rulers of the Sicilian city of Syracuse, Dionysius I and his son Dionysius II, and their kinsman Dion, who was Plato’s close friend and student. Plato visited Sicily three times during the period from the early 380s to the late 360s. He and Dion evidently planned to educate the younger Dionysius in the hopes that, upon succeeding his father, he would put into practice the political ideals they cherished. Several scholars have speculated that these political ideals were something like the proposals for the ideal state and the government of philosopher-rulers that Socrates advances in Republic. Whatever their aspirations were, Plato and Dion were disappointed when Dionysius II took power in the early 360s and quickly broke with his kinsman and his tutor.

Soon after Plato returned to Athens from his first visit to Syracuse in the early 380s, he began teaching at a place near the grove of the hero Academus on the city’s outskirts. The school came to be called the “Academy” because of its location, and its original mission, like that of Isocrates’ school, may have been to train young men for civic leadership. Plato taught what he called “philosophy” (philosophia) and subjects he deemed essential to its study, notably mathematical sciences.

Plato probably started to compose dialogues before he established the Academy. In all but a few of his dialogues Socrates is the main interlocutor, and most are peopled with figures who would have been well known in Athens’ elite circles during the fifth century. Plato’s older brothers, Glaucon and Adeimantus, play prominent parts in Republic and figure briefly in Parmenides’ introduction. Several dialogues have identifiable “dramatic dates,” at least in approximate terms. The gathering of sophists and their followers at Callias’ house in Protagoras, for example, is set sometime around 432 B.C.E., and the party at Agathon’s house described in Symposium would have taken place in the spring of 416. Most of these works also contain anachronistic details, which seem deliberately planted in order to underscore their inherent fictionality. It is important for readers to keep in mind that the dialogues are not historically accurate accounts of actual conversations, although they may aim to suggest the kinds of conversations that Socrates could have had with Protagoras, Agathon, Plato’s brothers, and other men. Interestingly and importantly, Plato never represents himself as a speaker, although he is mentioned by Socrates in Apology and by Phaedo in Phaedo.

Many scholars have speculated about the dating of Plato’s works, and at times the speculation has inspired heated controversy. Relative dating of the dialogues is complicated by the fact that there is little external evidence corroborating when any of them was composed. One long-popular approach has been to classify the texts as “early,” “middle,” and “late,” on the grounds that there is a development in styles and concerns that reflects the maturation of Plato’s thought. Apology and the “Socratic” dialogues, which feature Socrates in conversation with various men about basic ethical questions and tend to end “aporetically” (without reaching satisfactory resolutions), are thus thought to date to the early years of Plato’s career, when he was still more or less a “Socratic.” “Middle” dialogues in which Socrates is made to advance positive theories, most importantly the theory of the metaphysical “ideas,” are viewed as reflecting the fruition of Plato’s own philosophical inquiries. Those dialogues that reflect less interest in the theory of the ideas and deal instead with other concerns and analyses (for example, the method of “collection and division”) are grouped together as “late.”

According to this interpretation, Republic is categorized among the “middle” dialogues because, among other things, it contains one of the most detailed expositions of the theory of the ideas, which Plato almost certainly derived independently of Socrates from Parmenides’ theory of “Being.” Some critics accordingly estimate that it was composed during the 370s B.C.E. Yet, once again, readers should be aware that such dating is purely speculative, since it depends upon subjective estimations of the developmental stages in Plato’s thought and style.

The past few decades have witnessed an explosion of interest in Plato’s reliance on the dialogue format, and readers can find overviews of the topic in John M. Cooper’s introduction to Plato: Complete Works (pp. xviii-xxi) and Ruby Blondell’s The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues (pp. 1-52). The fact that he chose to write not treatises, but dialogues in which different points of view compete, coupled with the fact that he never presents himself as an interlocutor, raises important questions about the relationships among written texts, Plato’s actual thoughts, and his teachings at the Academy. Passages such as Phaedrus 274e-278b, in which Socrates asserts that a sensible and noble man treats written discourse as a mere “amusement,” further complicate interpretation of all the dialogues, including Republic. Readers of Republic will note that, at a crucial moment (7.536b-c), Socrates reminds Glaucon that they are “not serious.” And, although Socrates remarks more than once on the importance of the issues he and his companions are discussing, he repeatedly draws attention to their conversation’s incomplete and provisional qualities.

These factors lead some scholars to argue that the dialogues cannot provide reliable guides to what Plato thought. According to this school of interpretation, Republic and its counterparts showcase the Socratic method of inquiry; they are intended to stimulate readers’ interest in asking their own questions, but do not aim to guide them toward specific points of view, or “theories,” on any given topic. Yet there is a definite set of concerns—about the unreliability of opinions held by “the many,” for example, and their heedless pursuit of pleasure and gratification—that is explored and substantiated in several dialogues. The recurrence of these concerns, and the consistent manner in which they are addressed from dialogue to dialogue, suggest that Plato’s written works are not only advertisements for the Socratic method of inquiry, but also vehicles for a complex agenda that is at once ethical and intellectual, cultural and political.

Succinct summary of this complex agenda is impossible. Readers interested in exploring what scholars have deduced about Plato’s interests and aims are encouraged to consult one or more of the excellent studies available today, including Andrea Wilson Nightingale’s Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy, Angela Hobbs’s Plato and the Hero: Courage, Manliness, and the Impersonal Good, Charles H. Kahn’s Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form, Terence Irwin’s Plato’s Ethics, Debra Nails’s Agora, Academy, and the Conduct of Philosophy, and Josiah Ober’s Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. This introduction to Republic merits discussion of just a few basic points.

First, the recurrent expose of the unreliability of “what most people think” functions as a weapon that permits a simultaneous attack on traditional ethical understandings (for example, the identification of “justice” with retribution and vengeance) and on the particular ideological assumptions of democracy. (The most important of these assumptions was that, regardless of social position or experience, free-born male citizens were qualified to participate to some extent in political processes.) The critique that Republic and other Platonic texts offer concerning the pervasive materialist tendencies in Greek culture, which are repeatedly said to prioritize appearances and “external” goods (such as wealth, looks, social status, and political power) over “internal” goods and actual conditions, thus complements their more narrowly focused challenge to the soundness of Athenian democracy’s presumptions and practices.

At the heart of this double-sided critique lies the concern that Hellenic culture encouraged a fundamentally childish attachment to pleasure-not just physical and sensual pleasures, but to the psychological pleasures gained through the exercise of power, or through the indulgence of ambition, pride, grief, anger, and other strong emotions. Athenian democracy is represented as exacerbating these childish tendencies, because it maximizes the number of individuals who are permitted to indulge themselves with little real restraint. The ultimate effect of democracy is to render political leaders helplessly incapable of true governance, since they are inevitably forced to gratify and flatter the common people, who can turn on them with impunity as soon as they fail to please (see, for example, Gorgias 500a-519c; Republic 6.492a-493d).

These criticisms run counter to the self-images that most Athenians—and most Greeks—would have nurtured, although the negative assessment of Athenian democracy echoes points made by other upper-class Athenians writing in the fifth and fourth centuries, such as Thucydides, Xenophon, and Isocrates. Plato distinguishes himself, however, by positioning his critique of Athens’ democratic culture within a far broader interrogation of time-honored values and practices that were not specific to Athens. In so doing, he takes aim at the traditional aristocratic ideology cherished by his own social group, which assumed that the well-born and elite few—purportedly endowed with superior intelligence, skill, resources, and “excellence” (aretê)—possessed a natural and god-given right to power. As Andrea Wilson Nightingale argues (Genres in Dialogue, pp. 55-59), the dialogues time and again expose the ignorance and powerlessness of well-born men who presume and are presumed to be “superior.” Even the gifted and privileged Alcibiades is made to concede the “slavishness” of his desire to “please the crowd” in Symposium 215e-216b.

Yet the repeated exposes of how elite individuals like Alcibiades fail to be morally and intellectually “superior” do not overturn the basic presumption that, in a given community, only a few individuals are sufficiently gifted to wield political power. Critical as they are of the conduct and attitudes of contemporary elites, the dialogues ultimately validate the principle of elitism. Against the claims of democracy’s pluralist ideology, Plato’s works seek to reenergize traditional aristocratic views of political power as a special responsibility and privilege reserved for the very few. In the process, however, they completely redefine who the “best men” (hoi aristoi) are, and completely reconfigure the meaning of traditional terms for the qualities of those best men—that is, excellence (aretê), wisdom (sophia), courage (andreia), temperance (sophrosynê), and justice (dikaiosynê).

At its most basic level, Republic is an effort to forge a consistent and meaningful redefinition of “justice” that goes against the grain of much traditional teaching. Readers will see for themselves how its reconfiguration of what is signified by the term goes hand in hand with its argument for an “aristocracy” of men called “philosophers,” whose apprehension of the metaphysical ideas leads them to disdain appearances of all sorts. Their aretê lies in nothing outward, but rests solely in their mature reason and regard for what is beneficial to the soul.

These thoughts could have been conveyed in any number of ways, and in themselves they do not tell us why Plato chose to write dialogues as opposed to treatises. His choice must have been motivated to some extent by the fact that other members of the Socratic circle were composing dialogues, but there might have been additional reasons for his gravitation toward this versatile form. Certainly the dialogue afforded him great flexibility of expression, and with it he was able to craft attractive alternatives to the very forms of discourse (including poetic genres such as tragedy and epic) that Republic and other works expose as the principal carriers of problematic cultural values.

Moreover, even though the dialogues are not philosophical discourses in their own right—since such can never take place in writing (compare Phaedrus 274e-278b)—they are plainly models of the kinds of conversations that thoughtful men can have. They are, in some regards, advertisements for philosophy, and they might have been composed to engage the interest of young Athenian men in the philosophical studies of the Academy.

We should observe here that Isocrates, too, claimed to teach philosophia, using the term to express the dominant cultural values that Socrates and other Platonic interlocutors vigorously criticize. In a work titled Antidosis (354 or 353 B.C.E.), Isocrates explicitly casts doubt on the relevance of the kinds of studies pursued at the Academy—that is, mathematical sciences that aim at the discovery of absolute truths. Isocrates’ skepticism doubtless reflects the long-running competition between his school and the Academy, and it seems likely, as Nightingale maintains (Genres in Dialogue, pp. 21-59), that the dialogues had the additional function of advancing Plato’s far more exclusive definitions of philosophy and the philosopher. Not only do they counter Isocrates’ definition of philosophy, but they also repeatedly strive to demonstrate how Plato’s “brand” of philosophy is useful to both the individuals who practice it and their communities.

At times, as in books 5-10 of Republic, Plato has his interlocutors directly define philosophia and expound on its usefulness. Yet the dialogue form has the additional virtue of permitting Plato to define philosophia indirectly as well as directly, through the very drama of his “plays” in prose. In the dialogues he is able to show—and not merely describe—what philosophy is, and the benefits it brings as well as the challenges it imposes. On the latter score, the give-and-take of the conversations, especially those in which Socrates and his interlocutors reach neither satisfactory conclusion nor mutual understanding, highlight how emotional factors such as ambition, pride, anger, and fear affect the cognitive abilities and powers of reason in even the most intelligent people. These conversations seem designed to bear out what is claimed in book 7 of Republic, that the “whole soul” must be moved in order for the mind to “know,” just as the whole body must be turned from darkness toward light for the eyes to see (7.518c). The rewards, however, are made to seem worth the trouble of this arduous psychological reorientation. Readers have only to contemplate the ease and grace of Socrates, even as he faces death in Crito and Phaedo, to find compelling “advertisements” for the supreme value of Plato’s distinctive brand of philosophy.

The dialogues present Socrates as a paragon of the philosopher’s aretê. They simultaneously permit Plato and his readers to look back at Socrates in a nuanced manner and mark his shortcomings as well as his fine and admirable traits. Socrates may have seen it as his duty to talk to “anyone, young or old” (so Apology 33a), but Plato’s many representations of Socrates’ conversations subtly bring out how such an indiscriminate approach, however commendable in intention, is unrealistic and ultimately self-defeating. Plato himself, we should note, was considerably more selective than Socrates in his contacts; at the Academy he worked only with people eager to study with him, whom he could vet as a condition of their “admission.” In Plato’s hands, then, the Socratic dialogue becomes both homage to a beloved mentor and declaration of intellectual independence.

Republic

In the manuscripts and ancient citations, the title of Republic is given as Politeia (“Constitution”) or Politeiai (“Constitutions”); Peri dikaiou (literally, “concerning that which is just”) is sometimes listed as an alternative title. The book divisions, as those in Laws, are probably not Platonic, but rather the work of scholars in the third and second centuries B.C.E. The sectional numbers (for example, Republic 327b) found in most modern editions refer to the page and section numbers used in one of the first printed texts of Plato’s dialogues, which was published in the late sixteenth century; like the book divisions, they are retained for the sake of convenience.

Again, the date of Republic’s composition is a matter of conjecture. Some scholars argue that it was actually composed in stages, on the grounds that the current text imperfectly marries two (or more) “dramatic” conceptions. Although the physical setting is certain (the house of the metic Polemarchus in Piraeus), there is much disagreement over the dramatic date. Debra Nails (The People of Plato, pp. 324—326) compellingly summarizes the evidence for viewing the current text of Republic as a combination of and expansion upon two earlier works: first, an inconclusive (“aporetic”) Thrasymachus or On Justice, similar to Gorgias and Protagoras and set in the 420s B.C.E., which would have supplied the basis for what is now called book 1, and second, an Ideal State, which would have been the foundation for what is currently in books 2-5. If the latter composition featured Plato’s older brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus as interlocutors, it would have been set in or after 411. This analysis comfortably accounts for the many anachronisms that arise if one attempts, as some critics do, to fix the dramatic date of Republic in a particular year such as 411 or 410, and it also permits some reconciliation with the apparent reference to the discussion of Republic as “yesterday‘s” conversation in Timaeus 17a-19e, which seems to be set in the 420s.

The text that we now possess surely could have been composed in more than one stage. Yet, since anachronisms are present in dialogues that have readily identifiable dramatic dates, the obligation to explain away Republic’s anachronisms by means of theories concerning its composition is less than pressing. Awkward anachronisms and all, Republic is a unified work with a logical and elegant organization, to which we will now direct our attention.

Socrates himself is the narrator of Republic, in which he tells an unknown audience about a conversation that took place “yesterday.” His main interlocutors, from book 2 on, are Glaucon and Adeimantus. His host Polemarchus and Polemarchus’ aged father, Cephalus, are instrumental in getting the conversation going, and the aggressive challenge posed by the rhetorician Thrasymachus in the second part of book 1 is what determines the dialogue’s main interests.

Other men are present in the dialogue: Polemarchus’ half-brother Lysias, a professional speech writer who is discussed in Phaedrus and whose works still survive; another half-brother, Euthydemus; a man named Charmantides, who could be either an elderly man from the rural Attic deme of Paeania or his grandson; and Niceratus, the son of the well-respected political leader and strategos Nicias. These four men are silent witnesses to the conversation, as are the nameless “others” mentioned in 1.327c. Aside from the slave who calls upon Socrates and Glaucon in the first paragraph of book 1, the only other speaker is Cleitophon, an Athenian politician who briefly comes to Thrasymachus’ aid at 1.340b-c.

We do not know much about Glaucon and Adeimantus aside from what Plato shows us. They participated in a battle at Megara, to which Socrates refers at 2.368a. If this was the battle of 409 B.C.E., they could have been only a few years older than Plato, which is the estimate of most scholars; if it was an earlier battle in 424, they would have been much older. Adeimantus, along with Plato, apparently attended Socrates’ trial (Apology 34a), and both he and Glaucon appear on close terms with Socrates in Republic. Cephalus hailed originally from Syracuse on Sicily, and he and his sons were wealthy, well-established foreign residents in Athens. Represented by Plato as an old man, Cephalus was almost certainly dead by 411. Republic’s original readers would have also known that the Thirty Tyrants had Polemarchus executed in 404 so as to seize his property, and this fact puts Thrasymachus’ passionate glamorization of the tyrant’s self-aggrandizing ways ( 1.344a-c) in an especially ironic light. Thrasymachus, as we have already discussed, served as a diplomat in Athens for his native Chalcedon and was also a professional rhetorician, and Plato has Socrates link him to Lysias in Phaedrus. Cleitophon, who is associated with Lysias and Thrasymachus in the pseudo-Platonic dialogue Cleitophon, had become notorious for his political fickleness by the time Aristophanes produced his comedy Frogs in 405 B.C.E.

The conversation in Republic begins simply enough. Socrates, who has plainly been on familiar terms with Polemarchus’ family for a long time, forthrightly asks Cephalus about old age. His response, that aging is not as difficult as it is often reported to be, prompts Socrates to wonder out loud whether Cephalus’ easygoing attitude is in part facilitated by his wealth. The old man’s response is affirmative. The wealthy, he asserts, face death without fear; their resources enable them to satisfy their debts to gods and men and also to avoid lying and cheating, and thus they can die with the confidence that they will not be punished in the afterlife. These remarks are what precipitate the discussion of just behavior and moral conduct, which Socrates introduces as he asks his elderly friend whether “justice” (dikaiosynê) simply consists of paying debts and telling the truth. Cephalus politely bows out of the conversation, leaving his son Polemarchus to argue that justice—meaning “right behavior” in general—does indeed consist of paying debts and giving “what is due,” as poets such as Simonides claim. Socrates, however, quickly leads Polemarchus to realize that there are serious logical problems with this traditional conception of justice, in which “what is due” is defined in terms of “help” to “friends” and “harm” to “enemies,” and the young man is left perplexed.

At this point, Thrasymachus leaps into the discussion, asserting that justice is simply “the advantage of the stronger,” by which he clearly means that “justice” is relative—that is, “right behavior” is whatever those in power determine it to be. With a series of questions that recall those he just posed to Polemarchus, Socrates uncovers logical problems in Thrasymachus’ definition as well. Thrasymachus, however, does not give up. Exploding in frustration at Socrates’ naive assumptions about the responsibilities that the powerful bear to those who are under their control, he reformu lates his ideas with a bold new emphasis evocative of Antiphon’s thinking in “On Truth.” “Justice”—that is, the circumspect avoidance of doing “wrong” to others and obedience to social rules—is doing what is advantageous to another, who is stronger and more powerful than oneself. “Injustice,” on the other hand, is doing what is to one’s own advantage by taking what one wants regardless of social rules and by aggrandizing oneself at the expense of others. It is what leads to “happiness,” provided that one is not penalized for one’s exploitations. Tyrants who kill and confiscate and rape at will, according to Thrasymachus, are the happiest men of all.

Although Socrates is able to poke holes through the logic of this new formulation with questions that hark back once again to those he has already posed, Thrasymachus’ sulky concessions leave him unconvinced that he has made an effective case for the connection between justice, which through all has not been adequately defined, and “happiness.” Nor are Glaucon and Adeimantus convinced, and it is their persistence at the beginning of book 2 that launches the more systematic and extensive inquiry into the nature of justice and its relationship to happiness that occupies the rest of Republic. In particular, the brothers ask Socrates to explain how justice is in itself the source of happiness, regardless of whether it is recognized and rewarded, and how the just man can be happy, regardless of his material circumstances.

The challenges of defining justice and understanding its effects on long-term happiness, fulfillment, and well-being-all of which are conveyed by the Greek word eudaimonia—lead to the discussion of the ideal city-state, which is posited as a large-scale vehicle for apprehending the operations of justice in the individual. Socrates, Glaucon, and Adeimantus spend a good deal of time and energy discussing how the ideal state will be organized, and how its classes of warriors and leaders will be selected, educated, and provided for; they are especially concerned in books 2 and 3 with the training and acculturation of guardian children, whose exposure to poetry (Iliad and Odyssey in particular) is to be severely curtailed lest they learn harmful values and patterns of behavior.

Yet the three never lose sight of the goals of their examination. By the end of book 4, they arrive at a working (and, in several regards, striking) definition of justice as the condition, or state of being, in which each person in the community—and each element of the individual human soul (psyche)minds his/her/its own business and does his/her/its own “work.” Since it has been determined that there is in the human soul, as in human society, a natural ruling element, justice is thus equated with the unencumbered rule of these elements: the “gold” class of guardians in the ideal state, which holds sway over the silver and bronze/iron classes, and, in the individual, the rational part of the soul that ought to be master of both “spirit” and appetites.

The demonstration of how the rule of the superior element generates happiness in community and individual alike, however, is postponed until books 8 and 9. At the beginning of book 5, the brothers join Polemarchus, Thrasymachus, and the others in pressing Socrates to explain some of the extraordinary provisions he has stipulated for the lifestyle of the ideal state’s guardian classes. The group is most keenly interested in the proposed abolition of individual families. Socrates’ explanation of the “community” of wives and children among the guardians leads to exploration of a series of related topics: (1) the near-equality of female guardians, who would be warriors and leaders; (2) the abolition of private property in the guardian classes; and (3) the overall possibility of the ideal state as it has been heretofore envisioned.

In response to Glaucon’s query about this last issue, Socrates presents his bold thesis: The ideal state will come into being when “philosophers are kings, [and] the kings and philosophers of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy...” (5.473d-e). This statement drives the rest of the discussion in books 5-7, in which Socrates seeks with Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’ help to define philosophers, delineate the ultimate goal of their practice of philosophy as well as its utility, and outline the educational curriculum that would prepare philosophers, who are identified with the gold class of the ideal state, for their political responsibilities. In the course of this discussion, Socrates introduces the concept of metaphysical entities possessing true “being”; he calls them “ideas” (ideai and also eidê in Greek, terms that are sometimes translated as “forms”), and he presumes Plato’s brothers know something about them. He also argues, using the image of the “divided line,” that there are four distinct cognitive faculties whereby different types of objects are apprehended, ranging from the ideas themselves to entities in the phenomenal world to mere “reflections” and “imitations.”

To facilitate his audience’s appreciation of these abstract concepts, he develops two more striking images: the simile of the sun, which conveys the supreme importance of the idea of the good, and the allegory of the cave, which describes the difficult path of enlightenment undertaken by the philosopher. As the allegory explains, the ultimate goal of philosophy is in fact apprehension of the idea of the good, which is the source of “goodness” in all other things. Yet philosophy’s arduous “upward” journey to the apprehension of “true being” is not for everyone. Only those few with the talent, training, and discipline that permit “knowledge” of the idea of the good will correctly estimate what is good in the phenomenal world. They alone, according to Socrates, should be allowed to have political power.

The alternatives to the rule of philosophers are four dysfunctional constitutions, which Socrates describes and ranks in book 8, moving from the least problematic (“timarchy,” oligarchy) to the most defective (democracy, tyranny). These constitutions supply bases for identifying and analyzing the personalities of four types of individuals, who yield to the lesser elements in the soul. Their yielding to the inferior elements is contrasted with the rule of reason in the soul of the “kingly” or “aristocratic” just man, and is accordingly found to be the source of psychic dysfunction and misery. Thus Socrates, Glaucon, and Adeimantus not only establish the inviolable happiness of the just man, who is all but explicitly identified with the philosopher, but they also bring into full view (in book 9) the utterly wretched and enslaved condition of the tyrant, whose freedom and happiness Thrasymachus had celebrated in book 1. Moreover, the close association of democracy with tyranny at the end of book 8 caps the dialogue’s exposé of democracy’s errors and inadequacies.

With Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’ challenge thus met, Socrates reaffirms in book 10 the propriety of the ideal state’s careful censorship of poetic texts and, adding to the arguments presented in books 2 and 3, he suggests that adults as well as children should be shielded from poetry’s seductive yet dangerous charms. As Glaucon and Adeimantus rescind the cynical vision they had conjured for the sake of argument at the beginning of book 2, Socrates details how justice does in fact bear rewards in life. He thereupon draws the discussion to a close by relating a myth that describes the even greater rewards for the just—and the extreme punishments of the unjust—in the afterlife. The myth also reasserts the abiding importance of reason and philosophy for souls who, after a thousand-year absence, are about to choose their next lives in this world.

Republic covers many topics, as Socrates concedes at the beginning of book 6, (6.484a), and its exploration of justice’s relationship to happiness takes a circuitous route. The dialogue’s composition, however, is hardly haphazard. The preliminary conversation in book 1, though unsatisfactory, not only raises the issues that will be addressed in the rest of the work, but it also anticipates, through a variety of means, key formulations and points that Socrates will make in later books. Indeed, almost every detail in book 1 looks ahead to later developments; let us note here just a few examples of how this is so.

In his exchanges with Polemarchus and Thrasymachus, Socrates repeatedly compares the just individual/ruler to professionals with technical expertise and knowledge, such as doctors, musicians, and ships’ pilots. These analogies may strike readers as bizarre if not nonsensical; they pave the way, however, for the definition of justice as the rule of the soul’s rational element, and thus for the crucial associations of justice with expert knowledge—and of the philosopher with the just man. So, too, does the simple observation that each thing has a particular function (1.352e-353a) presage the definition of justice as “doing one’s own work.”

In addition, Socrates ultimately affirms that it is fair to conceive of justice as “giving what is due” and also as “the interest (or advantage) of the stronger,” although he does so by assigning meanings to these phrases that are wholly different from those intended by Polemarchus at 1.332a-c and Thrasymachus at 1.338c. On the other hand, Thrasymachus’ assumption that happiness resides in the satisfaction of appetites and desires (for example, in 1.344a-c) is completely overturned, insofar as justice is equated with the submission of the appetitive element of the soul to reason, its natural ruler. His corollary assumption that rulers willingly hold power (1.345e) is challenged in equally forceful terms by the allegory of the cave in book 7.

The ignorance in Cephalus’ declaration that wealth and property are facilitators of just behavior and moral excellence ( 1.331a-b) is likewise exposed during the analysis of degenerate constitutions in books 8 and 9, which posits private property as the principal catalyst for personal interests that will conflict with those of the community. Cephalus’ concerns for rewards and punishments in the afterlife are borne out, though, by the Myth of Er in book 10. The fact that Polemarchus immediately relies on the authority of the poet Simonides to support his problematic definition of justice (1.331d) sets the stage for Socrates’ arguments in books 2, 3, and 10 concerning the need to censor poetry.

Even the small details concerning Socrates’ and Glaucon’s visit to Piraeus—they are spectators who wish to view (theâsthai) the festival of Bendis—foreshadow the emphases placed in books 5-7 on philosophical contemplation (theôria) of “that which is” and in book 10 on Er’s vision (thea) of the afterlife (Nightingale, “On Wandering...,” pp. 33-39). The very first word of the dialogue, katebên (“I went down”), arguably looks ahead to the obligation that the ideal state would impose upon philosophers, who must descend (katabainein) from the sunlit world of “being” into the cave-prison of phenomenal experience, where they are to serve as unwilling rulers (7.519d; 7.539e).

The fact that book 10, which is something of a coda to the rest of the text, explores in depth topics of concern at the very beginning of book 1—that is, poetry’s “truthfulness” and pretense to moral authority, and the afterlife’s rewards for justice and punishment of wrongdoing—suggests that Republic’s “narrative” is structured in an almost circular pattern. This circular pattern is complex, but it has important symmetries. Most basically, the dialogue’s two main concerns (defining justice and ascertaining its relationship to happiness) are treated in two corresponding sections (books 2-4 and books 8-9) that are interrupted by what is nominally a series of digressions in books 5-7.

These nominal digressions, however, create the dialogue’s cen terpiece, a tour de force exposition of philosophical concepts that happens to be, at the same time, a literary masterwork. The definition of the philosopher offered in books 5-7, in conjunction with the metaphysical and epistemological concepts it introduces, provides the foundation not only for the “proofs” of the just man’s happiness and the tyrant’s misery in book 9, but also for the renewed critique of poetic mimesis in book 10.

Moreover, the passage makes a vivid and compelling case for what were arguably Plato’s own conceptions of how philosophy should be defined and pursued, and of how it could be used. The sustained distinction made in books 5-7 between the philosopher and mere “lovers of sights” (philotheamones), culminating in the allegory of the cave, seems fundamental to Plato’s work as a whole and to the political, ethical, and cultural agenda advanced in his dialogues. As such, it is appropriately showcased at the very center of Republic, which is one of his most ambitiously comprehensive texts.

The complex “circular” structure of Republic has the additional virtue of evoking the narrative patterns of epic poems such as Iliad and Odyssey. Critics as far back as Friedrich Nietzsche have commented on Plato’s rivalry with “Homer,” whose works attract particular scrutiny throughout Republic, and we might join Jacob Howland (The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy, pp. 30-31) and others in viewing the dialogue as a “philosophical epic.” Republic’s aim, then, is perhaps not only to critique the Homeric epics and the entire poetic tradition they head, but also to provide a fitting alternative to them, as it reworks their narrative patterns while revising their themes and concerns.

Republic derives coherence from its thematic focuses as well as its “plot” development. As is natural in a conversation about justice and “right conduct,” the concern for human excellence (aretê) pervades the text. Its treatment of aretê plainly responds to works like Iliad and Odyssey and the general values of Hellenic culture. Against their “lessons,” it seeks to redefine and limit what is meant by aretê, so as to exclude from its definition all notions of material success and identify it solely with what we would call “moral excellence” or “virtue.”

Like many other Platonic texts, Republic advances its argument about aretê by scrutinizing the role that the desire for pleasure and the fear of pain play in determining the attitudes and values that most people entertain about “virtue.” This is not to say, as the discussion of book 9 makes plain, that the philosopher has no regard nor desire for pleasure. Rather, the philosopher’s estimation of what constitutes the greatest pleasure differs radically from common views, and this is why he (or she) lives more happily than the majority of people. Like many other Platonic texts (notably Symposium and Phaedrus ), Republic is profoundly concerned with eros—that is, “erotic” desire that can find purely spiritual and intellectual as well as physical outlets. Book 9, by no accident, represents the tyrant as overwhelmed and enslaved by sexual desire more than any other appetite, and it thus positions him as polar opposite to the philosopher who, as a “lover of the vision of truth” (5.475e), achieves liberation to the fullest extent.

As the opposition of the tyrant and the philosopher indicates, servitude and enslavement, freedom and liberation also figure prominently in Republic’s nexus of thematic concerns. Thrasymachus’ initial conception of the tyrant as supremely free and happy, for all its arresting frankness, in fact reflects what most people think—at least if we trust Glaucon and Adeimantus in book 2—but the discussion in book 9 betrays the egregious error of this view. Much of Republic’s energies, then, are directed at challenging common understandings of “slavery,” “enslavement,” and “freedom,” as well as “justice” and “excellence,” and at reconfiguring what these terms mean. At the same time, the dialogue aims to demonstrate how the seemingly outrageous, “amoral” opinions espoused by a sophist like Thrasymachus do little more than reflect the thinking of the many.

The characterizations of the interlocutors are also crucial to the sense of unity and coherence in Republic, and they reinforce its key concerns and themes in subtle yet significant ways. Plato’s representations of Thrasymachus, Polemarchus, Cephalus, Glaucon, and Adeimantus doubtless combine fact with dramatic expedience, and they are as vivid and pointed as those in any other dialogue. Readers interested in detailed and sophisticated analysis of Republic’s handling of “character” should consult Ruby Blondell’s The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues (pp. 165-250).

By way of a few simple observations, we may note the immediate contrast presented in book 1 between the aggressive and contemptuous Thrasymachus and the more easygoing Polemarchus and Cephalus. These three are to be contrasted with Glaucon and Adeimantus who, though cooperative and on excellent terms with Socrates, can be persistent questioners. In his confidence and self-importance, Thrasymachus resembles the prominent rhetoricians, sophists, and politicians familiar from other dialogues such as Protagoras, Gorgias, and Euthydemus; his aggressiveness also holds up a mirror to the ideology of “might makes right” that he so enthusiastically embraces. He is out of place, however, in the friendly and almost homey atmosphere of Polemarchus’ house, since he is outnumbered by others keen to participate in a cooperative investigation, rather than witness a verbal competition.

Yet, as much as it owes to Polemarchus’ enthusiasm and the relaxed atmosphere of his home, Republic’s investigation of justice gets under way only because of Glaucon and Adeimantus. Most crucially, the brothers lack Thrasymachus’ egotism, and they are also plainly meant to seem sharper, better educated, and more intellectually gifted than Polemarchus. At 2.367e Socrates explicitly admires Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’ natural talent and ability (physis). The brothers’ conduct and conversation are doubtless intended to reinforce his oft-repeated insistence that both political leadership and philosophy—the two are ideally identical—can be practiced only by a naturally talented, well-trained, and disciplined few.

The good-natured Cephalus lacks the youthful energy and self-discipline to exercise his mind; Polemarchus, though willing, is clearly not able to “philosophize.” In contrast, Thrasymachus may have sufficient natural intelligence to engage in the kind of conversation undertaken by Socrates and Plato’s brothers, but his competitive nabits of self-promotion stand in his way. Modern readers may find Glaucon and Adeimantus too compliant and not sufficiently persistent in their interrogations of Socrates’ formulations and assessments. It is not clear, however, that Republic’s original readers would have so judged them, and it may well be that the two are offered up to readers as youthful models of the philosophical temperament who have benefited from proper education and training.

As we noted above, the importance of Republic’s concerns is affirmed on several occasions by its own interlocutors. It is, of course, Socrates who first asserts this importance, as he incredulously asks Thrasymachus at 1.344e, “Is the attempt to determine the way of man’s life so small a matter in your eyes?”

As we also remarked, Republic’s interlocutors draw attention to the incomplete, provisional, and at times unsatisfactory nature of their treatment of justice, happiness, the ideal political community, the theory of the ideas, the cognitive faculties of human beings, etc. The inadequacy of “the method we are employing” is acknowledged at 4.435c-d, and referring to this acknowledgment, Socrates cautions at 6.504b-d that the philosopher’s examination of justice, wisdom, temperance, and courage “must take a longer and more circuitous way.” His refusal to describe the idea of the good except by means of a simile, on the grounds that the task of delineating the good-in-itself is beyond the present conversation (6.506d—e), is matched by his admission in book 7 that dialectic “is not a theme to be treated of in passing only, but will have to be discussed again and again” (7.532d). Republic, we may conclude, is not meant to offer a definitive “last word” on any of the subjects it broaches. By no means does it tell readers everything that they need to know about justice, about the formation of functional political communities, about the practices and aims of philosophy, about the method of dialectic, about the ideas, even about poetry.

Readers familiar with Plato know well that other dialogues, notably Statesman and Laws, offer perspectives on these very same topics that complement, but also at times differ from, what is presented in Republic, and these differences further underscore the lack of definitiveness in Republic. Nonetheless, Republic is strongly suggestive, and, like its companion dialogues, it is full of “good ideas.” It offers up an enjoyable and—by its own standards—wholesome mimesis of a philosophical discussion, and it grants what was surely meant to be an enticing glimpse into the actual practice of Platonic philosophy.

Republic’s dialogue form encourages us to come forth with our own questions. Socrates’ defense of his conception of the ideal city-state qua ideal (5.472d-e), for example, may prompt us to wonder whether Plato actually thought this theoretical model for a political community was practicable. The gradual identification of the just man with the philosopher in books 6-9 invites speculation as to whether, on the logic of Republic, anyone but the philosopher can be “just” and “happy.”

If we approach the text from an analytic and conceptual standpoint, we find that Socrates and his companions make innumerable assumptions and countless leaps of logic. Each of these can be fairly scrutinized and contested. On a different score, we may raise any number of questions about the insights the dialogue might offer us into our world, and also about its relevance to our experiences and value systems. Much of Republic, especially its political philosophy and argument for censorship, is at odds with modern ideals; some readers will doubtless be dissatisfied with, among other things, its unapologetic elitism and naive confidence in the integrity of “philosopher-rulers.” Some, however, may find that its critique of ancient Athenian society opens the door to meaningful questions about contemporary cultural practices and priorities.

Whatever questions we ask, and whatever kind of “dialogue” we undertake with this text, we will do well to keep in mind that countless individuals from antiquity to the present have shared Republic’s concerns and been influenced by its conceptions—on matters ethical, political, metaphysical, epistemological, eschatological, or aesthetic. Various elements of Plato’s thought also find important parallels in the philosophical and religious traditions of other ancient cultures, such as Confucianism and Buddhism. Republic, then, might have been composed by a single individual in response to a particular set of cultural circumstances in fourth-century B.C.E. Athens, but the questions it raises and the approaches it takes to dealing with these questions are not wholly unique to Plato or even to ancient Athens. The spirit of Socratic—and Platonic—inquiry thus bids each of us to ask our own questions of Republic and let it help us, in turn, examine ourselves and our world.

 

Elizabeth Watson Scharffenberger received her A.B. in Classical Languages and Literatures from the University of Chicago and her M.A., M.Phil., and Ph.D. in Classics from Columbia University. A specialist in the culture and literature of Athens during the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E., she currently teaches at Columbia University.

Sources and Acknowledgments

For assistance in composing the introduction and notes to this volume, I have drawn on a variety of sources. James Adams’ commentary on Republic, though more than a century old and controversial in places, has been a great asset, as have been the more recent commentaries by Stephen Halliwell and Penelope Murray. The critical studies of Plato and Republic listed in the bibliography have contributed much to my understanding of the dialogue and its significance; of these, I am most indebted to Andrea Wilson Nightingale’s Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy. Meriting special mention among the more general works is M. L. West’s Ancient Greek Music, which supplies a wealth of important information about ancient instruments and musical tastes and is a particularly welcome companion to the study of book 3’s critique of music and song.

My colleagues and students are owed my boundless gratitude, since they have enriched my appreciation of Plato and Republic in the good old-fashioned Socratic way. My utmost thanks go to Professor Leonardo Taran and Professor James Coulter at Columbia University. Their graduate-level courses on Plato first sparked my enthusiasm for ancient philosophy, and their thoughtful suggestions regarding this edition of Republic have proven invaluable.

Many thanks are also due to the editor of this series, Jeffrey Broesche, and his staff for their patient effort in improving my work and bringing the volume to publication.

NOTE ON THE TRANSLATION

Benjamin Jowett (1818-1893) was appointed the Regius Professor of Greek at Oxford University’s Balliol College in 1855. He became master of Balliol in 1870 and vice-chancellor of the University in 1882. He was a prolific translator of ancient Greek texts as well as author of many scholarly works on the classics. His translation of Plato’s Republic, which was first published in 1871, enjoyed wide popularity for decades in English-speaking countries around the world.

In his review of the third edition of Jowett’s The Dialogues of Plato,a the eminent American classicist Paul Shorey states the following: “Ingenious, fluent, easy are epithets we apply to Professor jowett’s renderings; we should never, I think, call them inevitable” (p. 351). Shorey thus tactfully calls our attention to the fact that jowett’s translation of Plato is not as literal as it could be. As Shorey observes throughout his review, Jowett strove not merely to translate Plato but to interpret him—and to transform his Greek into something that would appeal to English-speaking readers in Great Britain and elsewhere during the Victorian era. The diction of his translation of Republic is accordingly stylized in a way that is at times alien to Plato’s nuanced and precise idiom, and in places its style may strike some modern readers as flowery, if not florid. To enhance its appeal to an audience familiar with English-language classics, Jowett embellished his version of Republic with language evocative of famous literary works dating from the Renaissance on, and readers of this edition should not be surprised if Socrates and his companions occasionally sound as if they were quoting from Shakespeare or the King James version of the Bible.

Nonetheless, Jowett’s translation of Republic remains eminently readable, and I have introduced into it a minimum number of changes. Most important are the corrections called for by Paul Shorey, who spotted several places in which Jowett mistranslated the Greek text. A list of the sections in which I have incorporated the corrections recommended by Shorey is given at the end of this note. In addition, I have occasionally replaced obsolete vocabulary with words more commonly used today. Some of Jowett’s choices, such as the rendering of the Greek word theos by “God” (with a capital G), appear so often as to make their alteration difficult; in these cases, I have left his text intact and discuss his choices—and why I disagree with them—in the endnotes. I also discuss in the endnotes a few instances in which I prefer a different reading of the Greek text but have not altered Jowett’s translation.

Jowett sometimes let the Greek usage, in which nouns designating inanimate as well as animate objects have gender (that is, masculine, feminine, or neuter), guide his choice of pronouns. Thus “soul” (psychê), which is feminine in Greek, is referred to by feminine pronouns such as “she”; “sun,” which is masculine (helios), is “he,” and so forth. I have changed Jowett’s renderings of these pronouns in only a few instances, since readers, once aware of his practice, will be able to make good sense of the passages in question.

 

Passages in this edition that incorporate corrections recommended
by Paul Shorey:

1.341c, 1.344e, 4.437d, 4.439e, 5.464e, 5.473a, 6.490d, 6.493c-d, 6.498a, 7.523c, 7.525b, 7.526c, 7.534a, 7.540b, 8.553d, 9.575c, 9.576d, 9.579c, 9.581c, 9.581d-e, 10.607a, 10.611b.

BOOK 1

SPEAKERSb

SOCRATES
GLAUCON
ADEIMANTUS
POLEMARCHUS
CEPHALUS
THRASYMACHUS
CLEITOPHON

I WENT DOWN YESTERDAY to the Piræusc with Glaucon, the son of Ariston, that I might offer up my prayers to the goddess;d and also because I wanted to see in what manner they would celebrate the festival, which was a new thing. I was delighted with the procession of the inhabitants; but that of the Thracians was equally, if not more, beautiful. When we had finished our prayers and viewed the spectacle, we turned in the direction of the city; and at that instant Polemarchus, the son of Cephalus, chanced to catch sight of us from a distance as we were starting on our way home, and told his slave to run and bid us wait for him. The slave took hold of me by the cloak behind, and said, Polemarchus desires you to wait.

327
b

I turned round, and asked him where his master was.

There he is, said the slave, coming after you, if you will only wait.

Certainly we will, said Glaucon; and in a few minutes Polemarchus appeared, and with him Adeimantus, Glaucon’s brother, Niceratus, the son of Nicias, and several others who had been at the procession.

c

Polemarchus said to me, I perceive, Socrates, that you and your companion are already on your way to the city.

You are not far wrong, I said.

But do you see, he rejoined, how many we are?

Of course.

And are you stronger than all these? for if not, you will have to remain where you are.

May there not be the alternative, I said, that we may persuade you to let us go?

But can you persuade us, if we refuse to listen to you? he said.

Certainly not, replied Glaucon.

Then we are not going to listen; of that you may be assured.

Adeimantus added: Has no one told you of the torch-race on horseback in honor of the goddess which will take place in the evening?

328

With horses! I replied. That is a novelty. Will horsemen carry torches and pass them one to another during the race?

Yes, said Polemarchus; and not only so, but a festival will be celebrated at night, which you certainly ought to see. Let us rise soon after supper and see this festival; there will be a gathering of young men, and we will have a good talk. Stay then, and do not be perverse.

b

Glaucon said, I suppose, since you insist, that we must.

Very good, I replied.

Accordingly we went with Polemarchus to his house; and there we found his brothers Lysias and Euthydemus, and with them Thrasymachus the Chalcedonian, Charmantides the Pæanian, and Cleitophon, the son of Aristonymus. There too was Cephalus, the father of Polemarchus, whom I had not seen for a long time, and I thought him very much aged. He was seated on a cushioned chair, and had a garland on his head, for he had been sacrificing in the court; and there were some other chairs in the room arranged in a semicircle, upon which we sat down by him. He saluted me eagerly, and then he said:

c

You don’t come to see me, Socrates, as often as you ought: If I were still able to go and see you I would not ask you to come to me. But at my age I can hardly get to the city, and therefore you should come oftener to the Piræus. For, let me tell you that the more the pleasures of the body fade away, the greater to me are the pleasure and charm of conversation. Do not, then, deny my request, but make our house your resort and keep company with these young men; we are old friends, and you will be quite at home with us.

d

I replied: There is nothing which for my part I like better, Cephalus, than conversing with aged men; for I regard them as travellers who have gone a journey which I too may have to go, and of whom I ought to inquire whether the way is smooth and easy or rugged and difficult. And this is a question which I should like to ask of you, who have arrived at that time which the poets call the “threshold of old age”:e Is life harder toward the end, or what report do you give of it?

e

I will tell you, Socrates, he said, what my own feeling is. Men of my age flock together; we are birds of a feather, as the old proverb says;f and at our meetings the tale of my acquaintance commonly is: I cannot eat, I cannot drink; the pleasures of youth and love are fled away; there was a good time once, but now that is gone, and life is no longer life. Some complain of the slights which are put upon them by relations, and they will tell you sadly of how many evils their old age is the cause. But to me, Socrates, these com plainers seem to blame that which is not really in fault. For if old age were the cause, I too, being old, and every other old man would have felt as they do. But this is not my own experience, nor that of others whom I have known. How well I remember the aged poet Sophocles,g when in answer to the question, How does love suit with age, Sophocles—are you still the man you were? Peace, he replied; most gladly have I escaped the thing of which you speak; I feel as if I had escaped from a mad and furious master. His words have often occurred to my mind since, and they seem as good to me now as at the time when he uttered them. For certainly old age has a great sense of calm and freedom; when the passions relax their hold, then, as Sophocles says, we are freed from the grasp not of one mad master only, but of many. The truth is, Socrates, that these regrets, and also the complaints about relations, are to be attributed to the same cause, which is not old age, but men’s characters and tempers; for he who is of a calm and happy nature will hardly feel the pressure of age, but to him who is of an opposite disposition youth and age are equally a burden.

329
c
d

I listened in admiration, and wanting to draw him out, that he might go on—Yes, Cephalus, I said; but I rather suspect that people in general are not convinced by you when you speak thus; they think that old age sits lightly upon you, not because of your happy disposition, but because you are rich, and wealth is well known to be a great comforter.

e

You are right, he replied; they are not convinced: and there is something in what they say; not, however, so much as they imagine. I might answer them as Themistoclesh answered the Seriphiani who was abusing him and saying that he was famous, not for his own merits but because he was an Athenian: “If you had been a native of my country or I of yours, neither of us would have been famous.” And to those who are not rich and are impatient of old age, the same reply may be made; for to the good poor man old age cannot be a light burden, nor can a bad rich man ever have peace with himself.

330

May I ask, Cephalus, whether your fortune was for the most part inherited or acquired by you?

Acquired! Socrates; do you want to know how much I acquired? In the art of making money I have been midway between my father and grandfather: for my grandfather, whose name I bear, doubled and trebled the value of his patrimony, that which he inherited being much what I possess now; but my father, Lysanias, reduced the property below what it is at present; and I shall be satisfied if I leave to these my sons not less, but a little more, than I received.

b

That was why I asked you the question, I replied, because I see that you are indifferent about money, which is a characteristic rather of those who have inherited their fortunes than of those who have acquired them; the makers of fortunes have a second love of money as a creation of their own, resembling the affection of authors for their own poems, or of parents for their children, besides that natural love of it for the sake of use and profit which is common to them and all men. And hence they are very bad company, for they can talk about nothing but the praises of wealth.

c

That is true, he said.

Yes, that is very true, but may I ask another question?—What do you consider to be the greatest blessing which you have reaped from your wealth?

d

One, he said, of which I could not expect easily to convince others. For let me tell you, Socrates, that when a man thinks himself to be near death, fears and cares enter into his mind which he never had before; the tales of a world below and the punishment which is exacted there of deeds done here were once a laughing matter to him, but now he is tormented with the thought that they may be true: either from the weakness of age, or because he is now drawing nearer to that other place, he has a clearer view of these things; suspicions and alarms crowd thickly upon him, and he begins to reflect and consider what wrongs he has done to others. And when he finds that the sum of his transgressions is great he will many a time like a child start up in his sleep for fear, and he is filled with dark forebodings. But to him who is conscious of no sin, sweet hope, as Pindarj charmingly says, is the kind nurse of his age:

e
331
“Hope,” he says, “cherishes the soul of him who lives in justice and holiness, and is the nurse of his age and the companion of his journey—hope which is mightiest to sway the restless soul of man.”

How admirable are his words! And the great blessing of riches, I do not say to every man, but to a good man, is, that he has had no occasion to deceive or to defraud others, either intentionally or unintentionally; and when he departs to the world below he is not in any apprehension about offerings due to the gods or debts which he owes to men. Now to this peace of mind the possession of wealth greatly contributes; and therefore I say, that, setting one thing against another, of the many advantages which wealth has to give, to a man of sense this is in my opinion the greatest.

b

Well said, Cephalus, I replied; but as concerning justice, what is it?—to speak the truth and to pay your debts—no more than this? And even to this are there not exceptions? Suppose that a friend when in his right mind has deposited arms with me and he asks for them when he is not in his right mind, ought I to give them back to him? No one would say that I ought or that I should be right in doing so, any more than they would say that I ought always to speak the truth to one who is in his condition.

c

You are quite right, he replied.

But then, I said, speaking the truth and paying your debts is not a correct definition of justice.

d

Quite correct, Socrates, if Simonidesk is to be believed,1 said Polemarchus, interposing.

I fear, said Cephalus, that I must go now, for I have to look after the sacrifices, and I hand over the argument to Polemarchus and the company.

Is not Polemarchus your heir? I said.

To be sure, he answered, and went away laughing to the sacrifices.

Tell me then, O thou heir of the argument, what did Simonides say, and according to you, truly say, about justice?

e

He said that the repayment of a debt is just, and in saying so he appears to me to be right.

I shall be sorry to doubt the word of such a wise and inspired man, but his meaning, though probably clear to you, is the reverse of clear to me. For he certainly does not mean, as we were just now saying, that I ought to return a deposit of arms or of anything else to one who asks for it when he is not in his right senses; and yet a deposit cannot be denied to be a debt.

332

True.

Then when the person who asks me is not in his right mind I am by no means to make the return?

Certainly not.

When Simonides said that the repayment of a debt was justice, he did not mean to include that case?

Certainly not; for he thinks that a friend ought always to do good to a friend, and never evil.

You mean that the return of a deposit of gold which is to the injury of the receiver, if the two parties are friends, is not the repayment of a debt—that is what you would imagine him to say?

b

Yes.

And are enemies also to receive what we owe to them?2

To be sure, he said, they are to receive what we owe them; and an enemy, as I take it, owes to an enemy that which is due or proper to him—that is to say, evil.3

Simonides, then, after the manner of poets, would seem to have spoken darkly of the nature of justice; for he really meant to say that justice is the giving to each man what is proper to him, and this he termed a debt.

c

That must have been his meaning, he said.

By heaven! I replied; and if we asked him what due or proper thing is given by medicine, and to whom, what answer do you think that he would make to us?4

He would surely reply that medicine gives drugs and meat and drink to human bodies.

And what due or proper thing is given by cookery, and to what?

Seasoning to food.

d

And what is that which justice gives, and to whom?

If, Socrates, we are to be guided at all by the analogy of the preceding instances, then justice is the art which gives good to friends and evil to enemies.

That is his meaning, then?

I think so.

And who is best able to do good to his friends and evil to his enemies in time of sickness?

The physician.

Or when they are on a voyage, amid the perils of the sea?

e

The pilot.

And in what sort of actions or with a view to what result is the just man most able to do harm to his enemy and good to his friend?

In going to war against the one and in making alliances with the other.

But when a man is well, my dear Polemarchus, there is no need of a physician?

No.

And he who is not on a voyage has no need of a pilot?

No.

Then in time of peace justice will be of no use?

I am very far from thinking so.

You think that justice may be of use in peace as well as in war?

Yes.

333

Like husbandry for the acquisition of corn?

Yes.

Or like shoemaking for the acquisition of shoes—that is what you mean?

Yes.

And what similar use or power of acquisition has justice in time of peace?

In contracts, Socrates, justice is of use.

And by contracts you mean partnerships?

Exactlv.

But is the just man or the skilful player a more useful and better partner at a game of draughts?

b

The skilful player.

And in the laying of bricks and stones is the just man a more useful or better partner than the builder?

Quite the reverse.

Then in what sort of partnership is the just man a better partner than the harp-player, as in playing the harp the harp-player is certainly a better partner than the just man?

In a money partnership.

Yes, Polemarchus, but surely not in the use of money; for you do not want a just man to be your counsellor in the purchase or sale of a horse; a man who is knowing about horses would be better for that, would he not?

C

Certainly.

And when you want to buy a ship, the shipwright or the pilot would be better?

True.

Then what is that joint use of silver or gold in which the just man is to be preferred?

When you want a deposit to be kept safely.

You mean when money is not wanted, but allowed to lie?

Precisely.

That is to say, justice is useful when money is useless?

d

That is the inference.

And when you want to keep a pruning-hook safe, then justice is useful to the individual and to the State; but when you want to use it, then the art of the vine-dresser?

Clearly.

And when you want to keep a shield or a lyre, and not to use them, you would say that justice is useful; but when you want to use them, then the art of the soldier or of the musician?

Certainly.

And so of all other things—justice is useful when they are useless, and useless when they are useful?

That is the inference.

Then justice is not good for much. But let us consider this further point: Is not he who can best strike a blow in a boxing match or in any kind of fighting best able to ward off a blow?

e

Certainly.

And he who is most skilful in preventing or escaping from a disease is best able to create one?

True.

And he is the best guard of a camp who is best able to steal a march upon the enemy?

334

Certainly.

Then he who is a good keeper of anything is also a good thief?

That, I suppose, is to be inferred.

Then if the just man is good at keeping money, he is good at stealing it.

That is implied in the argument.

Then after all, the just man has turned out to be a thief. And this is a lesson which I suspect you must have learnt out of Homer,5 for he, speaking of Autolycus,l the maternal grandfather of Odysseus, who is a favorite of his, affirms that And so, you and Homer and Simonides are agreed that justice is an art of theft; to be practised, however, “for the good of friends and for the harm of enemies”—that was what you were saying?

b
“He was excellent above all men in theft and perjury.”

No, certainly not that, though I do not now know what I did say; but I still stand by the latter words.

Well, there is another question: By friends and enemies do we mean those who are so really, or only in seeming?

c

Surely, he said, a man may be expected to love those whom he thinks good, and to hate those whom he thinks evil.

Yes, but do not persons often err about good and evil: many who are not good seem to be so, and conversely?

That is true.

Then to them the good will be enemies and the evil will be their friends?

True.

And in that case they will be right in doing good to the evil and evil to the good?

d

Clearly.

But the good are just and would not do an injustice?

True.

Then according to your argument it is just to injure those who do no wrong?

Nay, Socrates; the doctrine is immoral.

Then I suppose that we ought to do good to the just and harm to the unjust?

I like that better.

But see the consequence: Many a man who is ignorant of human nature has friends who are bad friends, and in that case he ought to do harm to them; and he has good enemies whom he ought to benefit; but, if so, we shall be saying the very opposite of that which we affirmed to be the meaning of Simonides.

e

Very true, he said; and I think that we had better correct an error into which we seem to have fallen in the use of the words “friend” and “enemy.”

What was the error, Polemarchus? I asked.

We assumed that he is a friend who seems to be or who is thought good.

And how is the error to be corrected?

We should rather say that he is a friend who is, as well as seems, good; and that he who seems only and is not good, only seems to be and is not a friend; and of an enemy the same may be said.

335

You would argue that the good are our friends and the bad our enemies?

Yes.

And instead of saying simply as we did at first, that it is just to do good to our friends and harm to our enemies, we should further say: It is just to do good to our friends when they are good, and harm to our enemies when they are evil?

Yes, that appears to me to be the truth.

b
But ought the just to injure anyone at all?

Undoubtedly he ought to injure those who are both wicked and his enemies.

When horses are injured, are they improved or deteriorated?

The latter.

Deteriorated, that is to say, in the good qualities of horses, not of dogs?6

Yes, of horses.

And dogs are deteriorated in the good qualities of dogs, and not of horses?

Of course.

And will not men who are injured be deteriorated in that which is the proper virtue of man?

c

Certainly.

And that human virtue is justice?

To be sure.

Then men who are injured are of necessity made unjust?

That is the result.

But can the musician by his art make men unmusical?

Certainly not.

Or the horseman by his art make them bad horsemen?

Impossible.

And can the just by justice make men unjust, or speaking generally, can the good by virtue make them bad?

d

Assuredly not.

Any more than heat can produce cold?

It cannot.

Or drought moisture?

Clearly not.

Nor can the good harm anyone?

Impossible.

And the just is the good?

Certainly.

Then to injure a friend or anyone else is not the act of a just man, but of the opposite, who is the unjust?

I think that what you say is quite true, Socrates.

Then if a man says that justice consists in the repayment of debts, and that good is the debt which a just man owes to his friends, and evil the debt which he owes to his enemies—to say this is not wise; for it is not true, if, as has been clearly shown, the injuring of another can be in no case just.

e

I agree with you, said Polemarchus.

Then you and I are prepared to take up arms against anyone who attributes such a saying to Simonides or Bias or Pittacus,m or any other wise man or seer?

I am quite ready to do battle at your side, he said.

Shall I tell you whose I believe the saying to be?

Whose?

336

I believe that Periander or Perdiccas or Xerxes or Ismenias the Theban,7 or some other rich and mighty man, who had a great opinion of his own power, was the first to say that justice is “doing good to your friends and harm to your enemies.”

Most true, he said.

Yes, I said; but if this definition of justice also breaks down, what other can be offered?

Several times in the course of the discussion Thrasymachus had made an attempt to get the argument into his own hands, and had been put down by the rest of the company, who wanted to hear the end. But when Polemarchus and I had done speaking and there was a pause, he could no longer hold his peace; and, gathering himself up, he came at us like a wild beast, seeking to devour us. We were quite panic-stricken at the sight of him.

b

He roared out to the whole company: What folly, Socrates, has taken possession of you all? And why do you knock under to one another? I say that if you want really to know what justice is, you should not only ask but answer, and you should not seek honor to yourself from the refutation of an opponent, but have your own answer; for there is many a one who can ask and cannot answer. And now I will not have you say that justice is duty or advantage or profit or gain or interest, for this sort of nonsense will not do for me; I must have clearness and accuracy.

c
d

I was panic-stricken at his words, and could not look at him without trembling. Indeed I believe that if I had not fixed my eye upon him, I should have been struck dumb: but when I saw his fury rising, I looked at him first, and was therefore able to reply to him.

Thrasymachus, I said, with a quiver, don’t be hard upon us. Polemarchus and I may have been guilty of a little mistake in the argument, but I can assure you that the error was not intentional. If we were seeking for a piece of gold, you would not imagine that we were “knocking under to one another,” and so losing our chance of finding it. And why, when we are seeking for justice, a thing more precious than many pieces of gold, do you say that we are weakly yielding to one another and not doing our utmost to get at the truth? Nay, my good friend, we are most willing and anxious to do so, but the fact is that we cannot. And if so, you people who know all things should pity us and not be angry with us.

e
337

How characteristic of Socrates! he replied, with a bitter laugh; that’s your ironical style! Did I not foresee—have I not already told you, that whatever he was asked he would refuse to answer, and try irony or any other shuffle, in order that he might avoid answering?

You are a clever man, Thrasymachus, I replied, and well know that if you ask a person what numbers make up twelve, taking care to prohibit him whom you ask from answering twice six, or three times four, or six times two, or four times three, “for this sort of nonsense will not do for me”—then obviously, if that is your way of putting the question, no one can answer you. But suppose that he were to retort: “Thrasymachus, what do you mean? If one of these numbers which you interdict be the true answer to the question, am I falsely to say some other number which is not the right one?—is that your meaning?”—How would you answer him?

b
c

Just as if the two cases were at all alike! he said.

Why should they not be? I replied; and even if they are not, but only appear to be so to the person who is asked, ought he not to say what he thinks, whether you and I forbid him or not?

I presume then that you are going to make one of the interdicted answers?

I dare say that I may, notwithstanding the danger, if upon reflection I approve of any of them.

But what if I give you an answer about justice other and better, he said, than any of these? What do you deserve to have done to you?

d

Done to me!—as becomes the ignorant, I must learn from the wise—that is what I deserve to have done to me.

What, and no payment! A pleasant notion!

I will pay when I have the money, I replied.

But you have, Socrates, said Glaucon: and you, Thrasymachus, need be under no anxiety about money, for we will all make a contribution for Socrates.

Yes, he replied, and then Socrates will do as he always does—refuse to answer himself, but take and pull to pieces the answer of someone else.

e

Why, my good friend, I said, how can anyone answer who knows, and says that he knows, just nothing; and who, even if he has some faint notions of his own, is told by a man of authority not to utter them? The natural thing is, that the speaker should be someone like yourself who professes to know and can tell what he knows. Will you then kindly answer, for the edification of the company and of myself?

338

Glaucon and the rest of the company joined in my request, and Thrasymachus, as anyone might see, was in reality eager to speak; for he thought that he had an excellent answer, and would distinguish himself. But at first he affected to insist on my answering; at length he consented to begin. Behold, he said, the wisdom of Socrates; he refuses to teach himself, and goes about learning of others, to whom he never even says, Thank you.

b

That I learn of others, I replied, is quite true; but that I am ungrateful I wholly deny. Money I have none, and therefore I pay in praise, which is all I have; and how ready I am to praise anyone who appears to me to speak well you will very soon find out when you answer; for I expect that you will answer well.

Listen, then, he said; I proclaim that justice is nothing else than the interest of the stronger.8 And now why do you not praise me? But of course you won’t.

c

Let me first understand you, I replied. Justice, as you say, is the interest of the stronger. What, Thrasymachus, is the meaning of this? You cannot mean to say that because Polydamas, the pancra tiast, is stronger than we are, and finds the eating of beef conducive to his bodily strength, that to eat beef is therefore equally for our good who are weaker than he is, and right and just for us?

That’s abominable of you, Socrates; you take the words in the sense which is most damaging to the argument.

d

Not at all, my good sir, I said; I am trying to understand them; and I wish that you would be a little clearer.

Well, he said, have you never heard that forms of government differ—there are tyrannies, and there are democracies, and there are aristocracies?9

Yes, I know.

And the government is the ruling power in each State?

Certainly.

And the different forms of government make laws democratical, aristocratical, tyrannical, with a view to their several interests; and these laws, which are made by them for their own interests, are the justice which they deliver to their subjects, and him who transgresses them they punish as a breaker of the law, and unjust. And that is what I mean when I say that in all States there is the same principle of justice, which is the interest of the government; and as the government must be supposed to have power, the only reasonable conclusion is that everywhere there is one principle of justice, which is the interest of the stronger.

e
339

Now I understand you, I said; and whether you are right or not I will try to discover. But let me remark that in defining justice you have yourself used the word “interest,” which you forbade me to use. It is true, however, that in your definition the words “of the stronger” are added.

A small addition, you must allow, he said.

b

Great or small, never mind about that: we must first inquire whether what you are saying is the truth. Now we are both agreed that justice is interest of some sort, but you go on to say “of the stronger”; about this addition I am not so sure, and must therefore consider further.

Proceed.

I will; and first tell me, Do you admit that it is just for subjects to obey their rulers?

I do.

But are the rulers of States absolutely infallible, or are they sometimes liable to err?

c

To be sure, he replied, they are liable to err.

Then in making their laws they may sometimes make them rightly, and sometimes not?

True.

When they make them rightly, they make them agreeably to their interest; when they are mistaken, contrary to their interest; you admit that?

Yes.

And the laws which they make must be obeyed by their subjects—and that is what you call justice?

Doubtless.

Then justice, according to your argument, is not only obedience to the interest of the stronger, but the reverse?

d

What is that you are saying? he asked.

I am only repeating what you are saying, I believe. But let us consider: Have we not admitted that the rulers may be mistaken about their own interest in what they command, and also that to obey them is justice? Has not that been admitted?

Yes.

Then you must also have acknowledged justice not to be for the interest of the stronger, when the rulers unintentionally command things to be done which are to their own injury. For if, as you say, justice is the obedience which the subject renders to their commands, in that case, O wisest of men, is there any escape from the conclusion that the weaker are commanded to do, not what is for the interest, but what is for the injury of the stronger?

e

Nothing can be clearer, Socrates, said Polemarchus.

340

Yes, said Cleitophon, interposing, if you are allowed to be his witness.

But there is no need of any witness, said Polemarchus, for Thrasymachus himself acknowledges that rulers may sometime command what is not for their own interest, and that for subjects to obey them is justice.

Yes, Polemarchus—Thrasymachus said that for subjects to do what was commanded by their rulers is just.

Yes, Cleitophon, but he also said that justice is the interest of the stronger, and, while admitting both these propositions, he further acknowledged that the stronger may command the weaker who are his subjects to do what is not for his own interest; whence follows that justice is the injury quite as much as the interest of the stronger.

b

But, said Cleitophon, he meant by the interest of the stronger what the stronger thought to be his interest—this was what the weaker had to do; and this was affirmed by him to be justice.

Those were not his words, rejoined Polemarchus.

Never mind, I replied, if he now says that they are, let us accept his statement. Tell me, Thrasymachus, I said, did you mean by justice what the stronger thought to be his interest, whether really so or not?

c

Certainly not, he said. Do you suppose that I call him who is mistaken the stronger at the time when he is mistaken?

Yes, I said, my impression was that you did so, when you admitted that the ruler was not infallible, but might be sometimes mistaken.

You argue like an informer,n Socrates. Do you mean, for example, that he who is mistaken about the sick is a physician in that he is mistaken? or that he who errs in arithmetic or grammar is an arithmetician or grammarian at the time when he is making the mistake, in respect of the mistake? True, we say that the physician or arithmetician or grammarian has made a mistake, but this is only a way of speaking; for the fact is that neither the grammarian nor any other person of skill ever makes a mistake in so far as he is what his name implies; they none of them err unless their skill fails them, and then they cease to be skilled artists. No artist or sage or ruler errs at the time when he is what his name implies; though he is commonly said to err, and I adopted the common mode of speaking. But to be perfectly accurate, since you are such a lover of accuracy, we should say that the ruler, in so far as he is a ruler, is unerring, and, being unerring, always commands that which is for his own interest; and the subject is required to execute his commands; and therefore, as I said at first and now repeat, justice is the interest of the stronger.

d
e
341

Indeed, Thrasymachus, and do I really appear to you to argue like an informer?

Certainly, he replied.

And do you suppose that I ask these questions with any design of injuring you in the argument?

Nay, he replied, “suppose” is not the word—I know it; but you will be found out, and by sheer force of argument you will never prevail.

b

I shall not make the attempt, my dear man; but to avoid any misunderstanding occurring between us in future, let me ask, in what sense do you speak of a ruler or stronger whose interest, as you were saying, he being the superior, it is just that the inferior should execute—is he a ruler in the popular or in the strict sense of the term?

In the strictest of all senses, he said. And now cheat and play the informer if you can; I ask no quarter at your hands. But you never will be able, never.

And do you imagine, I said, that I am such a madman as to try and cheat Thrasymachus? I might as well shave a lion.

c

Why, he said, you made the attempt a minute ago, though you proved to be a thing of naught with regard to that, too.

Enough, I said, of these civilities. It will be better that I should ask you a question: Is the physician, taken in that strict sense of which you are speaking, a healer of the sick or a maker of money? And remember that I am now speaking of the true physician.

A healer of the sick, he replied.

And the pilot—that is to say, the true pilot—is he a captain of sailors or a mere sailor?

A captain of sailors.

The circumstance that he sails in the ship is not to be taken into account; neither is he to be called a sailor; the name pilot by which he is distinguished has nothing to do with sailing, but is significant of his skill and of his authority over the sailors.

d

Very true, he said.

Now, I said, every art has an interest?10

Certainly.

For which the art has to consider and provide?

Yes, that is the aim of art.

And the interest of any art is the perfection of it—this and nothing else?

What do you mean?

e

I mean what I may illustrate negatively by the example of the body. Suppose you were to ask me whether the body is self-sufficing or has wants, I should reply: Certainly the body has wants; for the body may be ill and require to be cured, and has therefore interests to which the art of medicine ministers; and this is the origin and intention of medicine, as you will acknowledge. Am I not right?

Quite right, he replied.

But is the art of medicine or any other art faulty or deficient in any quality in the same way that the eye may be deficient in sight or the ear fail of hearing, and therefore requires another art to provide for the interests of seeing and hearing—has art in itself, I say, any similar liability to fault or defect, and does every art require another supplementary art to provide for its interests, and that another and another without end? Or have the arts to look only after their own interests? Or have they no need either of themselves or of another?—having no faults or defects, they have no need to correct them, either by the exercise of their own art or of any other; they have only to consider the interest of their subject-matter. For every art remains pure and faultless while remaining true—that is to say, while perfect and unimpaired. Take the words in your precise sense, and tell me whether I am not right.

342
b

Yes, clearly.

Then medicine does not consider the interest of medicine, but the interest of the body?

C

True, he said.

Nor does the art of horsemanship consider the interests of the art of horsemanship, but the interests of the horse; neither do any other arts care for themselves, for they have no needs; they care only for that which is the subject of their art?

True, he said.

But surely, Thrasymachus, the arts are the superiors and rulers of their own subjects?

To this he assented with a good deal of reluctance.

Then, I said, no science or art considers or enjoins the interest of the stronger or superior, but only the interest of the subject and weaker?

d

He made an attempt to contest this proposition also, but finally acquiesced.

Then, I continued, no physician, in so far as he is a physician, considers his own good in what he prescribes, but the good of his patient; for the true physician is also a ruler having the human body as a subject, and is not a mere money-maker; that has been admitted?

Yes.

And the pilot likewise, in the strict sense of the term, is a ruler of sailors, and not a mere sailor?

That has been admitted.

e

And such a pilot and ruler will provide and prescribe for the interest of the sailor who is under him, and not for his own or the ruler’s interest?

He gave a reluctant “Yes.”

Then, I said, Thrasymachus, there is no one in any rule who, in so far as he is a ruler, considers or enjoins what is for his own interest, but always what is for the interest of his subject or suitable to his art; to that he looks, and that alone he considers in everything which he says and does.

When we had got to this point in the argument, and everyone saw that the definition of justice had been completely upset, Thrasymachus, instead of replying to me, said, Tell me, Socrates, have you got a nurse?

343

Why do you ask such a question, I said, when you ought rather to be answering?

Because she leaves you to snivel, and never wipes your nose: she has not even taught you to know the shepherd from the sheep.

What makes you say that? I replied.

Because you fancy that the shepherd or cowherd fattens or tends the sheep or oxen with a view to their own good and not to the good of himself or his master; and you further imagine that the rulers of States, if they are true rulers, never think of their subjects as sheep, and that they are not studying their own advantage day and night.11 Oh, no; and so entirely astray are you in your ideas about the just and unjust as not even to know that justice and the just are in reality another’s good; that is to say, the interest of the ruler and stronger, and the loss of the subject and servant; and injustice the opposite; for the unjust is lord over the truly simple and just: he is the stronger, and his subjects do what is for his interest, and minister to his happiness, which is very far from being their own. Consider further, most foolish Socrates, that the just is always a loser in comparison with the unjust. First of all, in private contracts: wherever the unjust is the partner of the just you will find that, when the partnership is dissolved, the unjust man has always more and the just less.12 Secondly, in their dealings with the State: when there is an income-tax, the just man will pay more and the unjust less on the same amount of income; and when there is anything to be received the one gains nothing and the other much. Observe also what happens when they take an office; there is the just man neglecting his affairs and perhaps suffering other losses, and getting nothing out of the public, because he is just; moreover he is hated by his friends and acquaintance for refusing to serve them in unlawful ways. But all this is reversed in the case of the unjust man. I am speaking, as before, of injustice on a large scale in which the advantage of the unjust is most apparent; and my meaning will be most clearly seen if we turn to that highest form of injustice in which the criminal is the happiest of men,13 and the sufferers or those who refuse to do injustice are the most miserable—that is to say tyranny, which by fraud and force takes away the property of others, not little by little but wholesale; comprehending in one, things sacred as well as profane, private and public; for which acts of wrong, if he were detected perpetrating any one of them singly, he would be punished and incur great disgrace—they who do such wrong in particular cases are called robbers of temples, and man-stealers and burglars and swindlers and thieves. But when a man besides taking away the money of the citizens has made slaves of them, then, instead of these names of reproach, he is termed happy and blessed, not only by the citizens but by all who hear of his having achieved the consummation of injustice. For mankind censure injustice, fearing that they may be the victims of it and not because they shrink from committing it. And thus, as I have shown, Socrates, injustice, when on a sufficient scale, has more strength and freedom and mastery than justice; and, as I said at first, justice is the interest of the stronger, whereas injustice is a man’s own profit and interest.

b
c
d
e
344
b
c

Thrasymachus, when he had thus spoken, having, like a bath-man, o deluged our ears with his words, had a mind to go away. But the company would not let him; they insisted that he should remain and defend his position; and I myself added my own humble request that he would not leave us. Thrasymachus, I said to him, excellent man, how suggestive are your remarks! And are you going to run away before you have fairly taught or learned whether they are true or not? Is the attempt to determine the way of man’s life so small a matter in your eyes—to determine how life may be passed by each one of us to the greatest advantage?14

d
e

And do 1 ditter from you, he said, as to the importance of the inquiry?

You appear to differ, I replied, or else to have no care or thought about us, Thrasymachus—whether we live better or worse from not knowing what you say you know, is to you a matter of indifference. Prithee, friend, do not keep your knowledge to yourself; we are a large party; and any benefit which you confer upon us will be amply rewarded. For my own part I openly declare that I am not convinced, and that I do not believe injustice to be more gainful than justice, even if uncontrolled and allowed to have free play.15 For, granting that there may be an unjust man who is able to commit injustice either by fraud or force, still this does not convince me of the superior advantage of injustice, and there may be others who are in the same predicament with myself. Perhaps we may be wrong; if so, you in your wisdom should convince us that we are mistaken in preferring justice to injustice.

345
b

And how am I to convince you, he said, if you are not already convinced by what I have just said; what more can I do for you? Would you have me put the proof bodily into your souls?

Heaven forbid! I said; I would only ask you to be consistent; or, if you change, change openly and let there be no deception. For I must remark, Thrasymachus, if you will recall what was previously said, that although you began by defining the true physician in an exact sense, you did not observe a like exactness when speaking of the shepherd; you thought that the shepherd as a shepherd tends the sheep not with a view to their own good, but like a mere diner or banqueter with a view to the pleasures of the table; or, again, as a trader for sale in the market, and not as a shepherd. Yet surely the art of the shepherd is concerned only with the good of his subjects; he has only to provide the best for them, since the perfection of the art is already insured whenever all the requirements of it are satisfied. And that was what I was saying just now about the ruler. I conceived that the art of the ruler, considered as a ruler, whether in a State or in private life, could only regard the good of his flock or subjects; whereas you seem to think that the rulers in States, that is to say, the true rulers, like being in authority.

c
d
e

Think! Nay, I am sure of it.

Then why in the case of lesser offices do men never take them willingly without payment, unless under the idea that they govern for the advantage not of themselves but of others? Let me ask you a question: Are not the several arts different, by reason of their each having a separate function? And, my dear illustrious friend, do say what you think, that we may make a little progress.

346

Yes, that is the difference, he replied.

And each art gives us a particular good and not merely a general one—medicine, for example, gives us health; navigation, safety at sea, and so on?

Yes, he said.

And the art of payment has the special function of giving pay: but we do not confuse this with other arts, any more than the art of the pilot is to be confused with the art of medicine, because the health of the pilot may be improved by a sea voyage. You would not be inclined to say, would you? that navigation is the art of medicine, at least if we are to adopt your exact use of language?

b

Certainly not.

Or because a man is in good health when he receives pay you would not say that the art of payment is medicine?

I should not.

Nor would you say that medicine is the art of receiving pay because a man takes fees when he is engaged in healing?

Certainly not.

C

And we have admitted, I said, that the good of each art is specially confined to the art?

Yes.

Then, if there be any good which all artists have in common, that is to be attributed to something of which they all have the common use?

True, he replied.

And when the artist is benefited by receiving pay the advantage is gained by an additional use of the art of pay, which is not the art professed by him?

He gave a reluctant assent to this.

Then the pay is not derived by the several artists from their respective arts. But the truth is, that while the art of medicine gives health, and the art of the builder builds a house, another art attends them which is the art of pay. The various arts may be doing their own business and benefiting that over which they preside, but would the artist receive any benefit from his art unless he were paid as well?

d

I suppose not.

But does he therefore confer no benefit when he works for nothing?

e

Certainly, he confers a benefit.

Then now, Thrasymachus, there is no longer any doubt that neither arts nor governments provide for their own interests; but, as we were before saying, they rule and provide for the interests of their subjects who are the weaker and not the stronger—to their good they attend and not to the good of the superior. And this is the reason, my dear Thrasymachus, why, as I was just now saying, no one is willing to govern; because no one likes to take in hand the reformation of evils which are not his concern, without remuneration.16 For, in the execution of his work, and in giving his orders to another, the true artist does not regard his own interest, but always that of his subjects; and therefore in order that rulers may be willing to rule, they must be paid in one of three modes of payment, money, or honor, or a penalty for refusing.

347

What do you mean, Socrates? said Glaucon. The first two modes of payment are intelligible enough, but what the penalty is I do not understand, or how a penalty can be a payment.

You mean that you do not understand the nature of this payment which to the best men is the great inducement to rule? Of course you know that ambition and avarice are held to be, as in deed they are, a disgrace?

b

Very true.

And for this reason, I said, money and honor have no attraction for them; good men do not wish to be openly demanding payment for governing and so to get the name of hirelings, nor by secretly helping themselves out of the public revenues to get the name of thieves. And not being ambitious they do not care about honor. Wherefore necessity must be laid upon them, and they must be induced to serve from the fear of punishment. And this, as I imagine, is the reason why the forwardness to take office, instead of waiting to be compelled, has been deemed dishonorable. Now the worst part of the punishment is that he who refuses to rule is liable to be ruled by one who is worse than himself. And the fear of this, as I conceive, induces the good to take office, not because they would, but because they cannot help—not under the idea that they are going to have any benefit or enjoyment themselves, but as a necessity, and because they are not able to commit the task of ruling to anyone who is better than themselves, or indeed as good. For there is reason to think that if a city were composed entirely of good men, then to avoid office would be as much an object of contention as to obtain office is at present; then we should have plain proof that the true ruler is not meant by nature to regard his own interest, but that of his subjects; and everyone who knew this would choose rather to receive a benefit from another than to have the trouble of conferring one. So far am I from agreeing with Thrasymachus that justice is the interest of the stronger. This latter question need not be further discussed at present; but when Thrasymachus says that the life of the unjust is more advantageous than that of the just, his new statement appears to me to be of a far more serious character. Which of us has spoken truly? And which sort of life, Glaucon, do you prefer?

c
d
e

I for my part deem the life of the just to be the more advantageous, he answered.

Did you hear all the advantages of the unjust which Thrasymachus was rehearsing?

348

Yes, I heard him, he replied, but he has not convinced me. Then shall we try to find some way of convincing him, if we can, that he is saying what is not true?

Most certainly, he replied.

If, I said, he makes a set speech and we make another recounting all the advantages of being just, and he answers and we rejoin, there must be a numbering and measuring of the goods which are claimed on either side, and in the end we shall want judges to decide; but if we proceed in our inquiry as we lately did, by making admissions to one another, we shall unite the offices of judge and advocate in our own persons.

b

Very good, he said.

And which method do I understand you to prefer? I said.

That which you propose.

Well, then, Thrasymachus, I said, suppose you begin at the beginning and answer me. You say that perfect injustice is more gainful than perfect justice?

Yes, that is what I say, and I have given you my reasons.

c

And what is your view about them? Would you call one of them virtue and the other vice?

Certainly.

I suppose that you would call justice virtue and injustice vice?

What a charming notion! So likely too, seeing that I affirm injustice to be profitable and justice not.

What else then would you say?

The opposite, he replied.

And would you call justice vice?

No, I would rather sav sublime simplicity.

Then would you call injustice malignity?17

d

No; I would rather say discretion.

And do the unjust appear to you to be wise and good?

Yes, he said; at any rate those of them who are able to be perfectly unjust, and who have the power of subduing States and nations; but perhaps you imagine me to be talking of cutpurses. Even this profession, if undetected, has advantages, though they are not to be compared with those of which I was just now speaking.

I do not think that I misapprehend your meaning, Thrasymachus, I replied; but still I cannot hear without amazement that you class injustice with wisdom and virtue, and justice with the opposite.

e

Certainly I do so class them.

Now, I said, you are on more substantial and almost unanswerable ground; for if the injustice which you were maintaining to be profitable had been admitted by you as by others to be vice and deformity, an answer might have been given to you on received principles; but now I perceive that you will call injustice honorable and strong, and to the unjust you will attribute all the qualities which were attributed by us before to the just, seeing that you do not hesitate to rank injustice with wisdom and virtue.

349

You have guessed most infallibly, he replied.

Then I certainly ought not to shrink from going through with the argument so long as I have reason to think that you, Thrasymachus, are speaking your real mind; for I do believe that you are now in earnest and are not amusing yourself at our expense.

I may be in earnest or not, but what is that to you?—to refute the argument is your business.

Very true, I said; that is what I have to do: But will you be so good as answer yet one more question? Does the just man try to gain any advantage over the just?

b

Far otherwise; if he did he would not be the simple amusing creature which he is.

And would he try to go beyond just action?

He would not.

And how would he regard the attempt to gain an advantage over the unjust; would that be considered by him as just or unjust?

He would think it just, and would try to gain the advantage; but he would not be able.

Whether he would or would not be able, I said, is not to the point. My question is only whether the just man, while refusing to have more than another just man, would wish and claim to have more than the unjust?

c

Yes, he would.

And what of the unjust—does he claim to have more than the just man and to do more than is just?

Of course, he said, for he claims to have more than all men.

And the unjust man will strive and struggle to obtain more than the just man or action, in order that he may have more than all?

True.

We may put the matter thus, I said—the just does not desire more than his like, but more than his unlike, whereas the unjust desires more than both his like and his unlike?

d

Nothing, he said, can be better than that statement.

And the unjust is goodp and wise, and the just is neither?

Good again, he said.

And is not the unjust like the wise and good, and the just unlike them?

Of course, he said, he who is of a certain nature, is like those who are of a certain nature; he who is not, not.

Each of them, I said, is such as his like is?

Certainly, he replied.

Very good, Thrasymachus, I said; and now to take the case of the arts: you would admit that one man is a musician and another not a musician?

e

Yes.

And which is wise and which is foolish?

Clearly the musician is wise, and he who is not a musician is foolish.

And he is good in as far as he is wise, and bad in as far as he is foolish?

Yes.

And you would say the same sort of thing of the physician?

Yes.

And do you think, my excellent friend, that a musician when he adjusts the lyreq would desire or claim to exceed or go beyond a musician in the tightening and loosening the strings?

I do not think that he would.

But he would claim to exceed the non-musician?

Of course.

And what would you say of the physician? In prescribing meats and drinks would he wish to go beyond another physician or beyond the practice of medicine?

350

He would not.

But he would wish to go beyond the non-physician?

Yes.

And about knowledge and ignorance in general; see whether you think that any man who has knowledge ever would wish to have the choice of saying or doing more than another man who has knowledge. Would he not rather say or do the same as his like in the same case?

That, I suppose, can hardly be denied.

And what of the ignorant? would he not desire to have more than either the knowing or the ignorant?

b

I dare say.

And the knowing is wise?

Yes.

And the wise is good?

True.

Then the wise and good will not desire to gain more than his like, but more than his unlike and opposite?

I suppose so.

Whereas the bad and ignorant will desire to gain more than both?

Yes.

But did we not say, Thrasymachus, that the unjust goes beyond both his like and unlike? Were not these your words?

They were.

And you also said that the just will not go beyond his like, but his unlike?

c

Yes.

Then the just is like the wise and good, and the unjust like the evil and ignorant?

That is the inference.

And each of them is such as his like is?

That was admitted.

Then the just has turned out to be wise and good, and the unjust evil and ignorant.

Thrasymachus made all these admissions, not fluently, as I repeat them, but with extreme reluctance; it was a hot summer’s day, and the perspiration poured from him in torrents; and then I saw what I had never seen before, Thrasymachus blushing. As we were now agreed that justice was virtue and wisdom, and injustice vice and ignorance, I proceeded to another point:

d

Well, I said, Thrasymachus, that matter is now settled; but were we not also saying that injustice had strength—do you remember?

Yes, I remember, he said, but do not suppose that I approve of what you are saying or have no answer; if, however, I were to answer, you would be quite certain to accuse me of haranguing; therefore either permit me to have my say out, or if you would rather ask, do so, and I will answer “Very good,” as they say to story-telling old women, and will nod “Yes” and “No.”

e

Certainly not, I said, if contrary to your real opinion.

Yes, he said, I will, to please you, since you will not let me speak. What else would you have?

Nothing in the world, I said; and if you are so disposed I will ask and you shall answer.

Proceed.

Then I will repeat the question which I asked before, in order that our examination of the relative nature of justice and injustice may be carried on regularly. A statement was made that injustice is stronger and more powerful than justice, but now justice, having been identified with wisdom and virtue, is easily shown to be stronger than injustice, if injustice is ignorance; this can no longer be questioned by anyone. But I want to view the matter, Thrasymachus, in a different way: You would not deny that a State may be unjust and may be unjustly attempting to enslave other States, or may have already enslaved them, and may be holding many of them in subjection?

351
b

True, he replied; and I will add that the best and most perfectly unjust State will be most likely to do so.

I know, I said, that such was your position; but what I would further consider is, whether this power which is possessed by the superior State can exist or be exercised without justice or only with justice.

If you are right in your view, and justice is wisdom, then only with justice; but if I am right, then without justice.

c

I am delighted, Thrasymachus, to see you not only nodding assent and dissent, but making answers which are quite excellent.

That is out of civility to you, he replied.

You are very kind, I said; and would you have the goodness also to inform me, whether you think that a State, or an army, or a band of robbers and thieves, or any other gang of evildoers could act at all if they injured one another?

No, indeed, he said, they could not.

d

But if they abstained from injuring one another, then they might act together better?

Yes.

And this is because injustice creates divisions and hatreds and fighting, and justice imparts harmony and friendship; is not that true, Thrasymachus?

I agree, he said, because I do not wish to quarrel with you.

How good of you, I said; but I should like to know also whether injustice, having this tendency to arouse hatred, wherever existing, among slaves or among freemen, will not make them hate one another and set them at variance and render them incapable of common action?

e

Certainly.

And even if injustice be found in two only, will they not quarrel and fight, and become enemies to one another and to the just?

They will.

And suppose injustice abiding in a single person, would your wisdom say that she loses or that she retains her natural power?

Let us assume that she retains her power.

Yet is not the power which injustice exercises of such a nature that wherever she takes up her abode, whether in a city, in an army, in a family, or in any other body, that body is, to begin with, rendered incapable of united action by reason of sedition and distraction? and does it not become its own enemy and at variance with all that opposes it, and with the just? Is not this the case?

352

Yes, certainly.

And is not injustice equally fatal when existing in a single person—in the first place rendering him incapable of action because he is not at unity with himself, and in the second place making him an enemy to himself and the just?18 Is not that true, Thrasymachus?

Yes.

And, O my friend, I said, surely the gods are just?

Granted that they are.

But, if so, the unjust will be the enemy of the gods, and the just will be their friends?

b

Feast away in triumph, and take your fill of the argument; I will not oppose you, lest I should displease the company.

Well, then, proceed with your answers, and let me have the remainder of my repast. For we have already shown that the just are clearly wiser and better and abler than the unjust, and that the unjust are incapable of common action; nay, more, that to speak as we did of men who are evil acting at any time vigorously together, is not strictly true, for, if they had been perfectly evil, they would have laid hands upon one another; but it is evident that there must have been some remnant of justice in them, which enabled them to combine; if there had not been they would have injured one another as well as their victims; they were but half-villains in their enterprises; for had they been whole villains, and utterly unjust, they would have been utterly incapable of action. That, as I believe, is the truth of the matter, and not what you said at first. But whether the just have a better and happier life than the unjust is a further question which we also proposed to consider. I think that they have, and for the reasons which I have given; but still I should like to examine further, for no light matter is at stake, nothing less than the rule of human life.

c
d

Proceed.

I will proceed by asking a question: Would you not say that a horse has some end?19

I should.

e

And the end or use of a horse or of anything would be that which could not be accomplished, or not so well accomplished, by any other thing?

I do not understand, he said.

Let me explain: Can you see, except with the eye?

Certainly not.

Or hear, except with the ear?

No.

These, then, may be truly said to be the ends of these organs?

They may.

But you can cut off a vine-branch with a dagger or with a chisel, and in many other ways?

353

Of course.

And yet not so well as with a pruning-hook made for the purpose?

True.

May we not say that this is the end of a pruning-hook?

We may.

Then now I think you will have no difficulty in understanding my meaning when I asked the question whether the end of anything would be that which could not be accomplished, or not so well accomplished, by any other thing?

I understand your meaning, he said, and assent.

b

And that to which an end is appointed has also an excellence? Need I ask again whether the eye has an end?

It has.

And has not the eye an excellence?20

Yes.

And the ear has an end and an excellence also?

True.

And the same is true of all other things; they have each of them an end and a special excellence?

That is so.

Well, and can the eyes fulfil their end if they are wanting in their own proper excellence and have a defect instead?

c

How can they, he said, if they are blind and cannot see?

You mean to say, if they have lost their proper excellence, which is sight; but I have not arrived at that point yet. I would rather ask the question more generally, and only inquire whether the things which fulfil their ends fulfil them by their own proper excellence, and fail of fulfilling them by their own defect?

Certainly, he replied.

I might say the same of the ears; when deprived of their own proper excellence they cannot fulfil their end?

True.

And the same observation will apply to all other things?

d

I agree.

Well; and has not the soul an end which nothing else can fulfil? 21 For example, to superintend and command and deliberate and the like. Are not these functions proper to the soul, and can they rightly be assigned to any other?

To no other.

And is not life to be reckoned among the ends of the soul?

Assuredly, he said.

And has not the soul an excellence also?

Yes.

And can she or can she not fulfil her own ends when deprived of that excellence?

e

She cannot.

Then an evil soul must necessarily be an evil ruler and superintendent, and the good soul a good ruler?

Yes, necessarily.

And we have admitted that justice is the excellence of the soul, and injustice the defect of the soul?

That has been admitted.

Then the just soul and the just man will live well, and the unjust man will live ill?

That is what your argument proves.

And he who lives well is blessed and happy, and he who lives ill the reverse of happy?

Certainly.

Then the just is happy, and the unjust miserable?

354

So be it.

But happiness, and not misery, is profitable?

Of course.

Then, my blessed Thrasymachus, injustice can never be more profitable than justice.

Let this, Socrates, he said, be your entertainment at the Bendidea. r

For which I am indebted to you, I said, now that you have grown gentle toward me and have left off scolding. Nevertheless, I have not been well entertained; but that was my own fault and not yours.22 As an epicure snatches a taste of every dish which is successively brought to table, he not having allowed himself time to enjoy the one before, so have I gone from one subject to another without having discovered what I sought at first, the nature of justice. I left that inquiry and turned away to consider whether justice is virtue and wisdom, or evil and folly; and when there arose a further question about the comparative advantages of justice and injustice, I could not refrain from passing on to that. And the result of the whole discussion has been that I know nothing at all. For I know not what justice is, and therefore I am not likely to know whether it is or is not a virtue, nor can I say whether the just man is happy or unhappy.

b
c

BOOK 2

WITH THESE WORDS I was thinking that I had made an end of the discussion; but the end, in truth, proved to be only a beginning. For Glaucon, who is always the most courageous of men, was dissatisfied at Thrasymachus’s retirement. So he said to me: Socrates, do you wish really to persuade us, or only to seem to have persuaded us, that to be just is always better than to be unjust?1

357
b

I should wish really to persuade you, I replied, if I could.

Then you certainly have not succeeded. Let me ask you now: Are there not some good things which we welcome for their own sakes, and independently of their consequences, as, for example, harmless pleasures and enjoyments, which delight us at the time, although nothing follows from them?

I agree in thinking that there is such a class, I replied.

Is there not also a second class of goods, such as knowledge, sight, health, which are desirable not only in themselves, but also for their results?

c

Certainly, I said.

And would you not recognize a third class, such as gymnastic, and the care of the sick, and the physician’s art; also the various ways of money-making—these do us good but we regard them as disagreeable; and no one would choose them for their own sakes, but only for the sake of some reward or result which flows from them?

There is, I said, this third class also. But why do you ask?

Because I want to know: In which of the three classes would you place justice?

In the highest class, I replied—among those goods which he who would be happy desires both for their own sake and for the sake of their results.

358

Then the many are of another mind; they think that justice is to be reckoned in the troublesome class, among goods which are to be pursued for the sake of rewards and of reputation, but in themselves are disagreeable and rather to be avoided.

I know, I said, that this is their manner of thinking, and that this was the thesis which Thrasymachus was maintaining just now, when he censured justice and praised injustice. But I am too slow-witted to be convinced by him.

I wish, he said, that you would hear me as well as him, and then I shall see whether you and I agree. For Thrasymachus seems to me, like a snake, to have been charmed by your voice sooner than he ought to have been; but to my mind the nature of justice and injustice has not yet been made clear. Setting aside their rewards and results, I want to know what they are in themselves, and how they inwardly work in the soul. If you please, then, I will revive the argument of Thrasymachus. And first I will speak of the nature and origin of justice according to the common view of them. Secondly, I will show that all men who practise justice do so against their will, of necessity, but not as a good. And thirdly, I will argue that there is reason in this view, for the life of the unjust is after all better far than the life of the just—if what they say is true, Socrates, since I myself am not of their opinion. But still I acknowledge that I am perplexed when I hear the voices of Thrasymachus and myriads of others dinning in my ears; and, on the other hand, I have never yet heard the superiority of justice to injustice maintained by anyone in a satisfactory way. I want to hear justice praised in respect of itself; then I shall be satisfied, and you are the person from whom I think that I am most likely to hear this; and therefore I will praise the unjust life to the utmost of my power, and my manner of speaking will indicate the manner in which I desire to hear you too praising justice and censuring injustice. Will you say whether you approve of my proposal?

b
c
d

Indeed I do; nor can I imagine any theme about which a man of sense would oftener wish to converse.

I am delighted, he replied, to hear you say so, and shall begin by speaking, as I proposed, of the nature and origin of justice.

e

They say that to do injustice is, by nature, good; to suffer injustice, evil; but that the evil is greater than the good.2 And so when men have both done and suffered injustice and have had experience of both, not being able to avoid the one and obtain the other, they think that they had better agree among themselves to have neither; hence there arise laws and mutual covenants; and that which is ordained by law is termed by them lawful and just. This they affirm to be the origin and nature of justice; it is a mean or compromise, between the best of all, which is to do injustice and not be punished, and the worst of all, which is to suffer injustice without the power of retaliation; and justice, being at a middle point between the two, is tolerated not as a good, but as the lesser evil, and honored by reason of the inability of men to do injustice. For no man who is worthy to be called a man would ever submit to such an agreement if he were able to resist; he would be mad if he did. Such is the received account, Socrates, of the nature and origin of justice.

b

Now that those who practise justice do so involuntarily and because they have not the power to be unjust will best appear if we imagine something of this kind: having given both to the just and the unjust power to do what they will, let us watch and see whither desire will lead them; then we shall discover in the very act the just and unjust man to be proceeding along the same road, following their interest, which all natures deem to be their good, and are only diverted into the path of justice by the force of law. The liberty which we are supposing may be most completely given to them in the form of such a power as is said to have been possessed by Gyges, the ancestor of Crœsus the Lydian. s According to the tradition, Gyges was a shepherd in the service of the King of Lydia; there was a great storm, and an earthquake made an opening in the earth at the place where he was feeding his flock. Amazed at the sight, he descended into the opening, where, among other marvels, he beheld a hollow brazen horse, having doors, at which he, stooping and looking in, saw a dead body of stature, as appeared to him, more than human and having nothing on but a gold ring; this he took from the finger of the dead and reascended. Now the shepherds met together, according to custom, that they might send their monthly report about the flocks to the King; into their assembly he came having the ring on his finger, and as he was sitting among them he chanced to turn the flange of the ring inside his hand, when instantly he became invisible to the rest of the company and they began to speak of him as if he were no longer present. He was astonished at this, and again touching the ring he turned the flange outward and reappeared; he made several trials of the ring, and always with the same result—when he turned the flange inward he became invisible, when outward he reappeared. Whereupon he contrived to be chosen one of the messengers who were sent to the court; where as soon as he arrived he seduced the Queen, and with her help conspired against the King and killed him and took the kingdom. Suppose now that there were two such magic rings, and the just put on one of them and the unjust the other; no man can be imagined to be of such an iron nature that he would stand fast in justice. No man would keep his hands off what was not his own when he could safely take what he liked out of the market, or go into houses and sleep with anyone at his pleasure, or kill or release from prison whom he would, and in all respects be like a god among men. Then the actions of the just would be as the actions of the unjust; they would both come at last to the same point. And this we may truly affirm to be a great proof that a man is just, not willingly or because he thinks that justice is any good to him individually, but of necessity, for wherever anyone thinks that he can safely be unjust, there he is unjust.3 For all men believe in their hearts that injustice is far more profitable to the individual than justice, and he who argues as I have been supposing, will say that they are right. If you could imagine anyone obtaining this power of becoming invisible, and never doing any wrong or touching what was another‘s, he would be thought by the lookers-on to be a most wretched idiot, although they would praise him to one another’s faces, and keep up appearances with one another from a fear that they too might suffer injustice. Enough of this.

c
d
e
360
b
c
d

Now, if we are to form a real judgment of the life of the just and unjust, we must isolate them; there is no other way; and how is the isolation to be effected? I answer: Let the unjust man be entirely unjust, and the just man entirely just; nothing is to be taken away from either of them, and both are to be perfectly furnished for the work of their respective lives. First, let the unjust be like other distinguished masters of craft; like the skilful pilot or physician, who knows intuitively his own powers and keeps within their limits, and who, if he fails at any point, is able to recover himself. So let the unjust make his unjust attempts in the right way, and lie hidden if he means to be great in his injustice (he who is found out is nobody): for the highest reach of injustice is, to be deemed just when you are not. Therefore I say that in the perfectly unjust man we must assume the most perfect injustice; there is to be no deduction, but we must allow him, while doing the most unjust acts, to have acquired the greatest reputation for justice. If he have taken a false step he must be able to recover himself; he must be one who can speak with effect, if any of his deeds come to light, and who can force his way where force is required by his courage and strength, and command of money and friends. And at his side let us place the just man in his nobleness and simplicity, wishing, as Æschylust says, to be and not to seem good. There must be no seeming, for if he seem to be just he will be honored and rewarded, and then we shall not know whether he is just for the sake of justice or for the sake of honor and rewards; therefore, let him be clothed in justice only, and have no other covering; and he must be imagined in a state of life the opposite of the former. Let him be the best of men, and let him be thought the worst; then he will have been put to the proof; and we shall see whether he will be affected by the fear of infamy and its consequences. And let him continue thus to the hour of death; being just and seeming to be unjust. When both have reached the uttermost extreme, the one of justice and the other of injustice, let judgment be given which of them is the happier of the two.

e
361
b
c
d

Heavens! my dear Glaucon, I said, how energetically you polish them up for the decision, first one and then the other, as if they were two statues.

I do my best, he said. And now that we know what they are like there is no difficulty in tracing out the sort of life which awaits either of them. This I will proceed to describe; but as you may think the description a little too coarse, I ask you to suppose, Socrates, that the words which follow are not mine. Let me put them into the mouths of the eulogists of injustice: They will tell you that the just man who is thought unjust will be scourged, racked, bound—will have his eyes burnt out; and, at last, after suffering every kind of evil, he will be impaled. Then he will understand that he ought to seem only, and not to be, just; the words of Æschylus may be more truly spoken of the unjust than of the just. For the unjust is pursuing a reality; he does not live with a view to appearances—he wants to be really unjust and not to seem only—

e
362
“His mind has a soil deep and fertile,
Out of which spring his prudent counsels.”u

In the first place, he is thought just, and therefore bears rule in the city; he can marry whom he will, and give in marriage to whom he will; also he can trade and deal where he likes, and always to his own advantage, because he has no misgivings about injustice; and at every contest, whether in public or private, he gets the better of his antagonists, and gains at their expense, and is rich, and out of his gains he can benefit his friends, and harm his enemies;4 moreover, he can offer sacrifices, and dedicate gifts to the gods abundantly and magnificently, and can honor the gods or any man whom he wants to honor in a far better style than the just, and therefore he is likely to be dearer than they are to the gods. And thus, Socrates, gods and men are said to unite in making the life of the unjust better than the life of the just.

b
c

I was going to say something in answer to Glaucon, when Adeimantus, his brother, interposed: Socrates, he said, you do not suppose that there is nothing more to be urged?

d

Why, what else is there? I answered.

The strongest point of all has not been even mentioned, he replied.

Well, then, according to the proverb, “Let brother help brother”v—if he fails in any part, do you assist him; although I must confess that Glaucon has already said quite enough to lay me in the dust, and take from me the power of helping justice.

Nonsense, he replied. But let me add something more: There is another side to Glaucon’s argument about the praise and censure of justice and injustice, which is equally required in order to bring out what I believe to be his meaning. Parents and tutors are always telling their sons and their wards that they are to be just; but why? not for the sake of justice, but for the sake of character and reputation; in the hope of obtaining for him who is reputed just some of those offices, marriages, and the like which Glaucon has enumerated among the advantages accruing to the unjust from the reputation of justice. More, however, is made of appearances by this class of persons than by the others; for they throw in the good opinion of the gods, and will tell you of a shower of benefits which the heavens, as they say, rain upon the pious; and this accords with the testimony of the noble Hesiodw and Homer, the first of whom says that the gods make the oaks of the just—

e
363
b
“To bear acorns at their summit, and bees in the middle;
And the sheep are bowed down with the weight of their fleeces,”x

and many other blessings of a like kind are provided for them. And Homer has a very similar strain; for he speaks of one whose fame is

“As the fame of some blameless king who, like a god,
Maintains justice; to whom the black earth brings forth
Wheat and barley, whose trees are bowed with fruit,
And his sheep never fail to bear, and the sea gives him fish.“y
c

Still grander are the gifts of heaven which Musæus and his son z vouchsafe to the just; they take them down into the world below, where they have the saints lying on couches at a feast, everlast ingly drunk, crowned with garlands; their idea seems to be that an immortality of drunkenness is the highest meed of virtue. Some extend their rewards yet further; the posterity, as they say, of the faithful and just shall survive to the third and fourth generation. This is the style in which they praise justice. But about the wicked there is another strain; they bury them in a slough in Hadesaa and make them carry water in a sieve; also while they are yet living they bring them to infamy, and inflict upon them the punishments which Glaucon described as the portion of the just who are reputed to be unjust; nothing else does their invention supply. Such is their manner of praising the one and censuring the other.

d
e

Once more, Socrates, I will ask you to consider another way of speaking about justice and injustice, which is not confined to the poets, but is found in prose writers. The universal voice of mankind is always declaring that justice and virtue are honorable, but grievous and toilsome; and that the pleasures of vice and injustice are easy of attainment, and are only censured by law and opinion. They say also that honesty is for the most part less profitable than dishonesty; and they are quite ready to call wicked men happy, and to honor them both in public and private when they are rich or in any other way influential, while they despise and overlook those who may be weak and poor, even though acknowledging them to be better than the others. But most extraordinary of all is their mode of speaking about virtue and the gods: they say that the gods apportion calamity and misery to many good men, and good and happiness to the wicked. And mendicant prophetsab go to rich men’s doors and persuade them that they have a power committed to them by the gods of making an atonement for a man’s own or his ancestor’s sins by sacrifices or charms, with rejoicings and feasts; and they promise to harm an enemy, whether just or unjust, at a small cost; with magic arts and incantations binding heaven, as they say, to execute their will. And the poets are the authorities to whom they appeal, now smoothing the path of vice with the words of Hesiod:

364
b
d
c
“Vice may be had in abundance without trouble; the way is smooth and her dwelling-place is near. But before virtue the gods have set toil”,ac

and a tedious and uphill road: then citing Homer as a witness that the gods may be influenced by men; for he also says:

“The gods, too, may be turned from their purpose; and men pray to them and avert their wrath by sacrifices and soothing entreaties, and by libations and the odor of fat, when they have sinned and transgressed.”ad
e

And they produce a host of books written by Musæus and Orpheus,ae who were children of the Moon and the muses—that is what they say—according to which they perform their ritual, and persuade not only individuals, but whole cities, that expiations and atonements for sin may be made by sacrifices and amusements which fill a vacant hour, and are equally at the service of the living and the dead; the latter sort they call mysteries, and they redeem us from the pains of hell, but if we neglect them no one knows what awaits us.

365

He proceeded: And now when the young hear all this said about virtue and vice, and the way in which gods and men regard them, how are their minds likely to be affected, my dear Socrates—those of them, I mean, who are quick-witted, and, like bees on the wing, light on every flower, and from all that they hear are prone to draw conclusions as to what manner of persons they should be and in what way they should walk if they would make the best of life? Probably the youth will say to himself in the words of Pindar:

b
“Can I by justice or by crooked ways of deceit ascend a loftier tower which may be a fortress to me all my days?”af

For what men say is that, if I am really just and am not also thought just, profit there is none, but the pain and loss on the other hand are unmistakable. But if, though unjust, I acquire the reputation of justice, a heavenly life is promised to me. Since then, as wise men prove, appearance tyrannizes over truthag and is lord of happiness, to appearance I must devote myself. I will describe around me a picture and shadow of virtue to be the vestibule and exterior of my house; behind I will trail the subtle and crafty fox, as Archilochus,ah greatest of sages, recommends. But I hear someone exclaiming that the concealment of wickedness is often difficult; to which I answer, Nothing great is easy. Nevertheless, the argument indicates this, if we would be happy, to be the path along which we should proceed. With a view to concealment we will establish secret brotherhoods and political clubs.5 And there are professors of rhetoric6 who teach the art of persuading courts and assemblies; and so, partly by persuasion and partly by force, I shall make unlawful gains and not be punished. Still I hear a voice saying that the gods cannot be deceived, neither can they be compelled. But what if there are no gods? or, suppose them to have no care of human things—why in either case should we mind about concealment? And even if there are gods, and they do care about us, yet we know of them only from tradition and the genealogies of the poets; and these are the very persons who say that they may be influenced and turned by “sacrifices and soothing entreaties and by offerings.”ai Let us be consistent, then, and believe both or neither. If the poets speak truly, why, then, we had better be unjust, and offer of the fruits of injustice; for if we are just, although we may escape the vengeance of heaven, we shall lose the gains of injustice; but, if we are unjust, we shall keep the gains, and by our sinning and praying, and praying and sinning, the gods will be propitiated, and we shall not be punished. “But there is a world below in which either we or our posterity will suffer for our unjust deeds.” Yes, my friend, will be the reflection, but there are mysteries and atoning deities, and these have great power. That is what mighty cities declare; and the children of the gods, who were their poets and prophets, bear a like testimony.

c
d
e
366
b

On what principle, then, shall we any longer choose justice rather than the worst injustice? when, if we only unite the latter with a deceitful regard to appearances, we shall fare to our mind both with gods and men, in life and after death, as the most numerous and the highest authorities tell us. Knowing all this, Socrates, how can a man who has any superiority of mind or person or rank or wealth, be willing to honor justice; or indeed to refrain from laughing when he hears justice praised? And even if there should be someone who is able to disprove the truth of my words, and who is satisfied that justice is best, still he is not angry with the unjust, but is very ready to forgive them, because he also knows that men are not just of their own free will;7 unless, peradventure, there be someone whom the divinity within him may have inspired with a hatred of injustice, or who has attained knowledge of the truth—but no other man. Only he blames injustice, who, owing to cowardice or age or some weakness, has not the power of being unjust. And this is proved by the fact that when he obtains the power, he immediately becomes unjust as far as he can be.

c
d

The cause of all this, Socrates, was indicated by us at the beginning of the argument, when my brother and I told you how astonished we were to find that of all the professing panegyrists of justice—beginning with the ancient heroes of whom any memorial has been preserved to us, and ending with the men of our own time—no one has ever blamed injustice or praised justice except with a view to the glories, honors, and benefits which flow from them. No one has ever adequately described either in verse or prose the true essential nature of either of them abiding in the soul, and invisible to any human or divine eye; or shown that of all the things of a man’s soul which he has within him, justice is the greatest good, and injustice the greatest evil. Had this been the universal strain, had you sought to persuade us of this from our youth upward, we should not have been on the watch to keep one another from doing wrong, but everyone would have been his own watchman8 because afraid, if he did wrong, of harboring in himself the greatest of evils. I dare say that Thrasymachus and others would seriously hold the language which I have been merely repeating, and words even stronger than these about justice and injustice, grossly, as I conceive, perverting their true nature. But I speak in this vehement manner, as I must frankly confess to you, because I want to hear from you the opposite side; and I would ask you to show not only the superiority which justice has over injustice, but what effect they have on the possessor of them which makes the one to be a good and the other an evil to him. And please, as Glaucon requested of you, to exclude reputations; for unless you take away from each of them his true reputation and add on the false, we shall say that you do not praise justice, but the appearance of it; we shall think that you are only exhorting us to keep injustice dark, and that you really agree with Thrasymachus in thinking that justice is another’s good and the interest of the stronger, and that injustice is a man’s own profit and interest, though injurious to the weaker. Now as you have admitted that justice is one of that highest class of goods which are desired, indeed, for their results, but in a far greater degree for their own sakes—like sight or hearing or knowledge or health, or any other real and natural and not merely conventional good—I would ask you in your praise of justice to regard one point only: I mean the essential good and evil which justice and injustice work in the possessors of them. Let others praise justice and censure injustice, magnifying the rewards and honors of the one and abusing the other; that is a manner of arguing which, coming from them, I am ready to tolerate, but from you who have spent your whole life in the consideration of this question, unless I hear the contrary from your own lips, I expect something better. And therefore, I say, not only prove to us that justice is better than injustice, but show what they either of them do to the possessor of them, which makes the one to be a good and the other an evil, whether seen or unseen by gods and men.

e
367
b
c
d
e

I had always admired the natural ability of Glaucon and Adeimantus,9 but on hearing these words I was quite delighted, and said: Sons of an illustrious father,aj that was not a bad beginning of the elegiac verses which the admirer of Glauconak made in honor of you after you had distinguished yourselves at the battle of Megara:al

368
“Sons of Ariston,” he sang, “divine offspring of an illustrious hero.”am

The epithet is very appropriate, for there is something truly divine in being able to argue as you have done for the superiority of injustice, and remaining unconvinced by your own arguments. And I do believe that you are not convinced—this I infer from your general character, for had I judged only from your speeches I should have mistrusted you. But now, the greater my confidence in you, the greater is my difficulty in knowing what to say. For I am in a strait between two; on the one hand I feel that I am unequal to the task; and my inability is brought home to me by the fact that you were not satisfied with the answer which I made to Thrasymachus, proving, as I thought, the superiority which justice has over injustice. And yet I cannot refuse to help, while breath and speech remain to me; I am afraid that there would be an impiety in being present when justice is evil spoken of and not lifting up a hand in her defence. And therefore I had best give such help as I can.

b
c

Glaucon and the rest entreated me by all means not to let the question drop, but to proceed in the investigation. They wanted to arrive at the truth, first, about the nature of justice and injustice, and secondly, about their relative advantages. I told them, what I really thought, that the inquiry would be of a serious nature, and would require very good eyes. Seeing then, I said, that we are no great wits, I think that we had better adopt a method which I may illustrate thus; suppose that a short-sighted person had been asked by someone to read small letters from a distance; and it occurred to someone else that they might be found in another place which was larger and in which the letters were larger—if they were the same and he could read the larger letters first, and then proceed to the lesser—this would have been thought a rare piece of good-fortune.

d

Very true, said Adeimantus; but how does the illustration apply to our inquiry?

e

I will tell you, I replied; justice, which is the subject of our inquiry, is, as you know, sometimes spoken of as the virtue of an individual, and sometimes as the virtue of a State.an

True, he replied.

And is not a State larger than an individual?

It is.

Then in the larger the quantity of justice is likely to be larger and more easily discernible. I propose therefore that we inquire into the nature of justice and injustice, first as they appear in the State, and secondly in the individual, proceeding from the greater to the lesser and comparing them.10

369

That, he said, is an excellent proposal.

And if we imagine the State in process of creation, we shall see the justice and injustice of the State in process of creation also.

I dare say.

When the State is completed there may be a hope that the object of our search will be more easily discovered.

Yes, far more easily.

b

But ought we to attempt to construct one? I said; for to do so, as I am inclined to think, will be a very serious task. Reflect therefore.

I have reflected, said Adeimantus, and am anxious that you should proceed.

A State, I said, arises, as I conceive, out of the needs of mankind; no one is self-sufficing, but all of us have many wants. Can any other origin of a State be imagined?11

There can be no other.

Then, as we have many wants, and many persons are needed to supply them, one takes a helper for one purpose and another for another; and when these partners and helpers are gathered together in one habitation the body of inhabitants is termed a State.

c

True, he said.

And they exchange with one another, and one gives, and another receives, under the idea that the exchange will be for their good.

Very true.

Then, I said, let us begin and create in idea a State; and yet the true creator is necessity, who is the mother of our invention.ao

Of course, he replied.

Now the first and greatest of necessities is food, which is the condition of life and existence.

d

Certainly.

The second is a dwelling, and the third clothing and the like.

True.

And now let us see how our city will be able to supply this great demand: We may suppose that one man is a husbandman, another a builder, someone else a weaver—shall we add to them a shoemaker, or perhaps some other purveyor to our bodily wants?

Quite right.

The barest notion of a State must include four or five men.

Clearly.

e

And how will they proceed? Will each bring the result of his labors into a common stock?—the individual husbandman, for example, producing for four, and laboring four times as long and as much as he need in the provision of food with which he supplies others as well as himself; or will he have nothing to do with others and not be at the trouble of producing for them, but provide for himself alone a fourth of the food in a fourth of the time, and in the remaining three-fourths of his time be employed in making a house or a coat or a pair of shoes, having no partnership with others, but supplying himself all his own wants?

370

Adeimantus thought that he should aim at producing food only and not at producing everything.

Probably, I replied, that would be the better way; and when I hear you say this, I am myself reminded that we are not all alike; there are diversities of natures among us which are adapted to different occupations.12

b

Very true.

And will you have a work better done when the workman has many occupations, or when he has only one?

When he has only one.

Further, there can be no doubt that a work is spoilt when not done at the right time?

No doubt.

For business is not disposed to wait until the doer of the business is at leisure; but the doer must follow up what he is doing, and make the business his first object.

c

He must.

And if so, we must infer that all things are produced more plentifully and easily and of a better quality when one man does one thing which is natural to him and does it at the right time, and leaves other things.13

Undoubtedly.

Then more than four citizens will be required; for the husbandman will not make his own plough or mattock, or other implements of agriculture, if they are to be good for anything. Neither will the builder make his tools—and he, too, needs many; and in like manner the weaver and shoemaker.

d

True.

Then carpenters and smiths and many other artisans will be sharers in our little State, which is already beginning to grow?

True.

Yet even if we add cowherds, shepherds, and other herdsmen, in order that our husbandmen may have oxen to plough with, and builders as well as husbandmen may have draught cattle, and cur riers and weavers fleeces and hides—still our State will not be very large.

e

That is true; yet neither will it be a very small State which contains all these.

Then, again, there is the situation of the city—to find a place where nothing need be imported is well-nigh impossible.

Impossible.

Then there must be another class of citizens who will bring the required supply from another city?

There must.

But if the trader goes empty-handed, having nothing which they require who would supply his need, he will come back empty-handed.

371

That is certain.

And therefore what they produce at home must be not only enough for themselves, but such both in quantity and quality as to accommodate those from whom their wants are supplied.

Very true.

Then more husbandmen and more artisans will be required?

They will.

Not to mention the importers and exporters, who are called merchants?

Yes.

Then we shall want merchants?

We shall.

And if merchandise is to be carried over the sea, skilful sailors will also be needed, and in considerable numbers?

b

Yes, in considerable numbers.

Then, again, within the city, how will they exchange their productions? To secure such an exchange was, as you will remember, one of our principal objects when we formed them into a society and constituted a State.

Clearly they will buy and sell.

Then they will need a market-place, and a money-token for purposes of exchange.

Certainly.

Suppose now that a husbandman or an artisan brings some production to market, and he comes at a time when there is no one to exchange with him—is he to leave his calling and sit idle in the market-place?

c

Not at all; he will find people there who, seeing the want, undertake the office of salesmen. In well-ordered States they are commonly those who are the weakest in bodily strength, and therefore of little use for any other purpose;14 their duty is to be in the market, and to give money in exchange for goods to those who desire to sell, and to take money from those who desire to buy.

d

This want, then, creates a class of retail-traders in our State. Is not “retailer” the term which is applied to those who sit in the market-place engaged in buying and selling, while those who wander from one city to another are called merchants?

Yes, he said.

And there is another class of servants, who are intellectually hardly on the level of companionship; still they have plenty of bodily strength for labor, which accordingly they sell, and are called, if I do not mistake, hirelings, “hire” being the name which is given to the price of their labor.

e

True.

Then hirelings will help to make up our population?

Yes.

And now, Adeimantus, is our State matured and perfected?

I think so.

Where, then, is justice, and where is injustice, and in what part of the State did they spring up?

Probably in the dealings of these citizens with one another.15 I cannot imagine that they are more likely to be found anywhere else.

372

I dare say that you are right in your suggestion, I said; we had better think the matter out, and not shrink from the inquiry.

Let us then consider, first of all, what will be their way of life, now that we have thus established them. Will they not produce corn and wine and clothes and shoes, and build houses for themselves? And when they are housed, they will work, in summer, commonly, stripped and barefoot, but in winter substantially clothed and shod. They will feed on barley-meal and flour of wheat, baking and kneading them, making noble cakes and loaves; these they will serve up on a mat of reeds or on clean leaves, themselves reclining the while upon beds strewn with yew or myrtle. And they and their children will feast, drinking of the wine which they have made, wearing garlands on their heads, and hymning the praises of the gods, in happy converse with one another. And they will take care that their families do not exceed their means; having an eye to poverty or war.

b
c

But, said Glaucon, interposing, you have not given them a relish to their meal.

True, I replied, I had forgotten; of course they must have a relish—salt and olives and cheese—and they will boil roots and herbs such as country people prepare; for a dessert we shall give them figs and peas and beans; and they will roast myrtle-berries and acorns at the fire, drinking in moderation. And with such a diet they may be expected to live in peace and health to a good old age, and bequeath a similar life to their children after them.

Yes, Socrates, he said, and if you were providing for a city of pigs, how else would you feed the beasts?

d

But what would you have, Glaucon? I replied.

Why, he said, you should give them the ordinary conveniences of life. People who are to be comfortable are accustomed to lie on sofas, and dine off tables, and they should have sauces and sweets in the modem style.

e

Yes, I said, now I understand: the question which you would have me consider is, not only how a State, but how a luxurious State is created; and possibly there is no harm in this, for in such a State we shall be more likely to see how justice and injustice originate. In my opinion the true and healthy constitution of the State is the one which I have described. But if you wish also to see a State at fever-heat, I have no objection.16 For I suspect that many will not be satisfied with the simpler way of life. They will be for adding sofas and tables and other furniture; also dainties and perfumes and incense and courtesansap and cakes, all these not of one sort only, but in every variety. We must go beyond the necessaries of which I was at first speaking, such as houses and clothes and shoes; the arts of the painter and the embroiderer will have to be set in motion, and gold and ivory and all sorts of materials must be procured.

373

True, he said.

b

Then we must enlarge our borders; for the original healthy State is no longer sufficient. Now will the city have to fill and swell with a multitude of callings which are not required by any natural want; such as the whole tribe of hunters and actors, of whom one large class have to do with forms and colors; another will be the votaries of music—poets and their attendant train of rhapsodists, players, dancers, contractors; also makers of diverse kinds of articles, including women’s dresses. And we shall want more servants. Will not tutors be also in request, and nurses wet and dry, hairdressers, and barbers, as well as confectioners and cooks; and swineherds,aq too, who were not needed and therefore had no place in the former edition of our State, but are needed now? They must not be forgotten: and there will be animals of many other kinds, if people eat them.

c

Certainly.

And living in this way we shall have much greater need of physicians than before?

d

Much greater.

And the country which was enough to support the original inhabitants will be too small now, and not enough?

Quite true.

Then a slice of our neighbors’ land will be wanted by us for pasture and tillage, and they will want a slice of ours, if, like ourselves, they exceed the limit of necessity, and give themselves up to the unlimited accumulation of wealth?

That, Socrates, will be inevitable.

e

And so we shall go to war, Glaucon. Shall we not?

Most certainly, he replied.

Then, without determining as yet whether war does good or harm, thus much we may affirm, that now we have discovered war to be derived from causes which are also the causes of almost all the evils in States, private as well as public.

Undoubtedly.

And our State must once more enlarge; and this time the enlargement will be nothing short of a whole army, which will have to go out and fight with the invaders for all that we have, as well as for the things and persons whom we were describing above.

374

Why? he said; are they not capable of defending themselves?

No, I said; not if we were right in the principle which was acknowledged by all of us when we were framing the State. The principle, as you will remember, was that one man cannot practise many arts with success.

Very true, he said.

But is not war an art?

b

Certainly.

And an art requiring as much attention as shoemaking?

Quite true.

And the shoemaker was not allowed by us to be a husbandman, or a weaver, or a builder—in order that we might have our shoes well made; but to him and to every other worker was assigned one work for which he was by nature fitted, and at that he was to continue working all his life long and at no other; he was not to let opportunities slip, and then he would become a good workman. Now nothing can be more important than that the work of a soldier should be well done. But is war an art so easily acquired that a man may be a warrior who is also a husbandman, or shoemaker, or other artisan;17 although no one in the world would be a good dice or draught player who merely took up the game as a recreation, and had not from his earliest years devoted himself to this and nothing else? No tools will make a man a skilled workman or master of defence, nor be of any use to him who has not learned how to handle them, and has never bestowed any attention upon them. How, then, will he who takes up a shield or other implement of war become a good fighter all in a day, whether with heavy-armed or any other kind of troops?

c
d

Yes, he said, the tools which would teach men their own use would be beyond price.

And the higher the duties of the guardian, I said, the more time and skill and art and application will be needed by him?

e

No doubt, he replied.

Will he not also require natural aptitude for his calling?

Certainly.

Then it will be our duty to select, if we can, natures which are fitted for the task of guarding the city?

It will.

And the selection will be no easy matter, I said; but we must be brave and do our best.

We must.

375

Is not the noble youth very like a well-bred dog in respect of guarding and watching?

What do you mean?

I mean that both of them ought to be quick to see, and swift to overtake the enemy when they see him; and strong too if, when they have caught him, they have to fight with him.

All these qualities, he replied, will certainly be required by them.

Well, and your guardian must be brave if he is to fight well?

Certainly.

And is he likely to be brave who has no spirit, whether horse or dog or any other animal? Have you never observed how invincible and unconquerable is spirit and how the presence of it makes the soul of any creature to be absolutely fearless and indomitable?

b

I have.

Then now we have a clear notion of the bodily qualities which are required in the guardian.

True.

And also of the mental ones; his soul is to be full of spirit?

Yes.

But are not these spirited natures apt to be savage with one another, and with everybody else?

A difficulty by no means easy to overcome, he replied.

Whereas, I said, they ought to be dangerous to their enemies, and gentle to their friends; if not, they will destroy themselves without waiting for their enemies to destroy them.

c

True, he said.

What is to be done, then? I said; how shall we find a gentle nature which has also a great spirit, for the one is the contradiction of the other? 18

True.

He will not be a good guardian who is wanting in either of these two qualities; and yet the combination of them appears to be impossible; and hence we must infer that to be a good guardian is impossible.

d

I am afraid that what you say is true, he replied.

Here feeling perplexed I began to think over what had preceded. My friend, I said, no wonder that we are in a perplexity; for we have lost sight of the image which we had before us.

What do you mean? he said.

I mean to say that there do exist natures gifted with those opposite qualities.

And where do you find them?

Many animals, I replied, furnish examples of them; our friend the dog is a very good one: you know that well-bred dogs are per tectly gentle to their familiars and acquaintances, and the reverse to strangers.

e

Yes, I know.

Then there is nothing impossible or out of the order of nature in our finding a guardian who has a similar combination of qualities?

Certainly not.

Would not he who is fitted to be a guardian, besides the spirited nature, need to have the qualities of a philosopher?

I do not apprehend your meaning.

376

The trait of which I am speaking, I replied, may be also seen in the dog, and is remarkable in the animal.

What trait?

Why, a dog, whenever he sees a stranger, is angry; when an acquaintance, he welcomes him, although the one has never done him any harm, nor the other any good. Did this never strike you as curious?

The matter never struck me before; but I quite recognize the truth of your remark.

And surely this instinct of the dog is very charming; your dog is a true philosopher.

b

Why?

Why, because he distinguishes the face of a friend and of an enemy only by the criterion of knowing and not knowing. And must not an animal be a lover of learning who determines what he likes and dislikes by the test of knowledge and ignorance?

Most assuredly.

And is not the love of learning the love of wisdom, which is philosophy?

They are the same, he replied.

And may we not say confidently of man also, that he who is likely to be gentle to his friends and acquaintances, must by nature be a lover of wisdom and knowledge?

c

That we may safely affirm.

Then he who is to be a really good and noble guardian of the State will require to unite in himself philosophy and spirit and swiftness and strength?

Undoubtedly.

Then we have found the desired natures; and now that we have found them, how are they to be reared and educated?19 Is not this an inquiry which may be expected to throw light on the greater inquiry which is our final end—How do justice and injustice grow up in States? for we do not want either to omit what is to the point or to draw out the argument to an inconvenient length.

d

Adeimantus thought that the inquiry would be of great service to us.

Then, I said, my dear friend, the task must not be given up, even if somewhat long.

Certainly not.

Come then, and let us pass a leisure hour in story-telling, and our story shall be the education of our heroes.

By all means.

e

And what shall be their education? Can we find a better than the traditional sort?—and this has two divisions, gymnastics for the body, and music for the soul.20

True.

Shall we begin education with music, and go on to gymnastics afterward?

By all means.

And when you speak of music, do you include literature or not?

I do.

And literature may be either true or false?

Yes.

And the young should be trained in both kinds, and we begin with the false?

377

I do not understand your meaning, he said.

You know, I said, that we begin by telling children stories which, though not wholly destitute of truth, are in the main fictitious; and these stories are told them when they are not of an age to learn gymnastics.

Very true.

That was my meaning when I said that we must teach music before gymnastics.

Quite right, he said.

You know also that the beginning is the most important part of any work, especially in the case of a young and tender thing; for that is the time at which the character is being formed and the desired impression is more readily taken.

b

Quite true.

And shall we just carelessly allow children to hear any casual tales which may be devised by casual persons, and to receive into their minds ideas for the most part the very opposite of those which we should wish them to have when they are grown up?

We cannot.

Then the first thing will be to establish a censorship of the writers of fiction, and let the censors receive any tale of fiction which is good, and reject the bad; and we will desire mothers and nurses to tell their children the authorized ones only. Let them fashion the mind with such tales, even more fondly than they mould the body with their hands; but most of those which are now in use must be discarded.

c

Of what tales are you speaking? he said.

You may find a model of the lesser in the greater,21 I said; for they are necessarily of the same type, and there is the same spirit in both of them.

d

Very likely, he replied; but I do not as yet know what you would term the greater.

Those, I said, which are narrated by Homer and Hesiod, and the rest of the poets, who have ever been the great storytellers of mankind.

But which stories do you mean, he said; and what fault do you find with them?

A fault which is most serious, I said; the fault of telling a lie, and, what is more, a bad lie.

But when is this fault committed?

Whenever an erroneous representation is made of the nature of gods and heroes—as when a painter paints a portrait not having the shadow of a likeness to the original.

e

Yes, he said, that sort of thing is certainly very blamable; but what are the stories which you mean?

First of all, I said, there was that greatest of all lies in high places, which the poet told about Uranus, and which was a bad lie too—I mean what Hesiod says that Uranus did, and how Cronus retaliated on him.ar The doings of Cronus, and the sufferings which in turn his son inflicted upon him, even if they were true, ought certainly not to be lightly told to young and thoughtless persons; if possible, they had better be buried in silence. But if there is an absolute necessity for their mention, a chosen few might hear them in a mystery, and they should sacrifice not a common [Eleusinian] pig,as but some huge and unprocurable victim; and then the number of the hearers will be very few indeed.

378

Why, yes, said he, those stories are extremely objectionable. Yes, Adeimantus, they are stories not to be repeated in our State; the young man should not be told that in committing the worst of crimes he is far from doing anything outrageous;22 and that even if he chastises his father when he does wrong, in whatever manner, he will only be following the example of the first and greatest among the gods.

b

I entirely agree with you, he said; in my opinion those stories are quite unfit to be repeated.

Neither, if we mean our future guardians to regard the habit of quarrelling among themselves as of all things the basest, should any word be said to them of the wars in heaven, and of the plots and fightings of the gods against one another, for they are not true. No, we shall never mention the battles of the giants,at or let them be embroidered on garments; and we shall be silent about the innumerable other quarrels of gods and heroes with their friends and relatives. If they would only believe us we would tell them that quarrelling is unholy, and that never up to this time has there been any quarrel between citizens; this is what old men and old women should begin by telling children; and when they grow up, the poets also should be told to compose them in a similar spirit. But the narrative of Hephæstus binding Here his mother,au or how on another occasion Zeus sent him flying for taking her part when she was being beaten,av and all the battles of the gods in Homer—these tales must not be admitted into our State, whether they are supposed to have an allegorical meaning or not. For a young person cannot judge what is allegorical and what is literal;23 anything that he receives into his mind at that age is likely to become indelible and unalterable; and therefore it is most important that the tales which the voung first hear should be models of virtuous thoughts.

c
d
e

There you are right, he replied; but if anyone asks where are such models to be found and of what tales are you speaking—how shall we answer him?

I said to him, You and I, Adeimantus, at this moment are not poets, but founders of a State: now the founders of a State ought to know the general forms in which poets should cast their tales, and the limits which must be observed by them, but to make the tales is not their business.

379

Very true, he said; but what are these torms of theology which you mean?

Something of this kind, I replied: God is always to be represented as he truly is,24 whatever be the sort of poetry, epic, lyric, or tragic, in which the representation is given.

Right.

And is he not truly good? and must he not be represented as such?

b

Certainly.

And no good thing is hurtful?

No, indeed.

And that which is not hurtful hurts not?

Certainly not.

And that which hurts not does no evil?

No.

And can that which does no evil be a cause of evil?

Impossible.

And the good is advantageous?

Yes.

And therefore the cause of well-being?

Yes.

It follows, therefore, that the good is not the cause of all things, but of the good only?

Assuredly.

c

Then God, if he be good, is not the author of all things, as the many assert, but he is the cause of a few things only, and not of most things that occur to men. For few are the goods of human life, and many are the evils, and the good is to be attributed to God alone; of the evils the causes are to be sought elsewhere, and not in him.

That appears to me to be most true, he said.

Then we must not listen to Homer or to any other poet who is guilty of the folly of saying that two casks

“Lie at the threshold of Zeus, full of lots, one of good, the other of evil lots,”aw

and that he to whom Zeus gives a mixture of the two but that he to whom is given the cup of unmingled ill, And again—

d
e
“Sometimes meets with evil fortune, at other times with good;”
“Him wild hunger drives o‘er the beauteous earth.”
“Zeus, who is the dispenser of good and evil to us.”ax

And if anyone asserts that the violation of oaths and treaties, which was really the work of Pandarus,ay was brought about by Atheneaz and Zeus, or that the strife and contention of the gods were instigated by Themis and Zeus,ba he shall not have our approval; neither will we allow our young men to hear the words of Æschylus,25 that

380
“God plants guilt among men when he desires utterly to destroy a house.”bb

And if a poet writes of the sufferings of Niobebc—the subject of the tragedy in which these iambic verses occur—or of the house of Pelops,26 or of the Trojan War or on any similar theme, either we must not permit him to say that these are the works of God, or if they are of God, he must devise some explanation of them such as we are seeking: he must say that God did what was just and right, and they were the better for being punished; but that those who are punished are miserable, and that God is the author of their misery—the poet is not to be permitted to say; though he may say that the wicked are miserable because they require to be punished, and are benefited by receiving punishment from God; but that God being good is the author of evil to anyone is to be strenuously denied, and not to be said or sung or heard in verse or prose by anyone whether old or young in any well-ordered commonwealth. Such a fiction is suicidal, ruinous, impious.

b
c

I agree with you, he replied, and am ready to give my assent to the law.

Let this then be one of our rules and principles concerning the gods, to which our poets and reciters will be expected to conform—that God is not the author of all things, but of good only.

That will do, he said.

And what do you think of a second principle? Shall I ask you whether God is a magician, and of a nature to appear insidiously now in one shape, and now in another—sometimes himself changing and passing into many forms, sometimes deceiving us with the semblance of such transformations; or is he one and the same immutably fixed in his own proper image?

d

I cannot answer you, he said, without more thought.

Well, I said; but if we suppose a change in anything, that change must be effected either by the thing itself or by some other thing?

e

Most certainly.

And things which are at their best are also least liable to be altered or discomposed; for example, when healthiest and strongest, the human frame is least liable to be affected by meats and drinks, and the plant which is in the fullest vigor also suffers least from winds or the heat of the sun or any similar causes.

381

Of course.

And will not the bravest and wisest soul be least confused or deranged by any external influence?

True.

And the same principle, as I should suppose, applies to all composite things—furniture, houses, garments: when good and well made, they are least altered by time and circumstances.

Very true.

Then everything which is good, whether made by art or nature, or both, is least liable to suffer change from without?

b

True.

But surely God and the things of God are in every way perfect?

Of course they are.

Then he can hardly be compelled by external influence to take many shapes?

He cannot.

But may he not change and transform himself?

Clearly, he said, that must be the case if he is changed at all.

And will he then change himself for the better and fairer, or for the worse and more unsightly?

If he change at all he can only change for the worse, for we cannot suppose him to be deficient either in virtue or beauty.

c

Very true, Adeimantus; but then, would anyone, whether God or man, desire to make himself worse?

Impossible.

Then it is impossible that God should ever be willing to change; being, as is supposed, the fairest and best that is conceivable, every God remains absolutely and forever in his own form.

That necessarily follows, he said, in my judgment.

Then, I said, my dear friend, let none of the poets tell us that and let no one slander Proteusbe and Thetis,bf neither let anyone, either in tragedy or in any other kind of poetry, introduce Here disguised in the likeness of a priestess asking an alms

d
“The gods, taking the disguise of strangers from other lands, walk up and down cities in all sorts of forms;”bd

“For the life-giving daughters of Inachus the river of Argos;”bg

—let us have no more lies of that sort. Neither must we have mothers under the influence of the poets scaring their children with a bad version of these myths—telling how certain gods, as they say, “Go about by night in the likeness of so many strangers and in diverse forms;”bh but let them take heed lest they make cowards of their children, and at the same time speak blasphemy against the gods.

e

Heaven forbid, he said.

But although the gods are themselves unchangeable, still by witchcraft and deception they may make us think that they appear in various forms?

Perhaps, he replied.

Well, but can you imagine that God will be willing to lie, whether in word or deed, or to put forth a phantom of himself?

382

I cannot say, he replied.

Do you not know, I said, that the true lie, if such an expression may be allowed, is hated of gods and men?

What do you mean? he said.

I mean that no one is willingly deceived in that which is the truest and highest part of himself, or about the truest and highest matters; there, above all, he is most afraid of a lie having possession of him.

Still, he said, I do not comprehend you.

The reason is, I replied, that you attribute some profound meaning to my words; but I am only saying that deception, or being deceived or uninformed about the highest realities in the highest part of themselves, which is the soul, and in that part of them to have and to hold the lie, is what mankind least like;—that, I say, is what they utterly detest.

b

There is nothing more hateful to them.

And, as I was just now remarking, this ignorance in the soul of him who is deceived may be called the true lie; for the lie in words is only a kind of imitation and shadowy image of a previous affection of the soul, not pure unadulterated falsehood. Am I not right?

c

Perfectly right.

The true lie is hated not only by the gods, but also by men?

Yes.

Whereas the lie in words is in certain cases useful and not hateful; 27 in dealing with enemies—that would be an instance; or again, when those whom we call our friends in a fit of madness or illusion are going to do some harm, then it is useful and is a sort of medicine or preventive; also in the tales of mythology, of which we were just now speaking—because we do not know the truth about ancient times, we make falsehood as much like truth as we can, and so turn it to account.

d

Very true, he said.

But can any of these reasons apply to God? Can we suppose that he is ignorant of antiquity, and therefore has recourse to invention?

That would be ridiculous, he said.

Then the lying poet has no place in our idea of God?

I should say not.

Or perhaps he may tell a lie because he is afraid of enemies?

That is inconceivable.

e

But he may have friends who are senseless or mad?

But no mad or senseless person can be a friend of God.

Then no motive can be imagined why God should lie?

None whatever.

Then the superhuman, and divine, is absolutely incapable of falsehood?

Yes.

Then is God perfectly simple and true both in word and deed; he changes not; he deceives not, either by sign or word, by dream or waking vision.

Your thoughts, he said, are the reflection of my own.

383

You agree with me then, I said, that this is the second type or form in which we should write and speak about divine things. The gods are not magicians who transform themselves, neither do they deceive mankind in any way.

I grant that.

Then, although we are admirers of Homer, we do not admire the lying dream which Zeus sends to Agamemnon;bi neither will we praise the verses of Æschylus in which Thetis says that Apollo at her nuptials

“was celebrating in song her fair progeny whose days were to be long, and to know no sickness. And when he had spoken of my lot as in all things blessed of heaven, he raised a note of triumph and cheered my soul. And I thought that the word of Phœbus, being divine and full of prophecy, would not fail. And now he himself who uttered the strain, he who was present at the banquet, and who said this—he it is who has slain my son.”bj
b

These are the kind of sentiments about the gods which will arouse our anger; and he who utters them shall be refused a chorus; neither shall we allow teachers to make use of them in the instruction of the young, meaning, as we do, that our guardians, as far as men can be, should be true worshippers of the gods and like them.

c

I entirely agree, he said, in these principles, and promise to make them my laws.

BOOK 3

SUCH, THEN, I SAID, are our principles concerning how the gods are to be represented—some tales are to be told, and others are not to be told to our disciples from their youth upward, if we mean them to honor the gods and their parents, and to value friendship with one another.

386

Yes; and I think that our principles are right, he said.

But if they are to be courageous, must they not learn other lessons beside these, and lessons of such a kind as will take away the fear of death? Can any man be courageous who has the fear of death in him?

b

Certainly not, he said.

And can he be fearless of death, or will he choose death in battle rather than defeat and slavery, who believes the world below to be real and terrible?

Impossible.

Then we must assume a control over the narrators of this class of tales as well as over the others, and beg them not simply to revile, but rather to commend the world below, intimating to them that their descriptions are untrue, and will do harm to our future warriors.

c

That will be our duty, he said.

Then, I said, we shall have to obliterate many obnoxious passages, beginning with the verses

“I would rather be a serf on the land of a poor and portionless man than rule over all the dead who have come to naught.”bk

We must also expunge the verse, which tells us how Pluto feared

And again:

“O heavens! verily in the house of Hades there is soul and ghostly form but no mind at all!”bm
“Lest the mansions grim and squalid which the gods abhor should be seen both of mortals and immortals.”bl
d

Again of Tiresias:

“[To him even after death did Persephone grant mind,] that he alone should be wise; but the other souls are flitting shades.”bn

Again:

“The soul flying from the limbs had gone to Hades, lamenting her fate, leaving manhood and youth.”bo
387

Again:

“And the soul, with shrilling cry, passed like smoke beneath the earth.”bp

And,

“As bats in hollow of mystic cavern, whenever any of them has dropped out of the string and falls from the rock, fly shrilling and cling to one another, so did they with shrilling cry hold together as they moved.”bq

And we must beg Homer and the other poets not to be angry if we strike out these and similar passages, not because they are unpoetical, or unattractive to the popular ear, but because the greater the poetical charm of them, the less are they suitable for the ears of boys and men who are meant to be free, and who should fear slavery more than death.

b

Undoubtedly.

Also we shall have to reject all the terrible and appalling names which describe the world below—Cocytus and Styx,br ghosts under the earth, and sapless shades, and any similar words of which the very mention causes a shudder to pass through the inmost soul of him who hears them. I do not say that these horrible stories may not have a use of some kind; but there is a danger that the nerves of our guardians may be rendered too excitable and effeminate by them.

c

There is a real danger, he said.

Then we must have no more of them.

True.

Another and a nobler strain must be composed and sung by us.

Clearly.

And shall we proceed to get rid of the weepings and wailings of famous men?

d

They will go with the rest.

But shall we be right in getting rid of them? Reflect: our principle is that the good man will not consider death terrible to any other good man who is his comrade.

Yes; that is our principle.

And therefore he will not sorrow for his departed friend as though he had suffered anything terrible?

He will not.

Such a one, as we further maintain, is sufficient for himself and his own happiness, and therefore is least in need of other men.

True, he said.

e

And for this reason the loss of a son or brother, or the deprivation of fortune, is to him of all men least terrible.

Assuredly.

And therefore he will be least likely to lament, and will bear with the greatest equanimity any misfortune of this sort which may befall him.

Yes, he will feel such a misfortune far less than another.

Then we shall be right in getting rid of the lamentations of famous men, and making them over to women (and not even to women who are good for anything), or to men of a baser sort, in order that those who are being educated by us to be the defenders of their country may scorn to do the like.

388

That will be very right.

Then we will once more entreat Homer and the other poets not to depict Achilles,bs who is the son of a goddess, first lying on his side, then on his back, and then on his face; then starting up and sailing in a frenzy along the shores of the barren sea; now taking the sooty ashes in both his handsbt and pouring them over his head, or weeping and wailing in the various modes which Homer has delineated. Nor should he describe Priam, the kinsman of the gods, as praying and beseeching, “Rolling in the dirt, calling each man loudly by his name.”bu

b

Still more earnestly will we beg of him at all events not to introduce the gods lamenting and saying,

“Alas! my misery! Alas! that I bore the bravest to my sorrow.”bv
c

But if he must introduce the gods, at any rate let him not dare so completely to misrepresent the greatest of the gods, as to make him say—

“O heavens! with my eyes verily I behold a dear friend of mine chased round and round the city, and my heart is sorrowful.”bw

Or again:

“Woe is me that I am fated to have Sarpedon, dearest of men to me, subdued at the hands of Patroclus the son of Menœtius.”bx
d

For if, my sweet Adeimantus, our youth seriously listen to such unworthy representations of the gods, instead of laughing at them as they ought, hardly will any of them deem that he himself, being but a man, can be dishonored by similar actions; neither will he rebuke any inclination which may arise in his mind to say and do the like. And instead of having any shame or self-control, he will be always whining and lamenting on slight occasions.

Yes, he said, that is most true.

e

Yes, I replied; but that surely is what ought not to be, as the argument has just proved to us; and by that proof we must abide until it is disproved by a better.

It ought not to be.

Neither ought our guardians to be given to laughter. For a fit of laughter which has been indulged to excess almost always produces a violent reaction.

So I believe.

Then persons of worth, even if only mortal men, must not be represented as overcome by laughter, and still less must such a representation of the gods be allowed.

389

Still less ot the gods, as you say, he replied.

Then we shall not suffer such an expression to be used about the gods as that of Homer when he describes how

“Inextinguishable laughter arose among the blessed gods, when they saw Hephæstus bustling about the mansion.”by

On your views, we must not admit them.

On my views, if you like to father them on me; that we must not admit them is certain.

b

Again, truth should be highly valued; if, as we were saying, a lie is useless to the gods, and useful only as a medicine to men, then the use of such medicines should be restricted to physicians; private individuals have no business with them.

Clearly not, he said.

Then if anyone at all is to have the privilege of lying, the rulers of the State should be the persons; and they, in their dealings either with enemies or with their own citizens, may be allowed to lie for the public good. But nobody else should meddle with anything of the kind; and although the rulers have this privilege, for a private man to lie to them in return is to be deemed a more heinous fault than for the patient or the pupil of a gymnasium not to speak the truth about his own bodily illnesses to the physician or to the trainer, or for a sailor not to tell the captain what is happening about the ship and the rest of the crew, and how things are going with himself or his fellow-sailors.

C

Most true, he said.

If, then, the ruler catches anybody besides himself lying in the State, he will punish him for introducing a practice which is equally subversive and destructive of ship or State.1

d
“Any of the craftsmen, whether he be priest or physician or carpenter,” bz

Most certainly, he said, if our idea of the State is ever carried out.

In the next place our youth must be temperate?

Certainly.

Are not the chief elements of temperance, speaking generally, obedience to commanders and self-control in sensual pleasures?

e

True.

Then we shall approve such language as that of Diomede in Homer, and the verses which follow, and other sentiments of the same kind.

“Friend, sit still and obey my word,”ca
“The Greeks marched breathing prowess,” “... in silent awe of their leaders.”cb

We shall.

What of this line, and of the words which follow? Would you say that these, or any similar impertinences which private individuals are supposed to address to their rulers, whether in verse or prose, are well or ill spoken?

“O heavy with wine, who hast the eyes of a dog and the heart of a stag,”cc
390

They are ill spoken.

They may very possibly afford some amusement, but they do not conduce to temperance. And therefore they are likely to do harm to our young men—you would agree with me there?

Yes.

And then, again, to make the wisest of men say that nothing in his opinion is more glorious than

“When the tables are full of bread and meat, and the cup-bearer carries round wine which he draws from the bowl and pours into the cups;”cd
b

is it fit or conducive to temperance for a young man to hear such words? or the verse

“The saddest of fates is to die and meet destiny from hunger”?ce

What would you say again to the tale of Zeus, who, while other gods and men were asleep and he the only one awake, lay devising plans, but forgot them all in a moment through his lust, and was so completely overcome at the sight of Here that he would not even go into the hut, but wanted to lie with her on the ground, declaring that he had never been in such a state of rapture before, even when they first met one another, or that other tale of how Hephæstus, because of similar goings on, cast a chain around Ares and Aphrodite?cg

c
“Without the knowledge of their parents”cf

Indeed, he said, I am strongly of opinion that they ought not to hear that sort of thing.

But any deeds of endurance which are done or told by famous men, these they ought to see and hear; as, for example, what is said in the verses, Certainly, he said.

d
“He smote his breast, and thus reproached his heart,
Endure, my heart; far worse hast thou endured!”ch

Certainly not.

e

Neither must we sing to them of

“Gifts persuading gods, and persuading reverend kings.”ci

Neither is Phoenix, the tutor of Achilles, to be approved or deemed to have given his pupil good counsel when he told him that he should take the gifts of the Greeks and assist them;cj but that without a gift he should not lay aside his anger. Neither will we believe or acknowledge Achilles himself to have been such a lover of money that he took Agamemnon’s gifts,ck or that when he had received payment he restored the dead body of Hector, but that without payment he was unwilling to do so.cl

391

Undoubtedly, he said, these are not sentiments which can be approved.

Loving Homer as I do, I hardly like to say2 that in attributing these feelings to Achilles, or in believing that they are truly attributed to him, he is guilty of downright impiety. As little can I believe the narrative of his insolence to Apollo, where he says,

“Thou hast wronged me, 0 far-darter, most abominable of deities. Verily I would be even with thee, if I had only the power;”cm

or his insubordination to the river-god,cn on whose divinity he is ready to lay hands; or his offerings to the dead Patroclus of his own hair,co which had been previously dedicated to the other river-god Spercheius, and that he actually performed this vow; or that he dragged Hector round the tomb of Patroclus,cp and slaughtered the captives at the pyre;cq of all this I cannot believe that he was guilty, any more than I can allow our citizens to believe that he, the wise Cheiron‘scr pupil, the son of a goddess and of Peleus who was the gentlest of men and third in descent from Zeus, was so disordered in his wits as to be at one time the slave of two seemingly inconsistent passions, meanness, not untainted by avarice, combined with overweening contempt of gods and men.

c
b

You are quite right, he replied.

And let us equally refuse to believe, or allow to be repeated, the tale of Theseus, son of Poseidon, or of Peirithous, son of Zeus, going forth as they did to perpetrate a horrid rape;cs or of any other hero or son of a god daring to do such impious and dreadful things as they falsely ascribe to them in our day: and let us further compel the poets to declare either that these acts were not done by them, or that they were not the sons of God; both in the same breath they shall not be permitted to affirm. We will not have them trying to persuade our youth that the gods are the authors of evil, and that heroes are no better than men—sentiments which, as we were saying, are neither pious nor true, for we have already proved that evil cannot come from the gods.

d
e

Assuredly not.

And, further, they are likely to have a bad effect on those who hear them; for everybody will begin to excuse his own vices when he is convinced that similar wickednesses are always being perpetrated by and who have

“The kindred of the gods, the relatives of Zeus, whose ancestral altar, the altar of Zeus, is aloft in air on the peak of Ida,”
“the blood of deities yet flowing in their veins.”ct

And therefore let us put an end to such tales, lest they engender laxity of morals among the young.

392

By all means, he replied.

But now that we are determining what classes of subjects are or are not to be spoken of, let us see whether any have been omitted by us. The manner in which gods and demigods and heroes and the world below should be treated has been already laid down.

Very true.

And what shall we say about men? That is clearly the remaining portion of our subject.

Clearly so.

But we are not in a condition to answer this question at present, my friend.

Why not?

Because, if I am not mistaken, we shall have to say that about men poets and story-tellers are guilty of making the gravest misstatements when they tell us that wicked men are often happy, and the good miserable; and that injustice is profitable when undetected, but that justice is a man’s own loss and another’s gain—these things we shall forbid them to utter, and command them to sing and say the opposite.

b

To be sure we shall, he replied.

But if you admit that I am right in this, then I shall maintain that you have implied the principle for which we have been all along contending.

I grant the truth of your inference.

That such things are or are not to be said about men is a question which we cannot determine until we have discovered what justice is, and how naturally advantageous to the possessor, whether he seem to be just or not.3

c

Most true, he said.

Enough of the subjects of poetry: let us now speak of the style; and when this has been considered, both matter and manner will have been completely treated.

I do not understand what you mean, said Adeimantus.

Then I must make you understand; and perhaps I may be more intelligible if I put the matter in this way. You are aware, I suppose, that all mythology and poetry are a narration of events, either past, present, or to come?

d

Certainly, he replied.

And narration may be either simple narration or imitation, or a union of the two?4

That, again, he said, I do not quite understand.

I fear that I must be a ridiculous teacher when I have so much difficulty in making myself apprehended. Like a bad speaker, therefore, I will not take the whole of the subject, but will break a piece off in illustration of my meaning. You know the first lines of the “Iliad,” in which the poet says that Chryses prayed Agamemnon to release his daughter, and that Agamemnon flew into a passion with him; whereupon Chryses, failing of his object, invoked the anger of the god against the Achæans. Now as far as these lines, the poet is speaking in his own person; he never leads us to suppose that he is anyone else. But in what follows he takes the person of Chryses, and then he does all that he can to make us believe that the speaker is not Homer, but the aged priest himself. And in this double form he has cast the entire narrative of the events which occurred at Troy and in Ithaca and throughout the “Odyssey.”

e
393
“And he prayed all the Greeks, but especially the two sons of Atreus, the chiefs of the people,”cu
b

Yes.

And a narrative it remains both in the speeches which the poet recites from time to time and in the intermediate passages?

Quite true.

But when the poet speaks in the person of another, may we not say that he assimilates his style to that of the person who, as he informs you, is going to speak?

c

Certainly.

And this assimilation of himself to another, either by the use of voice or gesture, is the imitation of the person whose character he assumes?

Of course.

Then in this case the narrative of the poet may be said to proceed by way of imitation?

Very true.

Or, if the poet everywhere appears and never conceals himself, then again the imitation is dropped, and his poetry becomes simple narration. However, in order that I may make my meaning quite clear, and that you may no more say, “I don’t understand,” I will show how the change might be effected. If Homer had said, “The priest came, having his daughter’s ransom in his hands, supplicating the Achæans, and above all the kings;” and then if, instead of speaking in the person of Chryses, he had continued in his own person, the words would have been, not imitation, but simple narration. The passage would have run as follows (I am no poet, and therefore I drop the metre): “The priest came and prayed the gods on behalf of the Greeks that they might capture Troy and return safely home, but begged that they would give him back his daughter, and take the ransom which he brought, and respect the god. Thus he spoke, and the other Greeks revered the priest and assented. But Agamemnon was wroth, and bade him depart and not come again, lest the staff and chaplets of the god should be of no avail to him—the daughter of Chryses should not be released, he said—she should grow old with him in Argos. And then he told him to go away and not to provoke him, if he intended to get home unscathed. And the old man went away in fear and silence, and, when he had left the camp, he called upon Apollo by his many names, reminding him of everything which he had done pleasing to him, whether in building his temples, or in offering sacrifice, and praying that his good deeds might be returned to him, and that the Achæanscv might expiate his tears by the arrows of the god”—and so on. In this way the whole becomes simple narrative.

d
e
394
b

I understand, he said.

Or you may suppose the opposite case—that the intermediate passages are omitted, and the dialogue only left.

That also, he said, I understand; you mean, for example, as in tragedy.

You have conceived my meaning perfectly; and if I mistake not, what you failed to apprehend before is now made clear to you, that poetry and mythology are, in some cases, wholly imitative—instances of this are supplied by tragedy and comedy; there is likewise the opposite style, in which the poet is the only speaker—of this the dithyrambcw affords the best example; and the combination of both is found in epic and in several other styles of poetry. Do I take you with me?

c

Yes, he said; I see now what you meant.

I will ask you to remember also what I began by saying, that we had done with the subject and might proceed to the style.

Yes, I remember.

In saying this, I intended to imply that we must come to an understanding about the mimetic art—whether the poets, in narrating their stories, are to be allowed by us to imitate, and if so, whether in whole or in part, and if the latter, in what parts; or should all imitation be prohibited?

d

You mean, I suspect, to ask whether tragedy and comedy shall be admitted into our State?

Yes, I said; but there may be more than this in question: I really do not know as yet, but whither the argument may blow, thither we go.

And go we will, he said.

Then, Adeimantus, let me ask you whether our guardians ought to be imitators; or rather, has not this question been decided by the rule already laid down that one man can only do one thing well, and not many; and that if he attempt many, he will altogether fail of gaining much reputation in any?

e

Certainly.

And this is equally true of imitation; no one man can imitate many things as well as he would imitate a single one?

He cannot.

Then the same person will hardly be able to play a serious part in life, and at the same time to be an imitator and imitate many other parts as well; for even when two species of imitation are nearly allied, the same persons cannot succeed in both, as, for example, the writers of tragedy and comedy—did you not just now call them imitations?

395

Yes, I did; and you are right in thinking that the same persons cannot succeed in both.

Any more than they can be rhapsodists and actors at once?

True.

Neither are comic and tragic actors the same; yet all these things are but imitations.

b

They are so.

And human nature,cx Adeimantus, appears to have been coined into yet smaller pieces, and to be as incapable of imitating many things well, as of performing well the actions of which the imitations are copies.

Quite true, he replied.

If then we adhere to our original notion and bear in mind that our guardians, setting aside every other business, are to dedicate themselves wholly to the maintenance of freedom in the State, making this their craft, and engaging in no work which does not bear on this end, they ought not to practise or imitate anything else; if they imitate at all, they should imitate from youth upward only those characters which are suitable to their profession—the courageous, temperate, holy, free, and the like; but they should not depict or be skilful at imitating any kind of illiberality or baseness, lest from imitation they should come to be what they imitate. Did you never observe how imitations, beginning in early youth and continuing far into life, at length grow into habits and become a second nature, affecting body, voice, and mind?

c
d

Yes, certainly, he said.

Then, I said, we will not allow those for whom we profess a care and of whom we say that they ought to be good men, to imitate a woman, whether young or old, quarrelling with her husband, or striving and vaunting against the gods in conceit of her happiness, or when she is in affliction, or sorrow, or weeping; and certainly not one who is in sickness, love, or labor.

e

Very right, he said.

Neither must they represent slaves, male or female, performing the offices of slaves?

They must not.

And surely not bad men, whether cowards or any others, who do the reverse of what we have just been prescribing, who scold or mock or revile one another in drink or out of drink, or who in any other manner sin against themselves and their neighbors in word or deed, as the manner of such is. Neither should they be trained to imitate the action or speech of men or women who are mad or bad; for madness, like vice, is to be known but not to be practised or imitated.

396

Very true, he replied.

Neither may they imitate smiths or other artificers, or oarsmen, or boatswains, or the like?

How can they, he said, when they are not allowed to apply their minds to the callings of any of these?

b

Nor may they imitate the neighing of horses, the bellowing of bulls, the murmur of rivers and roll of the ocean, thunder, and all that sort of thing?

Nay, he said, if madness be forbidden, neither may they copy the behavior of madmen.

You mean, I said, if I understand you aright, that there is one sort of narrative style which may be employed by a truly good man when he has anything to say, and that another sort will be used by a man of an opposite character and education.

c

And which are these two sorts? he asked.

Suppose, I answered, that a just and good man in the course of a narration comes on some saying or action of another good man—I should imagine that he will like to personate him, and will not be ashamed of this sort of imitation: he will be most ready to play the part of the good man when he is acting firmly and wisely; in a less degree when he is overtaken by illness or love or drink, or has met with any other disaster. But when he comes to a character which is unworthy of him, he will not make a study of that; he will disdain such a person, and will assume his likeness, if at all, for a moment only when he is performing some good action; at other times he will be ashamed to play a part which he has never practised, nor will he like to fashion and frame himself after the baser models; he feels the employment of such an art, unless in jest, to be beneath him, and his mind revolts at it.

d
e

So I should expect, he replied.

Then he will adopt a mode of narration such as we have illustrated out of Homer, that is to say, his style will be both imitative and narrative; but there will be very little of the former, and a great deal of the latter. Do you agree?

Certainly, he said; that is the model which such a speaker must necessarily take.

But there is another sort of character who will narrate anything, and, the worse he is, the more unscrupulous he will be; nothing will be too bad for him: and he will be ready to imitate anything, not as a joke, but in right good earnest, and before a large company. As I was just now saying, he will attempt to represent the roll of thunder, the noise of wind and hail, or the creaking of wheels, and pulleys, and the various sounds of flutes, pipes, trumpets, and all sorts of instruments: he will bark like a dog, bleat like a sheep, or crow like a cock; his entire art will consist in imitation of voice and gesture, and there will be very little narration.

397
b

That, he said, will be his mode of speaking.

These, then, are the two kinds of style?

Yes.

And you would agree with me in saying that one of them is simple and has but slight changes; and if the harmony and rhythm are also chosen for their simplicity, the result is that the speaker, if he speaks correctly, is always pretty much the same in style, and he will keep within the limits of a single harmony (for the changes are not great), and in like manner he will make use of nearly the same rhythm?

c

That is quite true, he said.

Whereas the other requires all sorts of harmonies and all sorts of rhythms, if the music and the style are to correspond, because the style has all sorts of changes.

That is also perfectly true, he replied.

And do not the two styles, or the mixture of the two, comprehend all poetry, and every form of expression in words? No one can say anything except in one or other of them or in both together.

They include all, he said.

And shall we receive into our State all the three styles, or one only of the two unmixed styles? or would you include the mixed?

d

I should prefer only to admit the pure imitator of virtue.

Yes, I said, Adeimantus; but the mixed style is also very charming: and indeed the pantomimic, which is the opposite of the one chosen by you, is the most popular style with children and their attendants, and with the world in general.5

I do not deny it.

But I suppose you would argue that such a style is unsuitable to our State, in which human nature is not twofold or manifold, for one man plays one part only?

e

Yes; quite unsuitable.

And this is the reason why in our State, and in our State only, we shall find a shoemaker to be a shoemaker and not a pilot also, and a husbandman to be a husbandman and not a dicast also, and a soldier a soldier and not a trader also, and the same throughout?

True, he said.

And therefore when any one of these pantomimic gentlemen, who are so clever that they can imitate anything, comes to us, and makes a proposal to exhibit himself and his poetry, we will fall down and worship him as a sweet and holy and wonderful being; but we must also inform him that in our State such as he are not permitted to exist; the law will not allow them. And so when we have anointed him with myrrh, and set a garland of wool upon his head, we shall send him away to another city. For we mean to employ for our souls’ health the rougher and severer poet or story-teller, who will imitate the style of the virtuous only, and will follow those models which we prescribed at first when we began the education of our soldiers.

398
b

We certainly will, he said, if we have the power.

Then now, my friend, I said, that part of music or literary education which relates to the story or myth may be considered to be finished; for the matter and manner have both been discussed.

I think so too, he said.

Next in order will follow melody and song.

c

That is obvious.

Everyone can see already what we ought to say about them, if we are to be consistent with ourselves.

I fear, said Glaucon, laughing, that the word “everyone” hardly includes me, for I cannot at the moment say what they should be; though I may guess.

At any rate you can tell that a song or ode has three parts—the words, the melody,cy and the rhythm; that degree of knowledge I may presuppose?

d

Yes, he said; so much as that you may.

And as for the words, there will surely be no difference between words which are and which are not set to music; both will conform to the same laws, and these have been already determined by us?

Yes.

And the melody and rhythm will depend upon the words?

Certainly.

We were saying, when we spoke of the subject-matter, that we had no need of lamentation and strains of sorrow?

True.

And which are the harmonies expressive of sorrow? You are musical, and can tell me.

e

The harmonies which you mean are the mixed or tenor Lydian, and the full-toned or bass Lydian, and such like.6

These then, I said, must be banished; they are of no use, even to women who have a character to maintain, and much less to men.

Certainly.

In the next place, drunkenness and softness and indolence are utterly unbecoming the character of our guardians.

Utterly unbecoming.

And which are the soft or drinking harmonies?

The Ionian, he replied, and the Lydian; they are termed “relaxed.”

Well, and are these of any military use?

399

Quite the reverse, he replied; and if so, the Dorian and the Phrygian are the only ones which you have left.

I answered: Of the harmonies I know nothing, but I want to have one warlike, to sound the note or accent which a brave man utters in the hour of danger and stern resolve, or when his cause is failing, and he is going to wounds or death or is overtaken by some other evil, and at every such crisis meets the blows of fortune with firm step and a determination to endure; and another to be used by him in times of peace and freedom of action, when there is no pressure of necessity, and he is seeking to persuade God by prayer, or man by instruction and admonition, or on the other hand, when he is expressing his willingness to yield to persuasion or entreaty or admonition, and which represents him when by prudent conduct he has attained his end, not carried away by his success, but acting moderately and wisely under the circumstances, and acquiescing in the event. These two harmonies I ask you to leave; the strain of necessity and the strain of freedom, the strain of the unfortunate and the strain of the fortunate, the strain of courage, and the strain of temperance; these, I say, leave.

b
c

And these, he replied, are the Dorian and Phrygian harmonies of which I was just now speaking.

Then, I said, if these and these only are to be used in our songs and melodies, we shall not want multiplicity of notes or a panharmonic scale?

I suppose not.

Then we shall not maintain the artificers of lyres with three corners and complex scales, or the makers of any other many-stringed, curiously harmonized instruments?7

d

Certainly not.

But what do you say to flute-makers and flute-players? Would you admit them into our State when you reflect that in this composite use of harmony the flutecz is worse than all the stringed instruments put together; even the panharmonic music is only an imitation of the flute?

Clearly not.

There remain then only the lyre and the harpda for use in the city, and the shepherds may have a pipe in the country.

That is surely the conclusion to be drawn from the argument.

The preferring of Apollo and his instruments to Marsyas and his instruments is not at all strange, I said.8

e

Not at all, he replied.

And so, by the dog of Egypt,db we have been unconsciously purging the State, which not long ago we termed luxurious.

And we have done wisely, he replied.

Then let us now finish the purgation, I said. Next in order to harmonies, rhythms will naturally follow, and they should be subject to the same rules, for we ought not to seek out complex systems of metre, or metres of every kind,9 but rather to discover what rhythms are the expressions of a courageous and harmonious life; and when we have found them, we shall adapt the foot and the melody to words having a like spirit, not the words to the foot and melody. To say what these rhythms are will be your duty—you must teach me them, as you have already taught me the harmonies.

But, indeed, he replied, I cannot tell you. I only know that there are some three principles of rhythm out of which metrical systems are framed, 10 just as in sounds there are four notes out of which all the harmonies are composed;11 that is an observation which I have made. But of what sort of lives they are severally the imitations I am unable to say.

400
b

Then, I said, we must take Damondc into our counsels; and he will tell us what rhythms are expressive of meanness, or insolence, or fury, or other unworthiness, and what are to be reserved for the expression of opposite feelings. And I think that I have an indistinct recollection of his mentioning a complex Cretic rhythm; also a dactylic or heroic, and he arranged them in some manner which I do not quite understand, making the rhythms equal in the rise and fall of the foot, long and short alternating; and, unless I am mistaken, he spoke of an iambic as well as of a trochaic rhythm, and assigned to them short and long quantities. Also in some cases he appeared to praise or censure the movement of the foot quite as much as the rhythm; or perhaps a combination of the two; for I am not certain what he meant. These matters, however, as I was saying, had better be referred to Damon himself, for the analysis of the subject would be difficult, you know?

c

Rather so, I should say.

But there is no difficulty in seeing that grace or the absence of grace is an effect of good or bad rhythm.

None at all.

And also that good and bad rhythm naturally assimilate to a good and bad style; and that harmony and discord in like manner follow style; for our principle is that rhythm and harmony are regulated by the words, and not the words by them. 12

d

Just so, he said, they should follow the words.

And will not the words and the character of the style depend on the temper of the soul?

Yes.

And everything else on the style?

Yes.

Then beauty of style and harmony and grace and good rhythm depend on simplicity13—I mean the true simplicity of a rightly and nobly ordered mind and character, not that other simplicity which is only an euphemism for folly?

e

Very true, he replied.

And if our youth are to do their work in life, must they not make these graces and harmonies their perpetual aim?

They must.

And surely the art of the painter and every other creative and constructive art are full of them—weaving, embroidery, architecture, and every kind of manufacture; also nature, animal and vegetable—in all of them there is grace or the absence of grace. And ugliness and discord and inharmonious motion are nearly allied to ill-words and ill-nature, as grace and harmony are the twin sisters of goodness and virtue and bear their likeness.

401

That is quite true, he said.

But shall our superintendence go no further, and are the poets only to be required by us to express the image of the good in their works, on pain, if they do anything else, of expulsion from our State? Or is the same control to be extended to other artists, and are they also to be prohibited from exhibiting the opposite forms of vice and intemperance and meanness and indecency in sculpture and building and the other creative arts; and is he who cannot conform to this rule of ours to be prevented from practising his art in our State, lest the taste of our citizens be corrupted by him? We would not have our guardians grow up amid images of moral deformity, as in some noxious pasture, and there browse and feed upon many a baneful herb and flower day by day, little by little, until they silently gather a festering mass of corruption in their own soul. Let our artists rather be those who are gifted to discern the true nature of the beautiful and graceful; then will our youth dwell in a land of health,14 amid fair sights and sounds, and receive the good in everything; and beauty, the effluence of fair works, shall flow into the eye and ear, like a health-giving breeze from a purer region, and insensibly draw the soul from earliest years into likeness and sympathy with the beauty of reason.

b
c
d

There can be no nobler training than that, he replied.

And therefore, I said, Glaucon, musical training is a more potent instrument than any other, because rhythm and harmony find their way into the inward places of the soul, on which they mightily fasten, imparting grace, and making the soul of him who is rightly educated graceful, or of him who is ill-educated ungrace ful; and also because he who has received this true education of the inner being will most shrewdly perceive omissions or faults in art and nature, and with a true taste, while he praises and rejoices over and receives into his soul the good, and becomes noble and good, he will justly blame and hate the bad, now in the days of his youth, even before he is able to know the reason why; and when reason comes he will recognize and salute the friend with whom his education has made him long familiar.

e
402

Yes, he said, I quite agree with you in thinking that our youth should be trained in music and on the grounds which you mention.

Just as in learning to read, I said, we were satisfied when we knew the letters of the alphabet, which are very few, in all their recurring sizes and combinations; not slighting them as unimportant whether they occupy a space large or small, but everywhere eager to make them out; and not thinking ourselves perfect in the art of reading until we recognize them wherever they are found:

b

True—

Or, as we recognize the reflection of letters in the water, or in a mirror, only when we know the letters themselves; the same art and study giving us the knowledge of both:

Exactly—

Even so, as I maintain, neither we nor our guardians, whom we have to educate, can ever become musical until we and they know the essential forms of temperance, courage, liberality, magnificence, and their kindred, as well as the contrary forms, in all their combinations, and can recognize them and their images wherever they are found, not slighting them either in small things or great, but believing them all to be within the sphere of one art and study.15

c

Most assuredly.

And when a beautiful soul harmonizes with a beautiful form, and the two are cast in one mould, that will be the fairest of sights to him who has an eye to see it?

d

The fairest indeed.

And the fairest is also the loveliest?

That may be assumed.

And the man who has the spirit of harmony will be most in love with the loveliest; but he will not love him who is of an inharmonious soul?

e

That is true, he replied, if the deficiency be in his soul; but if there be any merely bodily defect in another he will be patient of it, and will love all the same.

I perceive, I said, that you have or have had experiences of this sort, and I agree. But let me ask you another question: Has excess of pleasure any affinity to temperance?16

How can that be? he replied; pleasure deprives a man of the use of his faculties quite as much as pain.

Or any affinity to virtue in general?

None whatever.

403

Any affinity to wantonness and intemperance?

Yes, the greatest.

And is there any greater or keener pleasure than that of sensual love?

No, nor a madder.

Whereas true love is a love of beauty and order—temperate and harmonious?

Quite true, he said.

Then no intemperance or madness should be allowed to approach true love?

Certainly not.

Then mad or intemperate pleasure must never be allowed to come near the lover and his beloved; neither of them can have any part in it if their love is of the right sort?

b

No, indeed, Socrates, it must never come near them.

Then I suppose that in the city which we are founding you would make a law to the effect that a friend should use no other familiarity to his love than a father would use to his son, and then only for a noble purpose, and he must first have the other’s consent; and this rule is to limit him in all his intercourse, and he is never to be seen going further, or, if he exceeds, he is to be deemed guilty of coarseness and bad taste.

c

I quite agree, he said.

Thus much of music, which makes a fair ending; for what should be the end of music if not the love of beauty?

I agree, he said.

After music comes gymnastics, in which our youth are next to be trained.

Certainly.

Gymnastics as well as music should begin in early years; the training in it should be careful and should continue through life. Now my belief is—and this is a matter upon which I should like to have your opinion in confirmation of my own, but my own belief is—not that the good body by any bodily excellence improves the soul, but, on the contrary, that the good soul, by her own excellence, improves the body as far as this may be possible. What do you say?

d

Yes, I agree.

Then, to the mind when adequately trained, we shall be right in handing over the more particular care of the body; and in order to avoid prolixity we will now only give the general outlines of the subject.

e

Very good.

That they must abstain from intoxication has been already remarked by us; for of all persons a guardian should be the last to get drunk and not know where in the world he is.

Yes, he said; that a guardian should require another guardian to take care of him is ridiculous indeed.

But next, what shall we say of their food; for the men are in training for the great contest of all—are they not?

Yes, he said.

And will the habit of body of our ordinary athletes be suited to them?

404

Why not?

I am afraid, I said, that a habit of body such as they have is but a sleepy sort of thing, and rather perilous to health. Do you not observe that these athletes sleep away their lives, and are liable to most dangerous illnesses if they depart, in ever so slight a degree, from their customary regimen?

Yes, I do.

Then, I said, a finer sort of training will be required for our warrior athletes, who are to be like wakeful dogs, and to see and hear with the utmost keenness; amid the many changes of water and also of food, of summer heat and winter cold, which they will have to endure when on a campaign, they must not be liable to break down in health.

b

That is my view.

The really excellent gymnastics is twin sister of that simple music which we were just now describing.

How so?

Why, I conceive that there is a gymnastics which, like our music, is simple and good; and especially the military gymnastics.

What do you mean?

My meaning may be learned from Homer;17 he, you know, feeds his heroes at their feasts, when they are campaigning, on soldiers’ fare; they have no fish, although they are on the shores of the Hellespont, and they are not allowed boiled meats, but only roast, which is the food most convenient for soldiers, requiring only that they should light a fire, and not involving the trouble of carrying about pots and pans.

C

True.

And I can hardly be mistaken in saying that sweet sauces are nowhere mentioned in Homer. In proscribing them, however, he is not singular; all professional athletes are well aware that a man who is to be in good condition should take nothing of the kind.

Yes, he said; and knowing this, they are quite right in not taking them.

Then you would not approve of Syracusan dinners, and the refinements of Sicilian cookery?

d

I think not.

Nor, if a man is to be in condition, would you allow him to have a Corinthian girldd as his fair friend?

Certainly not.

Neither would you approve of the delicacies, as they are thought, of Athenian confectionery?de

Certainly not.

All such feeding and living may be rightly compared by us to melody and song composed in the panharmonic style, and in all the rhythms.

e

Exactly.

There complexity engendered license, and here disease; whereas simplicity in music was the parent of temperance in the soul; and simplicity in gymnastics of health in the body.

Most true, he said.

But when intemperance and diseases multiply in a State, halls of justice and medicine are always being opened; and the arts of the doctor and the lawyer give themselves airs, finding how keen is the interest which not only the slaves but the freemen of a city take about them.

405

Of course.

And yet what greater proof can there be of a bad and disgraceful state of education than this, that not only artisans and the meaner sort of people need the skill of first-rate physicians and judges, but also those who would profess to have had a liberal education? Is it not disgraceful, and a great sign of the want of good-breeding, that a man should have to go abroad for his law and physic because he has none of his own at home, and must therefore surrender himself into the hands of other men whom he makes lords and judges over him?

b

Of all things, he said, the most disgraceful.

Would you say “most,” I replied, when you consider that there is a further stage of the evil in which a man is not only a life-long litigant, passing all his days in the courts, either as plaintiff or defendant, but is actually led by his bad taste to pride himself on his litigiousness;18 he imagines that he is a master in dishonesty; able to take every crooked turn, and wriggle into and out of every hole, bending like a withy and getting out of the way of justice: and all for what?—in order to gain small points not worth mentioning, he not knowing that so to order his life as to be able to do without a napping judge is a far higher and nobler sort of thing. Is not that still more disgraceful?

c

Yes, he said, that is still more disgraceful.

Well, I said, and to require the help of medicine, not when a wound has to be cured, or on occasion of an epidemic, but just because, by indolence and a habit of life such as we have been describing, men fill themselves with waters and winds, as if their bodies were a marsh, compelling the ingenious sons of Asclepiusdf to find more names for diseases, such as flatulence and catarrh; is not this, too, a disgrace?

d

Yes, he said, they do certainly give very strange and newfangled names to diseases.

Yes, I said, and I do not believe that there were any such diseases in the days of Asclepius; and this I infer from the circumstance that the hero Eurypylus,dg after he has been wounded in Homer, drinks a cup of Pramnian wine well besprinkled with barley-meal and grated cheese, which are certainly inflammatory, and yet the sons of Asclepius who were at the Trojan war do not blame the damsel who gives him the drink, or rebuke Patroclus, who is treating his case.

e
406

Well, he said, that was surely an extraordinary drink to be given to a person in his condition.

Not so extraordinary, I replied, if you bear in mind that in former days, as is commonly said, before the time of Herodicus,dh the guild of Asclepius did not practise our present system of medicine, which may be said to educate diseases. But Herodicus, being a trainer, and himself of a sickly constitution, by a combination of training and doctoring found out a way of torturing first and chiefly himself, and secondly the rest of the world.

b

How was that? he said.

By the invention of lingering death; for he had a mortal disease which he perpetually tended, and as recovery was out of the question, he passed his entire life as an invalid; he could do nothing but attend upon himself, and he was in constant torment whenever he departed in anything from his usual regimen, and so dying hard, by the help of science he struggled on to old age.

A rare reward of his skill!

Yes, I said; a reward which a man might fairly expect who never understood that, if Asclepius did not instruct his descendants in valetudinarian arts, the omission arose, not from ignorance or inexperience of such a branch of medicine, but because he knew that in all well-ordered States every individual has an occupation to which he must attend, and has therefore no leisure to spend in continually being ill. This we remark in the case of the artisan, but, ludicrously enough, do not apply the same rule to people of the richer sort.

c

How do you mean? he said.

I mean this: When a carpenter is ill he asks the physician for a rough and ready cure; an emetic or a purge or a cautery or the knife—these are his remedies. And if someone prescribes for him a course of dietetics, and tells him that he must swathe and swaddle his head, and all that sort of thing, he replies at once that he has no time to be ill, and that he sees no good in a life which is spent in nursing his disease to the neglect of his customary employment; and therefore bidding good-by to this sort of physician, he resumes his ordinary habits, and either gets well and lives and does his business, or, if his constitution fails, he dies and has no more trouble.

d
e

Yes, he said, and a man in his condition of life ought to use the art of medicine thus far only.

Has he not, I said, an occupation; and what profit would there be in his life if he were deprived of his occupation?

407

Quite true, he said.

But with the rich man this is otherwise; of him we do not say that he has any specially appointed work which he must perform, if he would live.

He is generally supposed to have nothing to do.

Then you never heard of the saying of Phocylides,di that as soon as a man has a livelihood he should practise virtue?

Nay, he said, I think that he had better begin somewhat sooner.

Let us not have a dispute with him about this, I said; but rather ask ourselves: Is the practise of virtue obligatory on the rich man, or can he live without it? And if obligatory on him, then let us raise a further question, whether this dieting of disorders, which is an impediment to the application of the mind in carpentering and the mechanical arts, does not equally stand in the way of the sentiment of Phocylides?

b

Of that, he replied, there can be no doubt; such excessive care of the body, when carried beyond the rules of gymnastics, is most inimical to the practice of virtue.

Yes, indeed, I replied, and equally incompatible with the management of a house, an army, or an office of state; and, what is most important of all, irreconcilable with any kind of study or thought or self-renection—there is a constant suspicion that headache and giddiness are to be ascribed to philosophy, and hence all practising or making trial of virtue in the higher sense is absolutely stopped; for a man is always fancying that he is being made ill, and is in constant anxiety about the state of his body.

c

Yes, likely enough.

And therefore Asclepius may be supposed to have exhibited the power of his art only to persons who, being generally of healthy constitution and habits of life, had a definite ailment; such as these he cured by purges and operations, and bade them live as usual, herein consulting the interests of the State; but bodies which disease had penetrated through and through he would not have attempted to cure by gradual processes of evacuation and infusion: he did not want to lengthen out good-for-nothing lives, or to have weak fathers begetting weaker sons;—if a man was not able to live in the ordinary way he had no business to cure him; for such a cure would have been of no use either to himself, or to the State.

d
e

Then, he said, you regard Asclepius as a statesman.19

Clearly; and his character is further illustrated by his sons. Note that they were heroes in the days of old and practised the medicines of which I am speaking at the siege of Troy: You will remember how, when Pandarus wounded Menelaus, they “Sucked the blood out of the wound, and sprinkled soothing remedies,” dj but they never prescribed what the patient was afterward to eat or drink in the case of Menelaus, any more than in the case of Eurypylus; the remedies, as they conceived, were enough to heal any man who before he was wounded was healthy and regular in his habits; and even though he did happen to drink a cup of Pramnian wine, he might get well all the same. But they would have nothing to do with unhealthy and intemperate subjects, whose lives were of no use either to themselves or others; the art of medicine was not designed for their good, and though they were as rich as Midas,dk the sons of Asclepius would have declined to attend them.

408
b

They were very acute persons, those sons of Asclepius.

Naturally so, I replied. Nevertheless, the tragedians and Pindar disobeying our behests,dl although they acknowledge that Asclepius was the son of Apollo, say also that he was bribed into healing a rich man who was at the point of death, and for this reason he was struck by lightning. But we, in accordance with the principle already affirmed by us, will not believe them when they tell us both; if he was the son of a god, we maintain that he was not avaricious; or, if he was avaricious, he was not the son of a god.

c

All that, Socrates, is excellent; but I should like to put a question to you: Ought there not to be good physicians in a State, and are not the best those who have treated the greatest number of constitutions, good and bad? and are not the best judges in like manner those who are acquainted with all sorts of moral natures?20

d

Yes, I said, I too would have good judges and good physicians. But do you know whom I think good?

Will you tell me?

I will, if I can. Let me, however, note that in the same question you join two things which are not the same.

How so? he asked.

Why, I said, you join physicians and judges. Now the most skilful physicians are those who, from their youth upward, have combined with the knowledge of their art the greatest experience of disease; they had better not be robust in health, and should have had all manner of diseases in their own persons. For the body, as I conceive, is not the instrument with which they cure the body; in that case we could not allow them ever to be or to have been sickly; but they cure the body with the mind, and the mind which has become and is sick can cure nothing.

e

That is very true, he said.

But with the judge it is otherwise; since he governs mind by mind; he ought not therefore to have been trained among vicious minds, and to have associated with them from youth upward, and to have gone through the whole calendar of crime, only in order that he may quickly infer the crimes of others as he might their bodily diseases from his own self-consciousness; the honorable mind which is to form a healthy judgment should have had no experience or contamination of evil habits when young. And this is the reason why in youth good men often appear to be simple, and are easily practised upon by the dishonest, because they have no examples of what evil is in their own souls.

409
b

Yes, he said, they are far too apt to be deceived.

Therefore, I said, the judge should not be young; he should have learned to know evil, not from his own soul, but from late and long observation of the nature of evil in others: knowledge should be his guide, not personal experience.

c

Yes, he said, that is the ideal of a judge.

Yes, I replied, and he will be a good man (which is my answer to your question); for he is good who has a good soul. But the cunning and suspicious nature of which we spoke—he who has committed many crimes, and fancies himself to be a master in wickedness—when he is among his fellows, is wonderful in the precautions which he takes, because he judges of them by himself: but when he gets into the company of men of virtue, who have the experience of age, he appears to be a fool again, owing to his unseasonable suspicions; he cannot recognize an honest man, because he has no pattern of honesty in himself; at the same time, as the bad are more numerous than the good, and he meets with them oftener, he thinks himself, and is by others thought to be, rather wise than foolish.

d

Most true, he said.

Then the good and wise judge whom we are seeking is not this man, but the other; for vice cannot know virtue too, but a virtuous nature, educated by time, will acquire a knowledge both of virtue and vice: the virtuous, and not the vicious, man has wisdom—in my opinion.

e

And in mine also.

This is the sort of medicine, and this is the sort of law, which you will sanction in your State. They will minister to better natures, giving health both of soul and of body; but those who are diseased in their bodies they will leave to die, and the corrupt and incurable souls they will put an end to themselves.

410

That is clearly the best thing both for the patients and for the State.

And thus our youth, having been educated only in that simple music which, as we said, inspires temperance, will be reluctant to go to law.

Clearly.

And the musician, who, keeping to the same track, is content to practise the simple gymnastics, will have nothing to do with medicine unless in some extreme case.

b

That I quite believe.

The very exercises and toils which he undergoes are intended to stimulate the spirited element of his nature, and not to increase his strength; he will not, like common athletes, use exercise and regimen to develop his muscles.

Very right, he said.

Neither are the two arts of music and gymnastics really designed, as is often supposed, the one for the training of the soul, the other for the training of the body.

c

What then is the real object of them?

I believe, I said, that the teachers of both have in view chiefly the improvement of the soul.

How can that be? he asked.

Did you never observe, I said, the effect on the mind itself of exclusive devotion to gymnastics, or the opposite effect of an exclusive devotion to music?

In what way shown? he said.

The one producing a temper of hardness and ferocity, the other of softness and effeminacy, I replied.

d

Yes, he said, I am quite aware that the mere athlete becomes too much of a savage, and that the mere musician is melted and softened beyond what is good for him.

Yet surely, I said, this ferocity only comes from spirit, which, if rightly educated, would give courage, but, if too much intensified, is liable to become hard and brutal.

That I quite think.

On the other hand the philosopher will have the quality of gentleness. And this also, when too much indulged, will turn to softness, but, if educated rightly, will be gentle and moderate.

e

True.

And in our opinion the guardians ought to have both these qualities?21

Assuredly.

And both should be in harmony?

Beyond question.

And the harmonious soul is both temperate and courageous?

411

Yes.

And the inharmonious is cowardly and boorish?

Very true.

And, when a man allows music to play upon him and to pour into his soul through the funnel of his ears those sweet and soft and melancholy airs of which we were just now speaking, and his whole life is passed in warbling and the delights of song; in the first stage of the process the passion or spirit which is in him is tempered like iron, and made useful, instead of brittle and useless. But, if he carries on the softening and soothing process, in the next stage he begins to melt and waste, until he has wasted away his spirit and cut out the sinews of his soul; and he becomes a feeble warrior.

b

Very true.

If the element of spirit is naturally weak in him the change is speedily accomplished, but if he have a good deal, then the power of music weakening the spirit renders him excitable; on the least provocation he flames up at once, and is speedily extinguished; instead of having spirit he grows-irritable and passionate and is quite impractical.

c

bExactly.

And so in gymnastics, if a man takes violent exercise and is a great feeder, and the reverse of a great student of music and philosophy, at first the high condition of his body fills him with pride and spirit, and he becomes twice the man that he was.

Certainly.

And what happens? if he do nothing else, and holds no converse with the muses, does not even that intelligence which there may be in him, having no taste of any sort of learning or inquiry or thought or culture, grow feeble and dull and blind, his mind never waking up or receiving nourishment, and his senses not being purged of their mists?

d

True, he said.

And he ends by becoming a hater of philosophy, uncivilized, never using the weapon of persuasion—he is like a wild beast, all violence and fierceness, and knows no other way of dealing; and he lives in all ignorance and evil conditions, and has no sense of propriety and grace.

e

That is quite true, he said.

And as there are two principles of human nature, one the spirited and the other the philosophical, some god, as I should say, has given mankind two arts answering to them (and only indirectly to the soul and body), in order that these two principles (like the strings of an instrument) may be relaxed or drawn tighter until they are duly harmonized.

412

That appears to be the intention.

And he who mingles music with gymnastics in the fairest proportions, and best attempers them to the soul, may be rightly called the true musician and harmonist in a far higher sense than the tuner of the strings.

You are quite right, Socrates.

And such a presiding genius will be always required in our State if the government is to last.

Yes, he will be absolutely necessary.

b

Such, then, are our principles of nurture and education: Where would be the use of going into further details about the dances of our citizens, or about their hunting and coursing, their gymnastic and equestrian contests? For these all follow the general principle, and having found that, we shall have no difficulty in discovering them.

I dare say that there will be no difficulty.

Very good, I said; then what is the next question?22 Must we not ask who are to be rulers and who subjects?

Certainly.

c

There can be no doubt that the elder must rule the younger.

Clearly.

And that the best of these must rule.

That is also clear.

Now, are not the best husbandmen those who are most devoted to husbandry?

Yes.

And as we are to have the best of guardians for our city, must they not be those who have most the character of guardians?

Yes.

And to this end they ought to be wise and efficient, and to have a special care of the State?

True.

d

And a man will be most likely to care about that which he loves?

To be sure.

And he will be most likely to love that which he regards as having the same interests with himself, and that of which the good or evil fortune is supposed by him at any time most to affect his own?

Very true, he replied.

Then there must be a selection. Let us note among the guardians those who in their whole life show the greatest eagerness to do what is for the good of their country, and the greatest repugnance to do what is against her interests.

e

Those are the right men.

And they will have to be watched at every age, in order that we may see whether they preserve their resolution, and never, under the influence either of force or enchantment, forget or cast off their sense of duty to the State.

How cast off? he said.

I will explain to you, he replied. A resolution may go out of a man’s mind either with his will or against his will; with his will when he gets rid of a falsehood and learns better, against his will whenever he is deprived of a truth.

413

I understand, he said, the willing loss of a resolution; the meaning of the unwilling I have yet to learn.

Why, I said, do you not see that men are unwillingly deprived of good, and willingly of evil? Is not to have lost the truth an evil, and to possess the truth a good? and you would agree that to conceive things as they are is to possess the truth?

Yes, he replied; I agree with you in thinking that mankind are deprived of truth against their will.

And is not this involuntary deprivation caused either by theft, or force, or enchantment?

b

Still, he replied, I do not understand you.

I fear that I must have been talking darkly, like the tragedians. I only mean that some men are changed by persuasion and that others forget; argument steals away the hearts of one class, and time of the other; and this I call theft. Now you understand me?

Yes.

Those again who are forced, are those whom the violence of some pain or grief compels to change their opinion.

I understand, he said, and you are quite right.

And you would also acknowledge that the enchanted are those who change their minds either under the softer influence of pleasure, or the sterner influence of fear?

c

Yes, he said; everything that deceives may be said to enchant.

Therefore, as I was just now saying, we must inquire who are the best guardians of their own conviction that what they think the interest of the State is to be the rule of their lives.23 We must watch them from their youth upward, and make them perform actions in which they are most likely to forget or to be deceived, and he who remembers and is not deceived is to be selected, and he who fails in the trial is to be rejected. That will be the way?

d

Yes.

And there should also be toils and pains and conflicts prescribed for them, in which they will be made to give further proof of the same qualities.

Very right, he replied.

And then, I said, we must try them with enchantments—that is the third sort of test—and see what will be their behavior: like those who take colts amid noise and tumult to see if they are of a timid nature, so must we take our youth amid terrors of some kind, and again pass them into pleasures, and prove them more thoroughly than gold is proved in the furnace, that we may discover whether they are armed against all enchantments, and of a noble bearing always, good guardians of themselves and of the music which they have learned,24 and retaining under all circumstances a rhythmical and harmonious nature, such as will be most serviceable to the individual and to the State. And he who at every age, as boy and youth and in mature life, has come out of the trial victorious and pure, shall be appointed a ruler and guardian of the State; he shall be honored in life and death, and shall receive sepulture and other memorials of honor, the greatest that we have to give. But him who fails, we must reject. I am inclined to think that this is the sort of way in which our rulers and guardians should be chosen and appointed. I speak generally, and not with any pretension to exactness.

e
414

And, speaking generally, I agree with you, he said.

And perhaps the word “guardian” in the fullest sense ought to be applied to this higher class only who preserve us against foreign enemies and maintain peace among our citizens at home, that the one may not have the will, or the others the power, to harm us. The young men whom we before called guardians may be more properly designated auxiliaries and supporters of the principles of the rulers.

b

I agree with you, he said.

How then may we devise one of those needful falsehoods of which we lately spoke—just one royal lie which may deceive the rulers, if that be possible, and at any rate the rest of the city?

c

What sort of lie? he said.

Nothing new, I replied; only an old Phœnician tale25 of what has often occurred before now in other places (as the poets say, and have made the world believe), though not in our time, and I do not know whether such an event could ever happen again, or could now even be made probable, if it did.

How your words seem to hesitate on your lips!

You will not wonder, I replied, at my hesitation when you have heard.

Speak, he said, and fear not.

Well, then, I will speak, although I really know not how to look you in the face, or in what words to utter the audacious fiction, which I propose to communicate gradually, first to the rulers, then to the soldiers, and lastly to the people. They are to be told that their youth was a dream, and the education and training which they received from us, an appearance only; in reality during all that time they were being formed and fed in the womb of the earth,dm where they themselves and their arms and appurtenances were manufactured; when they were completed, the earth, their mother, sent them up; and so, their country being their mother and also their nurse, they are bound to advise for her good, and to defend her against attacks, and her citizens they are to regard as children of the earth and their own brothers.

d
e

You had good reason, he said, to be ashamed of the lie which you were going to tell.

True, I replied, but there is more coming; I have only told you half. Citizens, we shall say to them in our tale, you are brothers, yet God has framed you differently.dnSome of you have the power of command, and in the composition of these he has mingled gold,26 wherefore also they have the greatest honor; others he has made of silver, to be auxiliaries; others again who are to be husbandmen and craftsmen he has composed of brass and iron; and the species will generally be preserved in the children. But as all are of the same original stock, a golden parent will sometimes have a silver son, or a silver parent a golden son. And God proclaims as a first principle to the rulers, and above all else, that there is nothing which they should so anxiously guard, or of which they are to be such good guardians, as of the purity of the race. They should observe what elements mingle in their offspring; for if the son of a golden or silver parent has an admixture of brass and iron, then nature orders a transposition of ranks, and the eye of the ruler must not be pitiful toward the child because he has to descend in the scale and become a husbandman or artisan, just as there may be sons of artisans who having an admixture of gold or silver in them are raised to honor, and become guardians or auxiliaries. For an oracle says that when a man of brass or iron guards the State, it will be destroyed. Such is the tale; is there any possibility of making our citizens believe in it?

415
b
c

Not in the present generation,27 he replied; there is no way of accomplishing this; but their sons may be made to believe in the tale, and their sons’ sons, and posterity after them.

d

I see the difficulty, I replied; yet the fostering of such a belief will make them care more for the city and for one another. Enough, however, of the fiction, which may now fly abroad upon the wings of rumor, while we arm our earth-born heroes, and lead them forth under the command of their rulers. Let them look round and select a spot whence they can best suppress insurrection, if any prove refractory within, and also defend themselves against enemies, who, like wolves, may come down on the fold from without; there let them encamp, and when they have encamped, let them sacrifice to the proper gods and prepare their dwellings.

e

Just so, he said.

And their dwellings must be such as will shield them against the cold of winter and the heat of summer.

I suppose that you mean houses, he replied.

Yes, I said; but they must be the houses of soldiers, and not of shopkeepers.

What is the difference? he said.

416

That I will endeavor to explain, I replied. To keep watchdogs, who, from want of discipline or hunger, or some evil habit or other, would turn upon the sheep and worry them, and behave not like dogs, but wolves, would be a foul and monstrous thing in a shepherd?

Truly monstrous, he said.

And therefore every care must be taken that our auxiliaries, being stronger than our citizens, may not grow to be too much for them and become savage tyrants instead of friends and allies?

Yes, great care should be taken.

b

And would not a really good education furnish the best safeguard?

But they are well-educated already, he replied.

I cannot be so confident, my dear Glaucon, I said; I am much more certain that they ought to be, and that true education, whatever that may be, will have the greatest tendency to civilize and humanize them in their relations to one another, and to those who are under their protection.

c

Very true, he replied.

And not only their education, but their habitations, and all that belongs to them, should be such as will neither impair their virtue as guardians, nor tempt them to prey upon the other citizens. Any man of sense must acknowledge that.

d

He must.

Then now let us consider what will be their way of life, if they are to realize our idea of them. In the first place, none of them should have any property of his own beyond what is absolutely necessary; neither should they have a private house or store closed against anyone who has a mind to enter; their provisions should be only such as are required by trained warriors, who are men of temperance and courage; they should agree to receive from the citizens a fixed rate of pay, enough to meet the expenses of the year and no more; and they will go to mess and live together like soldiers in a camp. Gold and silver we will tell them that they have from God; the diviner metal is within them, and they have therefore no need of the dross which is current among men, and ought not to pollute the divine by any such earthly admixture; for that commoner metal has been the source of many unholy deeds, but their own is undefiled.28 And they alone of all the citizens may not touch or handle silver or gold, or be under the same roof with them, or wear them, or drink from them. And this will be their salvation, and they will be the saviours of the State. But should they ever acquire homes or lands or moneys of their own, they will become good housekeepers and husbandmen instead of guardians, enemies and tyrants instead of allies of the other citizens; hating and being hated, plotting and being plotted against, they will pass their whole life in much greater terror of internal than of external enemies, and the hour of ruin, both to themselves and to the rest of the State, will be at hand. For all which reasons may we not say that thus shall our State be ordered, and that these shall be the regulations appointed by us for our guardians concerning their houses and all other matters?

e
417
b

Yes, said Glaucon.

BOOK 4

HERE ADEIMANTUS INTERPOSED A question: How would you answer, Socrates, said he, if a person were to say that you are making these people miserable, and that they are the cause of their own unhappiness; the city in fact belongs to them, but they are none the better for it; whereas other men acquire lands, and build large and handsome houses, and have everything handsome about them, offering sacrifices to the gods on their own account, and practising hospitality; moreover, as you were saying just now, they have gold and silver, and all that is usual among the favorites of fortune; but our poor citizens are no better than mercenaries who are quartered in the city and are always mounting guard?

419
420

Yes, I said; and you may add that they are only fed, and not paid in addition to their food, like other men; and therefore they cannot, if they would, take a journey of pleasure; they have no money to spend on a mistress or any other luxurious fancy, which, as the world goes, is thought to be happiness; and many other accusations of the same nature might be added.

But, said he, let us suppose all this to be included in the charge.

You mean to ask, I said, what will be our answer?

b

Yes.

If we proceed along the old path, my belief, I said, is that we shall find the answer. And our answer will be that, even as they are, our guardians may very likely be the happiest of men; but that our aim in founding the State was not the disproportionate happiness of any one class, but the greatest happiness of the whole; we thought that in a State which is ordered with a view to the good of the whole we should be most likely to find justice, and in the ill-ordered State injustice: and, having found them, we might then decide which of the two is the happier. At present, I take it, we are fashioning the happy State, not piecemeal, or with a view of making a few happy citizens, but as a whole; and by and by we will proceed to view the opposite kind of State. Suppose that we were painting a statue, and someone came up to us and said: Why do you not put the most beautiful colors on the most beautiful parts of the body—the eyes ought to be purple, but you have made them black—to him we might fairly answer: Sir, you would not surely have us beautify the eyes to such a degree that they are no longer eyes; consider rather whether, by giving this and the other features their due proportion, we make the whole beautiful. And so I say to you, do not compel us to assign to the guardians a sort of happiness which will make them anything but guardians; for we too can clothe our husbandmen in royal apparel, and set crowns of gold on their heads, and bid them till the ground as much as they like, and no more. Our potters also might be allowed to repose on couches, and feast by the fireside, passing round the wine-cup, while their wheel is conveniently at hand, and working at pottery only as much as they like; in this way we might make every class happy—and then, as you imagine, the whole State would be happy. But do not put this idea into our heads; for, if we listen to you, the husbandman will be no longer a husbandman, the potter will cease to be a potter, and no one will have the character of any distinct class in the State. Now this is not of much consequence where the corruption of society, and pretension to be what you are not, are confined to cobblers; but when the guardians of the laws and of the government are only seeming and not real guardians, then see how they turn the State upside down; and on the other hand they alone have the power of giving order and happiness to the State. We mean our guardians to be true saviours and not the de stroyers of the State, whereas our opponentdo is thinking of peasants at a festival, who are enjoying a life of revelry, not of citizens who are doing their duty to the State. But, if so, we mean different things, and he is speaking of something which is not a State. And therefore we must consider whether in appointing our guardians we would look to their greatest happiness individually, or whether this principle of happiness does not rather reside in the State as a whole. But if the latter be the truth, then the guardians and auxiliaries, and all others equally with them, must be compelled orinduced to do their own work in the best way. And thus the whole State will grow up in a noble order, and the several classes will receive the proportion of happiness which nature assigns to them.

c
d
e
421
b
c

I think that you are quite right.

I wonder whether you will agree with another remark which occurs to me.

What may that be?

There seem to be two causes of the corruption of artisans.

d

What are they?

Wealth, I said, and poverty.

How do they act?

The process is as follows: When a potter becomes rich, will he, think you, any longer take the same pains with his art?

Certainly not.

He will grow more and more indolent and careless?

Very true.

And the result will be that he becomes a worse potter?

Yes; he greatly deteriorates.

But, on the other hand, if he has no money, and cannot provide himself with tools or instruments, he will not work equally well himself, nor will he teach his sons or apprentices to work equally well.

e

Certainly not.

Then, under the influence either of poverty or of wealth, workmen and their work are equally liable to degenerate?

That is evident.

Here, then, is a discovery of new evils, I said, against which the guardians will have to watch, or they will creep into the city unobserved.

What evils?

Wealth, I said, and poverty; the one is the parent of luxury and indolence, and the other of meanness and viciousness, and both of discontent.

422

That is very true, he replied; but still I should like to know, Socrates, how our city will be able to go to war, especially against an enemy who is rich and powerful, if deprived of the sinews of war.

There would certainly be a difficulty, I replied, in going to war with one such enemy; but there is no difficulty where there are two of them.

b

How so? he asked.

In the first place, I said, if we have to fight, our side will be trained warriors fighting against an army of rich men.

That is true, he said.

And do you not suppose, Adeimantus, that a single boxer who was perfect in his art would easily be a match for two stout and well-to-do gentlemen who were not boxers?

Hardly, if they came upon him at once.

What, not, I said, if he were able to run away and then turn and strike at the one who first came up? And supposing he were to do this several times under the heat of a scorching sun, might he not, being an expert, overturn more than one stout personage?

c

Certainly, he said, there would be nothing wonderful in that.

And yet rich men probably have a greater superiority in the science and practise of boxing than they have in military qualities.

Likely enough.

Then we may assume that our athletes will be able to fight with two or three times their own number?

I agree with you, for I think you right.

And suppose that, before engaging, our citizens send an embassy to one of the two cities, telling them what is the truth: Silver and gold we neither have nor are permitted to have, but you may; do you therefore come and help us in war, and take the spoils of the other city: Who, on hearing these words, would choose to fight against lean wiry dogs, rather than, with the dogs on their side, against fat and tender sheep?

d

That is not likely; and yet there might be a danger to the poor State if the wealth of many States were to be gathered into one.

e

But how simple of you to use the term State at all of any but our own!

Why so?

You ought to speak of other States in the plural number; not one of them is a city, but many cities, as they say in the game.dp For indeed any city, however small, is in fact divided into two, one the city of the poor, the other of the rich; these are at war with one another; and in either there are many smaller divisions, and you would be altogether beside the mark if you treated them all as a single State. But if you deal with them as many, and give the wealth or power or persons of the one to the others, you will always have a great many friends and not many enemies. And your State, while the wise order which has now been prescribed continues to prevail in her, will be the greatest of States, I do not mean to say in reputation or appearance, but in deed and truth, though she number not more than 1,000 defenders. A single State which is her equal you will hardly find, either among Hellenes or barbarians,1 though many that appear to be as great and many times greater.

423
b

That is most true, he said.

And what, I said, will be the best limit for our rulers to fix when they are considering the size of the State and the amount of territory which they are to include, and beyond which they will not go?

What limit would you propose?

I would allow the State to increase so far as is consistent with unity; that, I think, is the proper limit.

Very good, he said.

c

Here then, I said, is another order which will have to be conveyed to our guardians: Let our city be accounted neither large nor small, but one and self-sufficing.

d

And surely, said he, this is not a very severe order which we impose upon them.

And the other, said I, of which we were speaking before is lighter still—I mean the duty of degrading the offspring of the guardians when inferior, and of elevating into the rank of guardians the offspring of the lower classes, when naturally superior. The intention was, that, in the case of the citizens generally, each individual should be put to the use for which nature intended him, one to one work, and then every man would do his own business, and be one and not many; and so the whole city would be one and not many.

e

Yes, he said; that is not so difficult.

The regulations which we are prescribing, my good Adeimantus, are not, as might be supposed, a number of great principles, but trifles all, if care be taken, as the saying is, of the one great thing—a thing, however, which I would rather call, not great, but sufficient for our purpose.

What may that be? he asked.

Education, I said, and nurture: If our citizens are well educated, and grow into sensible men, they will easily see their way through all these, as well as other matters which I omit; such, for example, as marriage, the possession of women and the procreation of children, which will all follow the general principle that friends have all things in common,2 as the proverb says.

424

That will be the best way of settling them.

Also, I said, the State, if once started well, moves with accumulating force like a wheel. For good nurture and education implant good constitutions, and these good constitutions taking root in a good education improve more and more, and this improvement affects the breed in man as in other animals.

b

Very possibly, he said.

Then to sum up: This is the point to which, above all, the attention of our rulers should be directed—that music and gymnastics be preserved in their original form, and no innovation made. They must do their utmost to maintain them intact. And when anyone says that mankind most regard they will be afraid that he may be praising, not new songs, but a new kind of song; and this ought not to be praised, or conceived to be the meaning of the poet; for any musical innovation is full of danger to the whole State, and ought to be prohibited. So Damon tells me, and I can quite believe him; he says that when modes of music change, the fundamental laws of the State always change with them.3

“The newest song which the singers have,”dq
c

Yes, said Adeimantus; and you may add my vote to Damon’s and your own.

Then, I said, our guardians must lay the foundations of their fortress in music?

d

Yes, he said; the lawlessness of which you speak too easily steals in.

e

Yes, I replied, in the form of amusement; and at first sight it appears harmless.4

Why, yes, he said, and there is no harm; were it not that little by little this spirit of license, finding a home, imperceptibly penetrates into manners and customs; whence, issuing with greater force, it invades contracts between man and man, and from contracts goes on to laws and constitutions, in utter recklessness, ending at last, Socrates, by an overthrow of all rights, private as well as public.

425

Is that true? I said.

That is my belief, he replied.

Then, as I was saying, our youth should be trained from the first in a stricter system, for if amusements become lawless, and the youths themselves become lawless, they can never grow up into well-conducted and virtuous citizens.

b

Very true, he said.

And when they have made a good beginning in play, and by the help of music have gained the habit of good order, then this habit of order, in a manner how unlike the lawless play of the others! will accompany them in all their actions and be a principle of growth to them, and if there be any fallen places in the State will raise them up again.

Very true, he said.

Thus educated, they will invent for themselves any lesser rules which their predecessors have altogether neglected.

What do you mean?

I mean such things as these:—when the young are to be silent before their elders; how they are to show respect to them by standing and making them sit; what honor is due to parents; what garments or shoes are to be worn; the mode of dressing the hair; deportment and manners in general. You would agree with me?

c

Yes.

But there is, I think, small wisdom in legislating about such matters—I doubt if it is ever done; nor are any precise written enactments about them likely to be lasting.

Impossible.

It would seem, Adeimantus, that the direction in which education starts a man, will determine his future life. Does not like always attract like?

To be sure.

Until some one rare and grand result is reached which may be good, and may be the reverse of good?

That is not to be denied.

And for this reason, I said, I shall not attempt to legislate further about them.

Naturally enough, he replied.

Well, and about the business of the agora, and the ordinary dealings between man and man, or again about agreements with artisans; about insult and injury, or the commencement of actions, and the appointment of juries, what would you say? there may also arise questions about any impositions and exactions of market and harbor dues which may be required, and in general about the regulations of markets, police, harbors, and the like. But, O heavens! shall we condescend to legislate on any of these particulars?

d

I think, he said, that there is no need to impose laws about them on good men; what regulations are necessary they will find out soon enough for themselves.

e

Yes, I said, my friend, if God will only preserve to them the laws which we have given them.

And without divine help, said Adeimantus, they will go on forever making and mending the laws and their lives in the hope of attaining perfection.

You would compare them, I said, to those invalids who, having no self-restraint, will not leave off their habits of intemperance?

Exactly.

Yes, I said; and what a delightful life they lead! they are always doctoring and increasing and complicating their disorders, and always fancying that they will be cured by any panacea which anybody advises them to try.

426

Such cases are very common, he said, with invalids of this sort. Yes, I replied; and the charming thing is that they deem him their worst enemy who tells them the truth, which is simply that, unless they give up eating and drinking and wenching and idling, neither drug nor cautery nor spell nor amulet nor any other remedy will avail.

b

Charming! he replied. I see nothing in going into a passion with a man who tells you what is right.

These gentlemen, I said, do not seem to be in your good graces.

Assuredly not.

Nor would you praise the behavior of States which act like the men whom I was just now describing. For are there not ill-ordered States in which the citizens are forbidden under pain of death to alter the constitution; and yet he who most sweetly courts those who live under this regime and indulges them and fawns upon them and is skilful in anticipating and gratifying their humors is held to be a great and good statesman—do not these States resemble the persons whom I was describing?5

c

Yes, he said; the States are as bad as the men; and I am very far from praising them.

But do you not admire, I said, the coolness and dexterity of these ready ministers of political corruption?

d

Yes, he said, I do; but not of all of them, for there are some whom the applause of the multitude has deluded into the belief that they are really statesmen, and these are not much to be admired.

What do you mean? I said; you should have more feeling for them. When a man cannot measure, and a great many others who cannot measure declare that he is four cubits high, can he help believing what they say?

e

Nay, he said, certainly not in that case.

Well, then, do not be angry with them; for are they not as good as a play, trying their hand at paltry reforms such as I was describing; they are always fancying that by legislation they will make an end of frauds in contracts, and the other rascalities which I was mentioning, not knowing that they are in reality cutting off the heads of a hydra? dr

Yes, he said; that is just what they are doing.

I conceive, I said, that the true legislator will not trouble himself with this class of enactments whether concerning laws or the constitution either in an ill-ordered or in a well-ordered State; for in the former they are quite useless, and in the latter there will be no difficulty in devising them; and many of them will naturally flow out of our previous regulations.

427

What, then, he said, is still remaining to us of the work of legislation?

b

Nothing to us, I replied; but to Apollo, the god of Delphi,ds there remains the ordering of the greatest and noblest and chiefest things of all.

Which are they? he said.

The institution of temples and sacrifices, and the entire service of gods, demigods,dt and heroes;du also the ordering of the repositories of the dead, and the rites which have to be observed by him who would propitiate the inhabitants of the world below.dv These are matters of which we are ignorant ourselves, and as founders of a city we should be unwise in trusting them to any interpreter but our ancestral deity.dw He is the god who sits in the centre, on the navel of the earth, and he is the interpreter of religion to all mankind.

c

You are right, and we will do as you propose.

But where, amid all this, is justice? Son of Ariston, tell me where. Now that our city has been made habitable, light a candle and search, and get your brother and Polemarchus and the rest of our friends to help, and let us see where in it we can discover justice and where injustice, and in what they differ from one another, and which of them the man who would be happy should have for his portion, whether seen or unseen by gods and men.

d

Nonsense, said Glaucon: did you not promise to search yourself, saying that for you not to help justice in her need would be an impiety?

e

I do not deny that I said so; and as you remind me, I will be as good as my word; but you must join.

We will, he replied.

Well, then, I hope to make the discovery in this way: I mean to begin with the assumption that our State, if rightly ordered, is perfect.

That is most certain.

And being perfect, is therefore wise and valiant and temperate and just.

That is likewise clear.

And whichever of these qualities we find in the State, the one which is not found will be the residue?

Very good.

428

If there were four things, and we were searching for one of them, wherever it might be, the one sought for might be known to us from the first, and there would be no further trouble; or we might know the other three first, and then the fourth would clearly be the one left.

Very true, he said.

And is not a similar method to be pursued about the virtues, which are also four in number?6

Clearly.

First among the virtues found in the State, wisdom comes into view, and in this I detect a certain peculiarity.

b

What is that?

The State which we have been describing is said to be wise as being good in counsel?

Very true.

And good counsel is clearly a kind of knowledge, for not by ignorance, but by knowledge, do men counsel well?

Clearly.

And the kinds of knowledge in a State are many and diverse? Of course.

There is the knowledge of the carpenter; but is that the sort of knowledge which gives a city the title of wise and good in counsel?

Certainly not; that would only give a city the reputation of skill in carpentering.

c

Then a city is not to be called wise because possessing a knowledge which counsels for the best about wooden implements?

Certainly not.

Nor by reason of a knowledge which advises about brazen pots, he said, nor as possessing any other similar knowledge?

Not by reason of any of them, he said.

Nor yet by reason of a knowledge which cultivates the earth; that would give the city the name of agricultural?

Yes.

Well, I said, and is there any knowledge in our recently founded State among any of the citizens which advises, not about any particular thing in the State, but about the whole, and considers how a State can best deal with itself and with other States?

d

There certainly is.

And what is this knowledge, and among whom is it found? I asked.

It is the knowledge of the guardians, he replied, and is found among those whom we were just now describing as perfect guardians.

And what is the name which the city derives from the possession of this sort of knowledge?

The name of good in counsel and truly wise.

And will there be in our city more of these true guardians or more smiths?

e

The smiths, he replied, will be tar more numerous.

Will not the guardians be the smallest of all the classes who receive a name from the profession of some kind of knowledge?

Much the smallest.

And so by reason of the smallest part or class, and of the knowledge which resides in this presiding and ruling part of itself, the whole State, being thus constituted according to nature, will be wise; and this, which has the only knowledge worthy to be called wisdom, has been ordained by nature to be of all classes the least.

429

Most true.

Thus, then, I said, the nature and place in the State of one of the four virtues have somehow or other been discovered.

And, in my humble opinion, very satisfactorily discovered, he replied.

Again, I said, there is no difficulty in seeing the nature of courage, and in what part that quality resides which gives the name of courageous to the State.

How do you mean?

Why, I said, everyone who calls any State courageous or cow ardly, will be thinking of the part which fights and goes out to war on the State’s behalf.

b

No one, he replied, would ever think of any other.

The rest of the citizens may be courageous or may be cowardly, but their courage or cowardice will not, as I conceive, have the effect of making the city either the one or the other.

Certainly not.

The city will be courageous in virtue of a portion of herself which preserves under all circumstances that opinion about the nature of things to be feared and not to be feared in which our legislator educated them; and this is what you term courage.

c

I should like to hear what you are saying once more, for I do not think that I perfectly understand you.

I mean that courage is a kind of salvation.

Salvation of what?

Of the opinion respecting things to be feared, what they are and of what nature, which the law implants through education; and I mean by the words “under all circumstances” to intimate that in pleasure or in pain, or under the influence of desire or fear, a man preserves, and does not lose this opinion. Shall I give you an illustration?

d

If you please.

You know, I said, that dyers, when they want to dye wool for making the true sea-purple, begin by selecting their white color first; this they prepare and dress with much care and pains, in order that the white ground may take the purple hue in full perfection. The dyeing then proceeds; and whatever is dyed in this manner becomes a fast color, and no washing either with lyes or without them can take away the bloom. But, when the ground has not been duly prepared, you will have noticed how poor is the look either of purple or of any other color.

e

Yes, he said; I know that they have a washed-out and ridiculous appearance.

Then now, I said, you will understand what our object was in selecting our soldiers, and educating them in music and gymnastics; we were contriving influences which would prepare them to take the dye of the laws in perfection, and the color of their opinion about dangers and of every other opinion was to be indelibly fixed by their nurture and training, not to be washed away by such potent lyes as pleasure—mightier agent far in washing the soul than any soda or lye; or by sorrow, fear, and desire, the mightiest of all other solvents. And this sort of universal saving power of true opinion in conformity with law about real and false dangers I call and maintain to be courage, unless you disagree.

430
b
/

But I agree, he replied; for I suppose that you mean to exclude mere uninstructed courage, such as that of a wild beast or of a slave—this, in your opinion, is not the courage which the law ordains, and ought to have another name.

Most certainly.

c

Then I may infer courage to be such as you describe?

Why, yes, said I, you may, and if you add the words “of a citizen,” you will not be far wrong—hereafter, if you like, we will carry the examination further, but at present we are seeking, not for courage, but justice; and for the purpose of our inquiry we have said enough.

You are right, he replied.

Two virtues remain to be discovered in the State—first, temperance, and then justice, which is the end of our search.

d

Very true.

Now, can we find justice without troubling ourselves about temperance?

I do not know how that can be accomplished, he said, nor do I desire that justice should be brought to light and temperance lost sight of; and therefore I wish that you would do me the favor of considering temperance first.

Certainly, I replied, I should not be justified in refusing your request.

e

Then consider, he said.

Yes, I replied; I will; and as far as I can at present see, the virtue of temperance has more of the nature of harmony and symphony than the preceding.

How so? he asked.

Temperance, I replied, is the ordering or controlling of certain pleasures and desires; this is curiously enough implied in the saying of “a man being his own master;”dx and other traces of the same notion may be found in language.

No doubt, he said.

There is something ridiculous in the expression “master of himself;” for the master is also the servant and the servant the master; and in all these modes of speaking the same person is denoted.

431

Certainly.

The meaning is, I believe, that in the human soul there is a better and also a worse principle; and when the better has the worse under control, then a man is said to be master of himself; and this is a term of praise: but when, owing to evil education or association, the better principle, which is also the smaller, is overwhelmed by the greater mass of the worse—in this case he is blamed and is called the slave of self and unprincipled.

b

Yes, there is reason in that.

And now, I said, look at our newly created State, and there you will find one of these two conditions realized; for the State, as you will acknowledge, may be justly called master of itself, if the words “temperance” and “self-mastery” truly express the rule of the better part over the worse.

Yes, he said, I see that what you say is true.

Let me further note that the manifold and complex pleasures and desires and pains are generally found in children and women and servants, and in the freemen so called who are of the lowest and more numerous class.

c

Certainly, he said.

Whereas the simple and moderate desires which follow reason, and are under the guidance of mind and true opinion, are to be found only in a few, and those the best born and best educated.

Very true.

These two, as you may perceive, have a place in our State; and the meaner desires of the many are held down by the virtuous desires and wisdom of the few.

d

That I perceive, he said.

Then if there be any city which may be described as master of its own pleasures and desires, and master of itself, ours may claim such a designation?

Certainly, he replied.

It may also be called temperate, and for the same reasons? Yes.

And if there be any State in which rulers and subjects will be agreed as to the question who are to rule, that again will be our State?

e

Undoubtedly.

And the citizens being thus agreed among themselves, in which class will temperance be found—in the rulers or in the subjects?

In both, as I should imagine, he replied.

Do you observe that we were not far wrong in our guess that temperance was a sort of harmony?

Why so?

Why, because temperance is unlike courage and wisdom, each of which resides in a part only, the one making the State wise and the other valiant; not so temperance, which extends to the whole, and runs through all the notes of the scale, and produces a harmony of the weaker and the stronger and the middle class,dy whether you suppose them to be stronger or weaker in wisdom, or power, or numbers, or wealth, or anything else. Most truly then may we deem temperance to be the agreement of the naturally superior and inferior, as to the right to rule of either, both in States and individuals.

432

I entirely agree with you.

b

And so, I said, we may consider three out of the four virtues to have been discovered in our State. The last of those qualities which make a State virtuous must be justice, if we only knew what that was.

The inference is obvious.

The time then has arrived, Glaucon, when, like huntsmen, we should surround the cover, and look sharp that justice does not steal away, and pass out of sight and escape us; for beyond a doubt she is somewhere in this country: watch therefore and strive to catch a sight of her, and if you see her first, let me know.

c

Would that I could! but you should regard me rather as a follower who has just eyes enough to see what you show him—that is about as much as I am good for.

Offer up a prayer with me and follow.

I will, but you must show me the way.

Here is no path, I said, and the wood is dark and perplexing; still we must push on.

Let us push on.

d

Here I saw something: Halloo! I said, I begin to perceive a track, and I believe that the quarry will not escape.

Good news, he said.

Truly, I said, we are stupid fellows.

Why so?

Why, my good sir, at the beginning of our inquiry, ages ago, there was Justice tumbling out at our feet, and we never saw her; nothing could be more ridiculous.7 Like people who go about looking for what they have in their hands—that was the way with us—we looked not at what we were seeking, but at what was far off in the distance; and therefore, I suppose, we missed her.

e

What do you mean?

I mean to say that in reality for a long time past we have been talking of Justice, and have failed to recognize her.

I grow impatient at the length of your exordium.

Well, then, tell me, I said, whether I am right or not: You remember the original principledz which we were always laying down at the foundation of the State, that one man should practise one thing only, the thing to which his nature was best adapted; now justice is this principle or a part of it.

433

Yes, we often said that one man should do one thing only.

Further, we affirmed that Justice was doing one’s own business, and not being a busybody;8 we said so again and again, and many others have said the same to us.

b

Yes, we said so.

Then to do one’s own business in a certain way may be assumed to be justice. Can you tell me whence I derive this inference?

I cannot, but I should like to be told.

Because I think that this is the only virtue which remains in the State when the other virtues of temperance and courage and wisdom are abstracted; and, that this is the ultimate cause and condition of the existence of all of them, and while remaining in them is also their preservative; and we were saying that if the three were discovered by us, justice would be the fourth, or remaining one.

c

That follows of necessity.

If we are asked to determine which of these four qualities by its presence contributes most to the excellence of the State, whether the agreement of rulers and subjects, or the preservation in the soldiers of the opinion which the law ordains about the true nature of dangers, or wisdom and watchfulness in the rulers, or whether this other which I am mentioning, and which is found in children and women, slave and freeman, artisan, ruler, subject—the quality, I mean, of everyone doing his own work, and not being a busybody, would claim the palm—the question is not so easily answered.

d

Certainly, he replied, there would be a difficulty in saying which.

Then the power of each individual in the State to do his own work appears to compete with the other political virtues, wisdom, temperance, courage.

Yes, he said.

And the virtue which enters into this competition is justice?

e

Exactly.

Let us look at the question from another point of view: Are not the rulers in a State those to whom you would intrust the office of determining suits-at-law?

Certainly.

And are suits decided on any other ground but that a man may neither take what is another‘s, nor be deprived of what is his own?

Yes; that is their principle.

Which is a just principle?

Yes.

Then on this view also justice will be admitted to be the having and doing what is a man’s own, and belongs to him?

434

Very true.

Think, now, and say whether you agree with me or not. Suppose a carpenter to be doing the business of a cobbler, or a cobbler of a carpenter; and suppose them to exchange their implements or their duties, or the same person to be doing the work of both, or whatever be the change; do you think that any great harm would result to the State?

Not much.

But when the cobbler or any other man whom nature designed to be a trader, having his heart lifted up by wealth or strength or the number of his followers, or any like advantage, attempts to force his way into the class of warriors, or a warrior into that of legislators and guardians, for which he is unfitted, and either to take the implements or the duties of the other; or when one man is trader, legislator, and warrior all in one, then I think you will agree with me in saying that this interchange and this meddling of one with another is the ruin of the State.

b

Most true.

Seeing, then, I said, that there are three distinct classes, any meddling of one with another, or the change of one into another, is the greatest harm to the State, and may be most justly termed evil-doing?

c

Precisely.

And the greatest degree of evil-doing to one’s own city would be termed by you injustice?

Certainly.

This, then, is injustice; and on the other hand when the trader, the auxiliary, and the guardian each do their own business, that is justice, and will make the city just.

I agree with you.

d

We will not, I said, be over-positive as yet; but if, on trial, this conception of justice be verified in the individual as well as in the State, there will be no longer any room for doubt; if it be not verified, we must have a fresh inquiry. First let us complete the old investigation, which we began, as you remember, under the impression that, if we could previously examine justice on the larger scale, there would be less difficulty in discerning her in the individual. That larger example appeared to be the State, and accordingly we constructed as good a one as we could, knowing well that in the good State justice would be found. Let the discovery which we made be now applied to the individual—if they agree, we shall be satisfied; or, if there be a difference in the individual, we will come back to the State and have another trial of the theory. The friction of the two when rubbed together may possibly strike a light in which justice will shine forth, and the vision which is then revealed we will fix in our souls.

e
435

That will be in regular course; let us do as you say.

I proceeded to ask: When two things, a greater and less, are called by the same name, are they like or unlike in so far as they are called the same?

Like, he replied.

The just man then, if we regard the idea of justice only, will be like the just State?

b

He will.

And a State was thought by us to be just when the three classes in the State severally did their own business; and also thought to be temperate and valiant and wise by reason of certain other affections and qualities of these same classes?

True, he said.

And so of the individual; we may assume that he has the same three principles in his own soul which are found in the State; and he may be rightly described in the same terms, because he is affected in the same manner?9

c

Certainly, he said.

Once more, then, O my friend, we have alighted upon an easy question—whether the soul has these three principles or not?

An easy question! Nay, rather, Socrates, the proverb holds that hard is the good.

Very true, I said; and I do not think that the method which we are employing is at all adequate to the accurate solution of this question;10 the true method is another and a longer one. Still we may arrive at a solution not below the level of the previous inquiry.

d

May we not be satisfied with that? he said; under the circumstances, I am quite content.

I, too, I replied, shall be extremely well satisfied.

Then faint not in pursuing the speculation, he said.

Must we not acknowledge, I said, that in each of us there are the same principles and habits which there are in the State; and that from the individual they pass into the State?—how else can they come there? Take the quality of passion or spirit; it would be ridiculous to imagine that this quality, when found in States, is not derived from the individuals who are supposed to possess it, e.g., the Thracians, Scythians, and in general the Northern nations;11 and the same may be said of the love of knowledge, which is the special characteristic of our part of the world, or of the love of money, which may, with equal truth, be attributed to the Phœnicians and Egyptians.

e

436

Exactly so, he said.

There is no difficulty in understanding this.

None whatever.

But the question is not quite so easy when we proceed to ask whether these principles are three or one; whether, that is to say, we learn with one part of our nature, are angry with another, and with a third part desire the satisfaction of our natural appetites; or whether the whole soul comes into play in each sort of action—to determine that is the difficulty.

b

Yes, he said; there lies the difficulty.

Then let us now try and determine whether they are the same or different.

How can we? he asked.

I replied as follows: The same thing clearly cannot act or be acted upon in the same part or in relation to the same thing at the same time, in contrary ways; and therefore whenever this contradiction occurs in things apparently the same, we know that they are really not the same, but different.

c

Good.

For example, I said, can the same thing be at rest and in motion at the same time in the same part?

Impossible.

Still, I said, let us have a more precise statement of terms, lest we should hereafter fall out by the way. Imagine the case of a man who is standing and also moving his hands and his head, and suppose a person to say that one and the same person is in motion and at rest at the same moment—to such a mode of speech we should object, and should rather say that one part of him is in motion while another is at rest.

d

Very true.

And suppose the objector to refine still further, and to draw the nice distinction that not only parts of tops, but whole tops, when they spin round with their pegs fixed on the spot, are at rest and in motion at the same time (and he may say the same of anything which revolves in the same spot), his objection would not be admitted by us, because in such cases things are not at rest and in motion in the same parts of themselves; we should rather say that they have both an axis and a circumference; and that the axis stands still, for there is no deviation from the perpendicular; and that the circumference goes round. But if, while revolving, the axis inclines either to the right or left, forward or backward, then in no point of view can they be at rest.

e

That is the correct mode of describing them, he replied. Then none of these objections will confuse us, or incline us to believe that the same thing at the same time, in the same part or in relation to the same thing, can act or be acted upon in contrary ways.

437

Certainly not, according to my way of thinking.

Yet, I said, that we may not be compelled to examine all such objections, and prove at length that they are untrue, let us assume their absurdity, and go forward on the understanding that hereafter, if this assumption turn out to be untrue, all the consequences which follow shall be withdrawn.

Yes, he said, that will be the best way.

Well, I said, would you not allow that assent and dissent, desire and aversion, attraction and repulsion, are all of them opposites, whether they are regarded as active or passive (for that makes no difference in the fact of their opposition)?

b

Yes, he said, they are opposites.

Well, I said, and hunger and thirst, and the desires in general, and again willing and wishing—all these you would refer to the classes already mentioned. You would say—would you not?—that the soul of him who desires is seeking after the object of his desire; or that he is drawing to himself the thing which he wishes to possess: or again, when a person wants anything to be given him, his mind, longing for the realization of his desire, intimates his wish to have it by a nod of assent, as if he had been asked a question?

c

Very true.

And what would you say of unwillingness and dislike and the absence of desire; should not these be referred to the opposite class of repulsion and rejection?

Certainly.

d

Since these things are so, shall we say, then, that there is a distinct class of desires in the soul, and that the most conspicuous of these are the ones we call “hunger” and “thirst”?

Let us take that class, he said.

The object of one is food, and of the other drink?

Yes.

And here comes the point: is not thirst the desire which the soul has of drink, and of drink only; not of drink qualified by anything else;12 for example, warm or cold, or much or little, or, in a word, drink of any particular sort: but if the thirst be accompanied by heat, then the desire is of cold drink; or, if accompanied by cold, then of warm drink; or, if the thirst be excessive, then the drink which is desired will be excessive; or, if not great, the quantity of drink will also be small: but thirst pure and simple will desire drink pure and simple, which is the natural satisfaction of thirst, as food is of hunger?

e

Yes, he said; the simple desire is, as you say, in every case of the simple object, and the qualified desire of the qualified object.

But here a confusion may arise; and I should wish to guard against an opponent starting up and saying that no man desires drink only, but good drink, or food only, but good food; for good is the universal object of desire, and thirst being a desire, will necessarily be thirst after good drink; and the same is true of every other desire.

438

Yes, he replied, the opponent might have something to say.

Nevertheless I should still maintain, that of relatives some have a quality attached to either term of the relation; others are simple and have their correlatives simple.

b

I do not know what you mean.

Well, you know of course that the greater is relative to the less?

Certainly.

And the much greater to the much less?

Yes.

And the sometime greater to the sometime less, and the greater that is to be to the less that is to be?

Certainly, he said.

And so of more or less, and of other correlative terms, such as the double and the half, or, again, the heavier and the lighter, the swifter and the slower; and of hot and cold, and of any other relatives; is not this true of all of them?

c

Yes.

And does not the same principle hold in the sciences? The object of science is knowledge (assuming that to be the true definition), but the object of a particular science is a particular kind of knowledge; I mean, for example, that the science of house-building is a kind of knowledge which is defined and distinguished from other kinds and is therefore termed architecture.

d

Certainly.

Because it has a particular quality which no other has?

Yes.

And it has this particular quality because it has an object of a particular kind; and this is true of the other arts and sciences?

Yes.

Now, then, if I have made myself clear, you will understand my original meaning in what I said about relatives. My meaning was, that if one term of a relation is taken alone, the other is taken alone; if one term is qualified, the other is also qualified. I do not mean to say that relatives may not be disparate, or that the science of health is healthy, or of disease necessarily diseased, or that the sciences of good and evil are therefore good and evil; but only that, when the term “science” is no longer used absolutely, but has a qualified object which in this case is the nature of health and disease, it becomes defined, and is hence called not merely science, but the science of medicine.

e

I quite understand, and, I think, as you do.

Would you not say that thirst is one of these essentially relative terms, having clearly a relation—

439

Yes, thirst is relative to drink.

And a certain kind of thirst is relative to a certain kind of drink; but thirst taken alone is neither of much nor little, nor of good nor bad, nor of any particular kind of drink, but of drink only?

Certainly.

Then the soul of the thirsty one, in so far as he is thirsty, desires only drink; for this he yearns and tries to obtain it?

b

That is plain.

And if you suppose something which pulls a thirsty soul away from drink, that must be different from the thirsty principle which draws him like a beast to drink; for, as we were saying, the same thing cannot at the same time with the same part of itself act in contrary ways about the same.

Impossible.

No more than you can say that the hands of the archer push and pull the bow at the same time, but what you say is that one hand pushes and the other pulls.

Exactly so, he replied.

c

And might a man be thirsty, and yet unwilling to drink?

Yes, he said, it constantly happens.

And in such a case what is one to say? Would you not say that there was something in the soul bidding a man to drink, and something else forbidding him, which is other and stronger than the principle which bids him?

I should say so.

And the forbidding principle is derived from reason, and that which bids and attracts proceeds from passion and disease?

d

Clearly.

Then we may fairly assume that they are two, and that they differ from one another; the one with which a man reasons, we may call the rational principle of the soul; the other, with which he loves, and hungers, and thirsts, and feels the flutterings of any other desire, may be termed the irrational or appetitive, the ally of sundry pleasures and satisfactions?

Yes, he said, we may fairly assume them to be different.

e

Then let us accordingly determine that there are two principles existing in the soul. And what of passion, or spirit? Is it a third, or akin to one of the preceding?13

I should be inclined to say—akin to desire.

Well, I said, there is a story which I remember to have heard, and in which I put faith. The story is, that Leontius, the son of Aglaion,ea coming up one day from the Piræus, under the north wall on the outside, observed some dead bodies lying on the ground at the place of execution. He felt a desire to see them, and also a dread and abhorrence of them; for a time he struggled and covered his eyes, but at length the desire got the better of him; and forcing them open, he ran up to the dead bodies, saying, Look, ye wretches, take your fill of the fair sight.

440

I have heard the story myself, he said.

The moral of the tale is, that anger at times goes to war with desire, as though they were two distinct things.

Yes; that is the meaning, he said.

And are there not many other cases in which we observe that when a man’s desires violently prevail over his reason, he reviles himself, and is angry at the violence within him, and that in this struggle, which is like the struggle of factions in a State, his spirit is on the side of his reason; but for the passionate or spirited element to take part with the desires when reason decides that it should not be opposed, is a sort of thing which I believe that you never observed occurring in yourself, nor, as I should imagine, in anyone else?

b

Certainly not.

Suppose that a man thinks he has done a wrong to another, the nobler he is, the less able is he to feel indignant at any suffering, such as hunger, or cold, or any other pain which the injured person may inflict upon him—these he deems to be just, and, as I say, his anger refuses to be excited by them.

c

True, he said.

But when he thinks that he is the sufferer of the wrong, then he boils and chafes, and is on the side of what he believes to be justice; and because he suffers hunger or cold or other pain he is only the more determined to persevere and conquer. His noble spirit will not be quelled until he either slays or is slain; or until he hears the voice of the shepherd, that is, reason, bidding his dog bark no more.

d

The illustration is perfect, he replied; and in our State, as we were saying, the auxiliaries were to be dogs, and to hear the voice of the rulers, who are their shepherds.

I perceive, I said, that you quite understand me; there is, however, a further point which I wish you to consider.

What point?

e

You remember that passion or spirit appeared at first sight to be a kind of desire, but now we should say quite the contrary; for in the conflict of the soul spirit is arrayed on the side of the rational principle.

Most assuredly.

But a further question arises: Is passion different from reason also, or only a kind of reason; in which latter case, instead of three principles in the soul, there will only be two, the rational and the concupiscent; or rather, as the State was composed of three classes, traders, auxiliaries, counsellors, so may there not be in the individual soul a third element which is passion or spirit, and when not corrupted by bad education is the natural auxiliary of reason?

441

Yes, he said, there must be a third.

Yes, I replied, if passion, which has already been shown to be different from desire, turn out also to be different from reason.

But that is easily proved: We may observe even in young children that they are full of spirit almost as soon as they are born, whereas some of them never seem to attain to the use of reason, and most of them late enough.

b

Excellent, I said, and you may see passion equally in brute animals, which is a further proof of the truth of what you are saying. And we may once more appeal to the words of Homer, which have been already quoted by us, for in this verse Homer has clearly supposed the power which reasons about the better and worse to be different from the unreasoning anger which is rebuked by it.

“He smote his breast, and thus rebuked his soul;”eb
c

Very true, he said.

And so, after much tossing, we have reached land, and are fairly agreed that the same principles which exist in the State exist also in the individual, and that they are three in number.

Exactly.

Must we not then infer that the individual is wise in the same way, and in virtue of the same quality which makes the State wise?

Certainly.

Also that the same quality which constitutes courage in the State constitutes courage in the individual, and that both the State and the individual bear the same relation to all the other virtues?

d

Assuredly.

And the individual will be acknowledged by us to be just in the same way in which the State is just?

That follows of course.

We cannot but remember that the justice of the State consisted in each of the three classes doing the work of its own class?

We are not very likely to have forgotten, he said.

We must recollect that the individual in whom the several qualities of his nature do their own work will be just, and will do his own work?

e

Yes, he said, we must remember that too.

And ought not the rational principle, which is wise, and has the care of the whole soul, to rule, and the passionate or spirited principle to be the subject and ally?

Certainly.

And, as we were saying, the united influence of music and gymnastics will bring them into accord, nerving and sustaining the reason with noble words and lessons, and moderating and soothing and civilizing the wildness of passion by harmony and rhythm?

442

Quite true, he said.

And these two, thus nurtured and educated, and having learned truly to know their own functions, will rule over the concupiscent, which in each of us is the largest part of the soul and by nature most insatiable of gain;14 over this they will keep guard, lest, waxing great and strong with the fulness of bodily pleasures, as they are termed, the concupiscent soul, no longer confined to her own sphere, should attempt to enslave and rule those who are not her natural-born subjects, and overturn the whole life of man?

b

Very true, he said.

Both together will they not be the best defenders of the whole soul and the whole body against attacks from without; the one counselling, and the other fighting under his leader, and courageously executing his commands and counsels?

True.

And he is to be deemed courageous whose spirit retains in pleasure and in pain the commands of reason about what he ought or ought not to fear?

c

Right, he replied.

And him we call wise who has in him that little part which rules, and which proclaims these commands; that part too being supposed to have a knowledge of what is for the interest of each of the three parts and of the whole?

Assuredly.

And would you not say that he is temperate who has these same elements in friendly harmony, in whom the one ruling principle of reason, and the two subject ones of spirit and desire, are equally agreed that reason ought to rule, and do not rebel?

d

Certainly, he said, that is the true account of temperance whether in the State or individual.

And surely, I said, we have explained again and again how and by virtue of what quality a man will be just.

That is very certain.

And is justice dimmer in the individual, and is her form different, or is she the same which we found her to be in the State?

There is no difference, in my opinion, he said.

Because, if any doubt is still lingering in our minds, a few commonplace instances will satisfy us of the truth of what I am saying.

e

What sort of instances do you mean?

If the case is put to us, must we not admit that the just State, or the man who is trained in the principles of such a State, will be less likely than the unjust to make away with a deposit of gold or silver? Would anyone deny this?

443

No one, he replied.

Will the just man or citizen ever be guilty of sacrilege or theft, or treachery either to his friends or to his country?

Never.

Neither will he ever break faith where there have been oaths or agreements.

Impossible.

No one will be less likely to commit adultery, or to dishonor his father and mother, or to fail in his religious duties?

No one.

And the reason is that each part of him is doing its own business, whether in ruling or being ruled?

b

Exactly so.

Are you satisfied, then, that the quality which makes such men and such States is justice, or do you hope to discover some other?

Not I, indeed.

Then our dream has been realized; and the suspicion which we entertained at the beginning of our work of construction, that some divine power must have conducted us to a primary form of justice, has now been verified?

c

Yes, certainly.

And the division of labor which required the carpenter and the shoemaker and the rest of the citizens to be doing each his own business, and not another‘s, was a shadow of justice, and for that reason it was of use?

Clearly.

But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned, however, not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man:15 for the just man does not permit the several elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the work of others—he sets in order his own inner life, and is his own master and his own law, and at peace with himself; and when he has bound together the three principles within him, which may be compared to the higher, lower, and middle notes of the scale, and the intermediate intervals—when he has bound all these together, and is no longer many, but has become one entirely temperate and perfectly adjusted nature, then he proceeds to act, if he has to act, whether in a matter of property, or in the treatment of the body, or in some affair of politics or private business; always thinking and calling that which preserves and co-operates with this harmonious condition just and good action, and the knowledge which presides over it wisdom, and that which at any time impairs this condition he will call unjust action, and the opinion which presides over it ignorance.

d
e
444

You have said the exact truth, Socrates.

Very good; and if we were to affirm that we had discovered the just man and the just State, and the nature of justice in each of them, we should not be telling a falsehood?

Most certainly not.

May we say so, then?

Let us say so.

And now, I said, injustice has to be considered.

Clearly.

Must not injustice be a strife which arises among the three principles—a meddlesomeness, and interference,16 and rising up of a part of the soul against the whole, an assertion of unlawful authority, which is made by a rebellious subject against a true prince, of whom he is the natural vassal—what is all this confusion and delusion but injustice, and intemperance, and cowardice, and ignorance, and every form of vice?

b

Exactly so.

And if the nature of justice and injustice be known, then the meaning of acting unjustly and being unjust, or, again, of acting justly, will also be perfectly clear?

c

What do you mean? he said.

Why, I said, they are like disease and health; being in the soul just what disease and health are in the body.17

How so? he said.

Why, I said, that which is healthy causes health, and that which is unhealthy causes disease.

Yes.

And just actions cause justice, and unjust actions cause injustice?

d

That is certain.

And the creation of health is the institution of a natural order and government of one by another in the parts of the body; and the creation of disease is the production of a state of things at variance with this natural order?

True.

And is not the creation of justice the institution of a natural order and government of one by another in the parts of the soul, and the creation of injustice the production of a state of things at variance with the natural order?

Exactly so, he said.

Then virtue is the health, and beauty, and well-being of the soul, and vice the disease, and weakness, and deformity, of the same?

e

True.

And do not good practices lead to virtue, and evil practices to vice?

Assuredly.

Still our old question of the comparative advantage of justice and injustice has not been answered: Which is the more profitable, to be just and act justly and practise virtue, whether seen or unseen of gods and men, or to be unjust and act unjustly, if only unpunished and unreformed?

445

In my judgment, Socrates, the question has now become ridiculous. We know that, when the bodily constitution is gone, life is no longer endurable, though pampered with all kinds of meats and drinks, and having all wealth and all power; and shall we be told that when the very essence of the vital principle is undermined and corrupted, life is still worth having to a man, if only he be allowed to do whatever he likes with the single exception that he is not to acquire justice and virtue, or to escape from injustice and vice; assuming them both to be such as we have described?

Yes, I said, the question is, as you say, ridiculous. Still, as we are near the spot at which we may see the truth in the clearest manner with our own eyes, let us not faint by the way.

b

Certainly not, he replied.

Come up hither, I said, and behold the various forms of vice, those of them, I mean, which are worth looking at.

c

I am following you, he replied: proceed.

I said: The argument seems to have reached a height from which, as from some tower of speculation, a man may look down

d and see that virtue is one, but that the forms of vice are innumerable ; there being four special ones which are deserving of note.

What do you mean? he said.

I mean, I replied, that there appear to be as many forms of the soul as there are distinct forms of the State.

How many?

There are five of the State, and five of the soul, I said.

What are they?

e

The first, I said, is that which we have been describing, and which may be said to have two names, monarchy and aristocracy, according as rule is exercised by one distinguished man or by many.

True, he replied.

But I regard the two names as describing one form only; for whether the government is in the hands of one or many, if the governors have been trained in the manner which we have supposed, the fundamental laws of the State will be maintained.

That is true, he replied.

BOOK 5

SUCH IS THE GOOD and true City or State, and the good and true man is of the same pattern; and if this is right every other is wrong; and the evil is one which affects not only the ordering of the State, but also the regulation of the individual soul, and is exhibited in four forms.

449

What are they? he said.

I was proceeding to tell the order in which the four evil forms appeared to me to succeed one another, when Polemarchus, who was sitting a little way off, just beyond Adeimantus, began to whisper to him:1 stretching forth his hand, he took hold of the upper part of his coat by the shoulder, and drew him toward him, leaning forward himself so as to be quite close and saying something in his ear, of which I only caught the words, “Shall we let him off, or what shall we do?”

b

Certainly not, said Adeimantus, raising his voice.

Who is it, I said, whom you are refusing to let off?

You, he said.

I repeated, Why am I especially not to be let off?

c

Why, he said, we think that you are lazy, and mean to cheat us out of a whole chapter which is a very important part of the story; and you fancy that we shall not notice your airy way of proceeding ; as if it were self-evident to everybody, that in the matter of women and children “friends have all things in common.”ec

And was I not right, Adeimantus?

Yes, he said; but what is right in this particular case, like everything else, requires to be explained; for community may be of many kinds. Please, therefore, to say what sort of community you mean. We have been long expecting that you would tell us something about the family life of your citizens—how they will bring children into the world, and rear them when they have arrived, and, in general, what is the nature of this community of women and children—for we are of opinion that the right or wrong management of such matters will have a great and paramount influence on the State for good or for evil.2 And now, since the question is still undetermined, and you are taking in hand another State, we have resolved, as you heard, not to let you go until you give an account of all this.

d
450

To that resolution, said Glaucon, you may regard me as saying: Agreed.

And without more ado, said Thrasymachus, you may consider us all to be equally agreed.

I said, You know not what you are doing in thus assailing me: What an argument are you raising about the State! Just as I thought that I had finished, and was only too glad that I had laid this question to sleep, and was reflecting how fortunate I was in your acceptance of what I then said, you ask me to begin again at the very foundation, ignorant of what a hornet’s nest of words you are stirring. Now I foresaw this gathering trouble, and avoided it.

b

For what purpose do you conceive that we have come here, said Thrasymachus—to look for gold, or to hear discourse?

Yes, but discourse should have a limit.

Yes, Socrates, said Glaucon, and the whole of life is the only limit which wise men assign to the hearing of such discourses. But never mind about us; take heart yourself and answer the question in your own way: What sort of community of women and children is this which is to prevail among our guardians? and how shall we manage the period between birth and education, which seems to require the greatest care? Tell us how these things will be.

c

Yes, my simple friend, but the answer is the reverse of easy; many more doubts arise about this than about our previous conclusions. For the practicability of what is said may be doubted; and looked at in another point of view, whether the scheme, if ever so practicable, would be for the best, is also doubtful. Hence I feel a reluctance to approach the subject, lest our aspiration, my dear friend, should turn out to be a dream only.

d

Fear not, he replied, for your audience will not be hard upon you; they are not sceptical or hostile.

I said: My good friend, I suppose that you mean to encourage me by these words.

Yes, he said.

Then let me tell you that you are doing just the reverse; the encouragement which you offer would have been all very well had I myself believed that I knew what I was talking about. To declare the truth about matters of high interest which a man honors and loves, among wise men who love him, need occasion no fear or faltering in his mind; but to carry on an argument when you are yourself only a hesitating inquirer, which is my condition, is a dangerous and slippery thing; and the danger is not that I shall be laughed at (of which the fear would be childish), but that I shall miss the truth where I have most need to be sure of my footing, and drag my friends after me in my fall.3 And I pray Nemesised not to visit upon me the words which I am going to utter. For I do indeed believe that to be an involuntary homicide is a less crime than to be a deceiver about beauty, or goodness, or justice, in the matter of laws. And that is a risk which I would rather run among enemies than among friends; and therefore you do well to encourage me.

e
451
b

Glaucon laughed and said: Well, then, Socrates, in case you and your argument do us any serious injury you shall be acquitted beforehand of the homicide, and shall not be held to be a deceiver; take courage then and speak.

Well, I said, the law says that when a man is acquitted he is free from guilt, and what holds at law may hold in argument.

Then why should you mind?

Well, I replied, I suppose that I must retrace my steps and say what I perhaps ought to have said before in the proper place. The part of the men has been played out, and now properly enough comes the turn of the women. Of them I will proceed to speak, and the more readily since I am invited by you.

c

For men born and educated like our citizens, the only way, in my opinion, of arriving at a right conclusion about the possession and use of women and children is to follow the path on which we originally started, when we said that the men were to be the guardians and watch-dogs of the herd.

True.

Let us further suppose the birth and education of our women to be subject to similar or nearly similar regulations; then we shall see whether the result accords with our design.

d

What do you mean?

What I mean may be put into the form of a question, I said: Are dogs divided into he’s and she‘s, or do they both share equally in hunting and in keeping watch and in the other duties of dogs? or do we intrust to the males the entire and exclusive care of the flocks, while we leave the females at home, under the idea that the bearing and the suckling of their puppies are labor enough for them?

No, he said, they share alike; the only difference between them is that the males are stronger and the females weaker.

e

But can you use different animals for the same purpose, unless they are bred and fed in the same way?

You cannot.

Then, if women are to have the same duties as men, they must have the same nurture and education?

Yes.

452

The education which was assigned to the men was music and gymnastics.

Yes.

Then women must be taught music and gymnastics and also the art of war, which they must practise like the men?

That is the inference, I suppose.

I should rather expect, I said, that several of our proposals if they are carried out, being unusual, may appear ridiculous.4

No doubt of it.

Yes, and the most ridiculous thing of all will be the sight of women naked in the palæstra,ee exercising with the men, especially when they are no longer young; they certainly will not be a vision of beauty, any more than the enthusiastic old men who, in spite of wrinkles and ugliness, continue to frequent the gymnasia.

b

Yes, indeed, he said: according to present notions the proposal would be thought ridiculous.

But then, I said, as we have determined to speak our minds, we must not fear the jests of the wits which will be directed against this sort of innovation; how they will talk of women’s attainments, both in music and gymnastics, and above all about their wearing armor and riding upon horseback!

c

Very true, he replied.

Yet, having begun, we must go forward to the rough places of the law; at the same time begging of these gentlemenef for once in their lives to be serious. Not long ago, as we shall remind them, the Hellenes were of the opinion, which is still generally received among the barbarians, that the sight of a naked man was ridiculous and improper; and when first the Cretans, and then the Lacedæmonians, introduced the custom,5 the wits of that day might equally have ridiculed the innovation.

d

No doubt.

But when experience showed that to let all things be uncovered was far better than to cover them up, and the ludicrous effect to the outward eye had vanished before the better principle which reason asserted, then the man was perceived to be a fool who directs the shafts of his ridicule at any other sight but that of folly and vice, or seriously inclines to weigh the beautiful by any other standard but that of the good.

e

Very true, he replied.

First, then, whether the question is to be put in jest or in earnest, let us come to an understanding about the nature of woman: Is she capable of sharing either wholly or partially in the actions of men, or not at all? And is the art of war one of those arts in which she can or cannot share? That will be the best way of commencing the inquiry, and will probably lead to the fairest conclusion.

453

That will be much the best way.

Shall we take the other side first and begin by arguing against ourselves? in this manner the adversary’s position will not be undefended.

Why not? he said.

b

Then let us put a speech into the mouths of our opponents. They will say: “Socrates and Glaucon, no adversary need convict you, for you yourselves, at the first foundation of the State, admitted the principle that everybody was to do the one work suited to his own nature.” And certainly, if I am not mistaken, such an admission was made by us. “And do not the natures of men and women differ very much indeed?” And we shall reply, Of course they do. Then we shall be asked, “Whether the tasks assigned to men and to women should not be different, and such as are agreeable to their different natures?” Certainly they should. “But if so, have you not fallen into a serious inconsistency in saying that men and women, whose natures are so entirely different, ought to perform the same actions?” What defence will you make for us, my good sir, against anyone who offers these objections?

c

That is not an easy question to answer when asked suddenly; and I shall and I do beg of you to draw out the case on our side.

These are the objections, Glaucon, and there are many others of a like kind, which I foresaw long ago; they made me afraid and reluctant to take in hand any law about the possession and nurture of women and children.

d

By Zeus, he said, the problem to be solved is anything but easy.

Why, yes, I said, but the fact is that when a man is out of his depth, whether he has fallen into a little swimming-bath or into mid-ocean, he has to swim all the same.

Very true.

And must not we swim and try to reach the shore—we will hope that Arion’s dolphineg or some other miraculous help may save us?

I suppose so, he said.

e

Well, then, let us see if any way of escape can be found. We acknowledged—did we not?—that different natures ought to have different pursuits, and that men’s and women’s natures are different. And now what are we saying?—that different natures ought to have the same pursuits—this is the inconsistency which is charged upon us.

Precisely.

Verily, Glaucon, I said, glorious is the power of the art of contradiction! 6

454

Why do you say so?

Because I think that many a man falls into the practice against his will. When he thinks that he is reasoning he is really disputing, just because he cannot define and divide, and so know that of which he is speaking; and he will pursue a merely verbal opposition in the spirit of contention and not of fair discussion.

Yes, he replied, such is very often the case; but what has that to do with us and our argument?

A great deal; for there is certainly a danger of our getting unintentionally into a verbal opposition.

b

In what way?

Why we valiantly and pugnaciously insist upon the verbal truth, that different natures ought to have different pursuits, but we never considered at all what was the meaning of sameness or difference of nature, or why we distinguished them when we assigned different pursuits to different natures and the same to the same natures.

Why, no, he said, that was never considered by us.

I said: Suppose that by way of illustration we were to ask the question whether there is not an opposition in nature between bald men and hairy men; and if this is admitted by us, then, if bald men are cobblers, we should forbid the hairy men to be cobblers, and conversely?

c

That would be a jest, he said.

Yes, I said, a jest; and why? because we never meant when we constructed the State, that the opposition of natures should extend to every difference, but only to those differences which affected the pursuit in which the individual is engaged; we should have argued, for example, that a physician and one who is in mind a physician may be said to have the same nature.7

d

True.

e

Whereas the physician and the carpenter have different natures?

Certainly.

And if, I said, the male and female sex appear to differ in their fitness for any art or pursuit, we should say that such pursuit or art ought to be assigned to one or the other of them; but if the difference consists only in women bearing and men begetting children, this does not amount to a proof that a woman differs from a man in respect of the sort of education she should receive;8 and we shall therefore continue to maintain that our guardians and their wives ought to have the same pursuits.

455

Very true, he said.

Next, we shall ask our opponent how, in reference to any of the pursuits or arts of civic life, the nature of a woman differs from that of a man?

b

That will be quite fair.

And perhaps he, like yourself, will reply that to give a sufficient answer on the instant is not easy; but after a little reflection there is no difficulty.

Yes, perhaps.

Suppose then that we invite him to accompany us in the argument, and then we may hope to show him that there is nothing peculiar in the constitution of women which would affect them in the administration of the State.

c

By all means.

Let us say to him: Come now, and we will ask you a question: When you spoke of a nature gifted or not gifted in any respect, did you mean to say that one man will acquire a thing easily, another with difficulty; a little learning will lead the one to discover a great deal, whereas the other, after much study and application, no sooner learns than he forgets; or again, did you mean, that the one has a body which is a good servant to his mind, while the body of the other is a hinderance to him?—would not these be the sort of differences which distinguish the man gifted by nature from the one who is ungifted?

No one will deny that.

And can you mention any pursuit of mankind in which the male sex has not all these gifts and qualities in a higher degree than the female? Need I waste time in speaking of the art of weaving, and the management of pancakes and preserves, in which womankind does really appear to be great, and in which for her to be beaten by a man is of all things the most absurd?

d

You are quite right, he replied, in maintaining the general inferiority of the female sex: although many women are in many things superior to many men, yet on the whole what you say is true.

And if so, my friend, I said, there is no special faculty of administration in a State which a woman has because she is a woman, or which a man has by virtue of his sex, but the gifts of nature are alike diffused in both; all the pursuits of men are the pursuits of women also, but in all of them a woman is inferior to a man.

e

Very true.

Then are we to impose all our enactments on men and none of them on women?

That will never do.

One woman has a gift of healing, another not; one is a musician, and another has no music in her nature?

Very true.

And one woman has a turn for gymnastic and military exercises, and another is unwarlike and hates gymnastics?

456

Certainly.

And one woman is a philosopher, and another is an enemy of philosophy; one has spirit, and another is without spirit?

That is also true.

Then one woman will have the temper of a guardian, and another not. Was not the selection of the male guardians determined by differences of this sort?

Yes.

Men and women alike possess the qualities which make a guardian; they differ only in their comparative strength or weakness.

Obviously.

And those women who have such qualities are to be selected as the companions and colleagues of men who have similar qualities and whom they resemble in capacity and in character?

b

Very true.

And ought not the same natures to have the same pursuits?

They ought.

Then, as we were saying before, there is nothing unnatural in assigning music and gymnastics to the wives of the guardians—to that point we come round again.

Certainly not.

The law which we then enacted was agreeable to nature, and therefore not an impossibility or mere aspiration; and the contrary practice, which prevails at present, is in reality a violation of nature.

c

That appears to be true.

We had to consider, first, whether our proposals were possible, and secondly whether they were the most beneficial?

Yes.

And the possibility has been acknowledged?

Yes.

The very great benefit has next to be established?

Quite so.

You will admit that the same education which makes a man a good guardian will make a woman a good guardian; for their original nature is the same?

d

Yes.

I should like to ask you a question.

What is it?

Would you say that all men are equal in excellence, or is one man better than another?

The latter.

And in the commonwealth which we were founding do you conceive the guardians who have been brought up on our model system to be more perfect men, or the cobblers whose education has been cobbling?

What a ridiculous question!

You have answered me, I replied: Well, and may we not further say that our guardians are the best of our citizens?

e

By far the best.

And will not their wives be the best women?

Yes, by far the best.

And can there be anything better for the interests of the State than that the men and women of a State should be as good as possible?

There can be nothing better.

And this is what the arts of music and gymnastics, when present in such a manner as we have described, will accomplish?

457

Certainly.

Then we have made an enactment not only possible but in the highest degree beneficial to the State?

True.

Then let the wives of our guardians strip, for their virtue will be their robe, and let them share in the toils of war and the defence of their country; only in the distribution of labors the lighter are to be assigned to the women, who are the weaker natures, but in other respects their duties are to be the same. And as for the man who laughs at naked women exercising their bodies from the best of motives, in his laughter he is plucking and he himself is ignorant of what he is laughing at, or what he is about; for that is, and ever will be, the best of sayings, “that the useful is the noble, and the hurtful is the base.”

b
“A fruit of unripe wisdom,”eh

Very true.

Here, then, is one difficulty in our law about women, which we may say that we have now escaped; the wave has not swallowed us up alive for enacting that the guardians of either sex should have all their pursuits in common; to the utility and also to the possibility of this arrangement the consistency of the argument with itself bears witness.

c

Yes, that was a mighty wave which you have escaped.9

Yes, I said, but a greater is coming; you will not think much of this when you see the next.

Go on; let me see.

The law, I said, which is the sequel of this and of all that has preceded, is to the following effect, “that the wives of our guardians are to be common, and their children are to be common, and no parent is to know his own child, nor any child his parent.”

d

Yes, he said, that is a much greater wave than the other; and the possibility as well as the utility of such a law are far more questionable.

I do not think, I said, that there can be any dispute about the very great utility of having wives and children in common; the possibility is quite another matter, and will be very much disputed.

I think that a good many doubts may be raised about both.

e

You imply that the two questions must be combined, I replied.

Now I meant that you should admit the utility; and in this way, as I thought, I should escape from one of them, and then there would remain only the possibility.

But that little attempt is detected, and therefore you will please to give a defence of both.

Well, I said, I submit to my fate. Yet grant me a little favor: let me feast my mind with the dream as day-dreamers are in the habit of feasting themselves when they are walking alone; for before they have discovered any means of effecting their wishes—that is a matter which never troubles them—they would rather not tire themselves by thinking about possibilities; but assuming that what they desire is already granted to them, they proceed with their plan, and delight in detailing what they mean to do when their wish has come true—that is a way which they have of not doing much good to a capacity which was never good for much. Now I myself am beginning to lose heart, and I should like, with your permission, to pass over the question of possibility at present. Assuming therefore the possibility of the proposal, I shall now proceed to inquire how the rulers will carry out these arrangements, and I shall demonstrate that our plan, if executed, will be of the greatest benefit to the State and to the guardians. First of all, then, if you have no objection, I will endeavor with your help to consider the advantages of the measure; and hereafter the question of possibility.

458
b

I have no objection; proceed.

First, I think that if our rulers and their auxiliaries are to be worthy of the name which they bear, there must be willingness to obey in the one and the power of command in the other; the guardians themselves must obey the laws, and they must also imitate the spirit of them in any details which are intrusted to their care.

c

That is right, he said.

You, I said, who are their legislator, having selected the men, will now select the women and give them to them; they must be as far as possible of like natures with them; and they must live in common houses and meet at common meals. None of them will have anything specially his or her own; they will be together, and will be brought up together, and will associate at gymnastic exercises. And so they will be drawn by a necessity of their natures to have intercourse with each other—necessity is not too strong a word, I think?

d

Yes, he said; necessity, not geometrical, but another sort of necessity which lovers know, and which is far more convincing and constraining to the mass of mankind.10

True, I said; and this, Glaucon, like all the rest must proceed after an orderly fashion; in a city of the blessed,ei licentiousness is an unholy thing which the rulers will forbid.

e

Yes, he said, and it ought not to be permitted.

Then clearly the next thing will be to make matrimony sacred in the highest degree,11 and what is most beneficial will be deemed sacred?

Exactly.

And how can marriages be made most beneficial? that is a question which I put to you, because I see in your house dogs for hunting, and of the nobler sort of birds not a few. Now, I beseech you, do tell me, have you ever attended to their pairing and breeding?

459

In what particulars?

Why, in the first place, although they are all of a good sort, are not some better than others?

True.

And do you breed from them all indifferently, or do you take care to breed from the best only?

From the best.

And do you take the oldest or the youngest, or only those of ripe age?

b

I choose only those of ripe age.

And if care was not taken in the breeding, your dogs and birds would greatly deteriorate?

Certainly.

And the same of horses and of animals in general?

Undoubtedly.

Good heavens! my dear friend, I said, what consummate skill will our rulers need if the same principle holds of the human species!

Certainly, the same principle holds; but why does this involve any particular skill ?

c

Because, I said, our rulers will often have to practise upon the body corporate with medicines. Now you know that when patients do not require medicines, but have only to be put under a regimen, the inferior sort of practitioner is deemed to be good enough; but when medicine has to be given, then the doctor should be more of a man.

That is quite true, he said; but to what are you alluding?

I mean, I replied, that our rulers will find a considerable dose of falsehood and deceit necessary for the good of their subjects: we were saying that the use of all these things regarded as medicines might be of advantage.12

d

And we were very right.

And this lawful use of them seems likely to be often needed in the regulations of marriages and births.

How so?

Why, I said, the principle has been already laid down that the best of either sex should be united with the best as often, and the inferior with the inferior as seldom, as possible; and that they should rear the offspring of the one sort of union, but not of the other, if the flock is to be maintained in first-rate condition. Now these goings on must be a secret which the rulers only know, or there will be a further danger of our herd, as the guardians may be termed, breaking out into rebellion.

e

Very true.

Had we better not appoint certain festivals at which we will bring together the brides and bridegrooms, and sacrifices will be offered and suitable wedding songs composed by our poets: the number of weddings is a matter which must be left to the discretion of the rulers, whose aim will be to preserve the average of population? There are many other things which they will have to consider, such as the effects of wars and diseases and any similar agencies, in order as far as this is possible to prevent the State from becoming either too large or too small.

460

Certainly, he replied.

We shall have to invent some ingenious kind of lots which the less worthy may draw on each occasion of our bringing them together, and then they will accuse their own ill-luck and not the rulers.

To be sure, he said.

And I think that our braver and better youth, besides their other honors and rewards, might have greater facilities of intercourse with women given them; their bravery will be a reason, and such fathers ought to have as many sons as possible.

b

True.

And the proper officers, whether male or female or both, for offices are to be held by women as well as by men—

Yes—

The proper officers will take the offspring of the good parents to the pen or fold, and there they will deposit them with certain nurses who dwell in a separate quarter; but the offspring of the inferior, or of the better when they chance to be deformed, will be put away in some mysterious, unknown place, as they should be.13

c

Yes, he said, that must be done if the breed of the guardians is to be kept pure.

They will provide for their nurture, and will bring the mothers to the fold when they are full of milk, taking the greatest possible care that no mother recognizes her own child; and other wet-nurses may be engaged if more are required. Care will also be taken that the process of suckling shall not be protracted too long; and the mothers will have no getting up at night or other trouble, but will hand over all this sort of thing to the nurses and attendants.

d

You suppose the wives of our guardians to have a fine easy time of it when they are having children.

Why, said I, and so they ought. Let us, however, proceed with our scheme. We were saying that the parents should be in the prime of life?

Very true.

And what is the prime of life? May it not be defined as a period of about twenty years in a woman’s life, and thirty years in a man‘s?

e

Which years do you mean to include?

A woman, I said, at twenty years of age may begin to bear children to the State, and continue to bear them until forty;14 a man may begin at five-and-twenty, when he has passed the point at which the pulse of life beats quickest, and continue to beget children until he be fifty-five.

Certainly, he said, both in men and women those years are the prime of physical as well as of intellectual vigor.

461

Anyone above or below the prescribed ages who takes part in the public hymeneals shall be said to have done an unholy and unrighteous thing; the child of which he is the father, if it steals into life, will have been conceived under auspices very unlike the sacrifices and prayers, which at each hymeneal priestesses and priests and the whole city will offer, that the new generation may be better and more useful than their good and useful parents, whereas his child will be the offspring of darkness and strange lust.

b

Very true, he replied.

And the same law will apply to any one of those within the prescribed age who forms a connection with any woman in the prime of life without the sanction of the rulers; for we shall say that he is raising up a bastard to the State, uncertified and unconsecrated.

Very true, he replied.

This applies, however, only to those who are within the specified age: after that we will allow them to range at will, except that a man may not marry his daughter or his daughter’s daughter, or his mother or his mother’s mother; and women, on the other hand, are prohibited from marrying their sons or fathers, or son’s son or father’s father, and so on in either direction. And we grant all this, accompanying the permission with strict orders to prevent any embryo which may come into being from seeing the light; and if any force a way to the birth, the parents must understand that the offspring of such a union cannot be maintained, and arrange accordingly.

c

That also, he said, is a reasonable proposition. But how will they know who are fathers and daughters, and so on?

d

They will never know. The way will be this: dating from the day of the hymeneal, the bridegroom who was then married will call all the male children who are born in the seventh and the tenth monthej afterward his sons, and the female children his daughters, and they will call him father, and he will call their children his grandchildren, and they will call the elder generation grandfathers and grandmothers. All who were begotten at the time when their fathers and mothers came together will be called their brothers and sisters, and these, as I was saying, will be forbidden to intermarry. This, however, is not to be understood as an absolute prohibition of the marriage of brothers and sisters; if the lot favors them, and they receive the sanction of the Pythian oracle,ek the law will allow them.

e

Quite right, he replied.

Such is the scheme, Glaucon, according to which the guardians of our State are to have their wives and families in common. And now you would have the argument show that this community is consistent with the rest of our polity, and also that nothing can be better—would you not?

462

Yes, certainly.

Shall we try to find a common basis by asking of ourselves what ought to be the chief aim of the legislator in making laws and in the organization of a State—what is the greatest good, and what is the greatest evil, and then consider whether our previous description has the stamp of the good or of the evil?

By all means.

Can there be any greater evil than discord and distraction and plurality where unity ought to reign? or any greater good than the bond of unity?

b

There cannot.

And there is unity where there is community of pleasures and pains—where all the citizens are glad or grieved on the same occasions of joy and sorrow?

No doubt.

Yes; and where there is no common but only private feeling a State is disorganized—when you have one-half of the world triumphing and the other plunged in grief at the same events happening to the city or the citizens?

c

Certainly.

Such differences commonly originate in a disagreement about the use of the terms “mine” and “not mine,” “his” and “not his.”

Exactly so.

And is not that the best-ordered State in which the greatest number of persons apply the terms “mine” and “not mine” in the same way to the same thing?15

Quite true.

Or that again which most nearly approaches to the condition of the individual—as in the body, when but a finger of one of us is hurt, the whole frame, drawn toward the soul as a centre and forming one kingdom under the ruling power therein, feels the hurt and sympathizes all together with the part affected, and we say that the man has a pain in his finger; and the same expression is used about any other part of the body, which has a sensation of pain at suffering or of pleasure at the alleviation of suffering.

d

Very true, he replied; and I agree with you that in the best-ordered State there is the nearest approach to this common feeling which you describe.

Then when any one of the citizens experiences any good or evil, the whole State will make his case their own, and will either rejoice or sorrow with him?

e

Yes, he said, that is what will happen in a well-ordered State.

It will now be time, I said, for us to return to our State and see whether this or some other form is most in accordance with these fundamental principles.

Very good.

Our State, like every other, has rulers and subjects?

463

True.

All of whom will call one another citizens?

Of course.

But is there not another name which people give to their rulers in other States?

Generally they call them masters, but in democratic States they simply call them rulers.

And in our State what other name besides that of citizens do the people give the rulers?

They are called saviours and helpers, he replied.

b

And what do the rulers call the people?

Their maintainers and foster-fathers.

And what do they call them in other States?

Slaves.

And what do the rulers call one another in other States?

Fellow-rulers.

And what in ours?

Fellow-guardians.

Did you ever know an example in any other State of a ruler who would speak of one of his colleagues as his friend and of another as not being his friend?

Yes, very often.

And the friend he regards and describes as one in whom he has an interest, and the other as a stranger in whom he has no interest?

c

Exactly.

But would any of your guardians think or speak of any other guardian as a stranger?

Certainly he would not; for everyone whom they meet will be regarded by them either as a brother or sister, or father or mother, or son or daughter, or as the child or parent of those who are thus connected with him.

Capital, I said; but let me ask you once more: Shall they be a family in name only; or shall they in all their actions be true to the name? For example, in the use of the word “father,” would the care of a father be implied and the filial reverence and duty and obedience to him which the law commands; and is the violator of these duties to be regarded as an impious and unrighteous person who is not likely to receive much good either at the hands of God or of man? Are these to be or not to be the strains which the children will hear repeated in their ears by all the citizens about those who are intimated to them to be their parents and the rest of their kinsfolk?

d

These, he said, and none other; for what can be more ridiculous than for them to utter the names of family ties with the lips only and not to act in the spirit of them?

e

Then in our city the language of harmony and concord will be more often heard than in any other. As I was describing before, when anyone is well or ill, the universal word will be “with me it is well” or “it is ill.”

Most true.

And agreeably to this mode of thinking and speaking, were we not saying that they will have their pleasures and pains in common?

464

Yes, and so they will.

And they will have a common interest in the same thing which they will alike call “my own,” and having this common interest they will have a common feeling of pleasure and pain?

Yes, far more so than in other States.

And the reason of this, over and above the general constitution of the State, will be that the guardians will have a community of women and children?

That will be the chief reason.

And this unity of feeling we admitted to be the greatest good, as was implied in our comparison of a well-ordered State to the relation of the body and the members, when affected by pleasure or pain?

b

That we acknowledged, and very rightly.

Then the community of wives and children among our citizens is clearly the source of the greatest good to the State?

Certainly.

And this agrees with the other principle which we were affirming—that the guardians were not to have houses or lands or any other property; their pay was to be their food, which they were to receive from the other citizens, and they were to have no private expenses; for we intended them to preserve their true character of guardians.

Right, he replied.

c

Both the community of property and the community of families, as I am saying, tend to make them more truly guardians; they will not tear the city in pieces by differing about “mine” and “not mine;” each man dragging any acquisition which he has made into a separate house of his own, where he has a separate wife and children and private pleasures and pains; but all will be affected as far as may be by the same pleasures and pains because they are all of one opinion about what is near and dear to them, and therefore they all tend toward a common end.

d

Certainly, he replied.

And as they have nothing but their persons which they can call their own, suits and complaints will have no existence among them; they will be delivered from all those quarrels of which money or children or relations are the occasion.

e

Of course they will.

Neither will trials for assault or insult ever be likely to occur among them. For that equals should defend themselves against equals we shall maintain to be honorable and right; we shall compel them to care for their bodies.

That is good, he said.

Yes; and there is a further good in the law; viz., that if a man has a quarrel with another he will satisfy his resentment then and there, and not proceed to more dangerous lengths.

465

Certainly.

To the elder shall be assigned the duty of ruling and chastising the younger.

Clearly.

Nor can there be a doubt that the younger will not strike or do any other violence to an elder, unless the magistrates command him; nor will he slight him in any way. For there are two guardians, shame and fear, mighty to prevent him: shame, which makes men refrain from laying hands on those who are to them in the relation of parents; fear, that the injured one will be succored by the others who are his brothers, sons, fathers.

b

That is true, he replied.

Then in every way the laws will help the citizens to keep the peace with one another?

Yes, there will be no want of peace.

And as the guardians will never quarrel among themselves there will be no danger of the rest of the city being divided either against them or against one another.

None whatever.

I hardly like even to mention the little meannesses of which they will be rid, for they are beneath notice: such, for example, as the flattery of the rich by the poor, and all the pains and pangs which men experience in bringing up a family, and in finding money to buy necessaries for their household, borrowing and then repudiating, getting how they can, and giving the money into the hands of women and slaves to keep—the many evils of so many kinds which people suffer in this way are mean enough and obvious enough, and not worth speaking of.

c

Yes, he said, a man has no need of eyes in order to perceive that.

d

And trom all these evils they will be delivered, and their life will be blessed as the life of Olympic victors and yet more blessed.

How so?

The Olympic victor, I said, is deemed happy in receiving a part only of the blessedness which is secured to our citizens, who have won a more glorious victory and have a more complete maintenance at the public cost.16 For the victory which they have won is the salvation of the whole State; and the crown with which they and their children are crowned is the fulness of all that life needs; they receive rewards from the hands of their country while living, and after death have an honorable burial.

e

Do you remember, I said, how in the course of the previous discussion someone who shall be nameless accused us of making our guardians unhappy—they had nothing and might have possessed all things—to whom we replied that, if an occasion offered, we might perhaps hereafter consider this question, but that, as at present divided, we would make our guardians truly guardians, and that we were fashioning the State with a view to the greatest happiness, not of any particular class, but of the whole?

466

Yes, I remember.

And what do you say, now that the life of our protectors is made out to be far better and nobler than that of Olympic victors—is the life of shoemakers, or any other artisans, or of husbandmen, to be compared with it?

b

Certainly not.

At the same time I ought here to repeat what I have said elsewhere, that if any of our guardians shall try to be happy in such a manner that he will cease to be a guardian, and is not content with this safe and harmonious life, which, in our judgment, is of all lives the best, but, infatuated by some youthful conceit of happiness which gets up into his head shall seek to appropriate the whole State to himself, then he will have to learn how wisely Hesiod spoke, when he said, “half is more than the whole.”el

c

If he were to consult me, I should say to him: Stay where you are, when you have the offer of such a life.

You agree then, I said, that men and women are to have a common way of life such as we have described—common education, common children; and they are to watch over the citizens in common whether abiding in the city or going out to war; they are to keep watch together, and to hunt together like dogs; and always and in all things, as far as they are able, women are to share with the men? And in so doing they will do what is best, and will not violate, but preserve, the natural relation of the sexes.

d

I agree with you, he replied.

The inquiry, I said, has yet to be made, whether such a community will be found possible—as among other animals, so also among men—and if possible, in what way possible?17

You have anticipated the question which I was about to suggest.

There is no difficulty, I said, in seeing how war will be carried on by them.

How?

Why, of course they will go on expeditions together; and will take with them any of their children who are strong enough, that, after the manner of the artisan’s child, they may look on at the work which they will have to do when they are grown up; and besides looking on they will have to help and be of use in war, and to wait upon their fathers and mothers. Did you never observe in the arts how the potters’ boys look on and help, long before they touch the wheel?

467

Yes, I have.

And shall potters be more careful in educating their children and in giving them the opportunity of seeing and practising their duties than our guardians will be?

The idea is ridiculous, he said.

There is also the effect on the parents, with whom, as with other animals, the presence of their young ones will be the greatest incentive to valor.

b

That is quite true, Socrates; and yet if they are defeated, which may often happen in war, how great the danger is! the children will be lost as well as their parents, and the State will never recover.

True, I said; but would you never allow them to run any risk?

I am far from saying that.

Well, but if they are ever to run a risk should they not do so on some occasion when, if they escape disaster, they will be the better for it?

Clearly.

Whether the future soldiers do or do not see war in the days of their youth is a very important matter, for the sake of which some risk may fairly be incurred.

c

Yes, very important.

This then must be our first step—to make our children spectators of war; but we must also contrive that they shall be secured against danger; then all will be well.

True.

Their parents may be supposed not to be blind to the risks of war, but to know, as far as human foresight can, what expeditions are safe and what dangerous?

d

That may be assumed.

And they will take them on the safe expeditions and be cautious about the dangerous ones?

True.

And they will place them under the command of experienced veterans who will be their leaders and teachers?

Very properly.

Still, the dangers of war cannot be always foreseen; there is a good deal of chance about them?

rue.

Then against such chances the children must be at once furnished with wings, in order that in the hour of need they may fly away and escape.

What do you mean? he said.

e

I mean that we must mount them on horses in their earliest youth, and when they have learnt to ride, take them on horseback to see war: the horses must not be spirited and warlike, but the most tractable and yet the swiftest that can be had. In this way they will get an excellent view of what is hereafter to be their own business; and if there is danger they have only to follow their elder leaders and escape.

I believe that you are right, he said.

Next, as to war; what are to be the relations of your soldiers to one another and to their enemies? I should be inclined to propose that the soldier who leaves his rank or throws away his arms, or is guilty of any other act of cowardice, should be degraded into the rank of a husbandman or artisan. What do you think?

468

By all means, I should say.

And he who allows himself to be taken prisoner may as well be made a present of to his enemies; he is their lawful prey, and let them do what they like with him.

Certainly.

b

But the hero who has distinguished himself, what shall be done to him? In the first place, he shall receive honor in the army from his youthful comrades; every one of them in succession shall crown him.em What do you say?

I approve.

And what do you say to his receiving the right hand of fellowship?

To that too, I agree.

But you will hardly agree to my next proposal.

What is your proposal?

That he should kiss and be kissed by them.

Most certainly, and I should be disposed to go further, and say: Let no one whom he has a mind to kiss refuse to be kissed by him while the expedition lasts. So that if there be a lover in the army, whether his love be youth or maiden, he may be more eager to win the prize of valor.

c

Capital, I said. That the brave man is to have more wives than others has been already determined: and he is to have first choices in such matters more than others, in order that he may have as many children as possible?

Agreed.

Again, there is another manner in which, according to Homer, brave youths should be honored; for he tells how Ajax, after he had distinguished himself in battle, was rewarded with long chines,en which seems to be a compliment appropriate to a hero in the flower of his age, being not only a tribute of honor but also a very strengthening thing.

d

Most true, he said.

Then in this, I said, Homer shall be our teacher; and we too, at sacrifices and on the like occasions, will honor the brave according to the measure of their valor, whether men or women, with hymns and those other distinctions which we were mentioning; also with and in honoring them, we shall be at the same time training them.

“seats of precedence, and meats and full cups;”eo

That, he replied, is excellent.

e

Yes, I said; and when a man dies gloriously in war shall we not say, in the first place, that he is of the golden race?

To be sure.

Nay, have we not the authority of Hesiod for affirming that when they are dead

469
“They are holy angels upon the earth, authors of good, averters of evil, the guardians of speech-gifted men”?ep

Yes; and we accept his authority.

We must learn of the godeq now we are to order the sepulture of divine and heroic personages, and what is to be their special distinction ; and we must do as he bids?

By all means.

And in ages to come we will reverence them and kneel before their sepulchres as at the graves of heroes. And not only they, but any who are deemed pre-eminently good, whether they die from age or in any other way, shall be admitted to the same honors.

b

That is very right, he said.

Next, how shall our soldiers treat their enemies? What about this?

In what respect do you mean?

First of all, in regard to slavery? Do you think it right that Hellenes should enslave Hellenic States, or allow others to enslave them, if they can help?18 Should not their custom be to spare them, considering the danger which there is that the whole race may one day fall under the yoke of the barbarians?

c

To spare them is infinitely better.

Then no Hellene should be owned by them as a slave; that is a rule which they will observe and advise the other Hellenes to observe.

Certainly, he said; they will in this way be united against the barbarians and will keep their hands off one another.

Next as to the slain; ought the conquerors, I said, to take anything but their armor? Does not the practice of despoiling an enemy afford an excuse for not facing the battle? Cowards skulk about the dead, pretending that they are fulfilling a duty, and many an army before now has been lost from this love of plunder.

d

Very true.

And is there not illiberality and avarice in robbing a corpse,19 and also a degree of meanness and womanishness in making an enemy of the dead body when the real enemy has flown away and left only his fighting gear behind him—is not this rather like a dog who cannot get at his assailant, quarrelling with the stones which strike him instead?

e

Very like a dog, he said.

Then we must abstain from spoiling the dead or hindering their burial?

Yes, he replied, we most certainly must.

Neither shall we offer up arms at the temples of the gods, least of all the arms of Hellenes, if we care to maintain good feeling with other Hellenes; and, indeed, we have reason to fear that the offering of spoils taken from kinsmen may be a pollution unless commanded by the god himself?

470

Very true.

Again, as to the devastation of Hellenic territory or the burning of houses, what is to be the practice?

May I have the pleasure, he said, of hearing your opinion?

Both should be forbidden, in my judgment; I would take the annual produce and no more. Shall I tell you why?

b

Pray do.

Why, you see, there is a difference in the names “discord” and “war,” and I imagine that there is also a difference in their natures; the one is expressive of what is internal and domestic, the other of what is external and foreign; and the first of the two is termed discord, and only the second, war.

That is a very proper distinction, he replied.

And may I not observe with equal propriety that the Hellenic race is all united together by ties of blood and friendship, and alien and strange to the barbarians?

c

Very good, he said.

And therefore when Hellenes fight with barbarians, and barbarians with Hellenes, they will be described by us as being at war when they fight, and by nature enemies, and this kind of antagonism should be called war; but when Hellenes fight with one another we shall say that Hellas is then in a state of disorder and discord,20 they being by nature friends; and such enmity is to be called discord.

d

I agree.

Consider then, I said, when that which we have acknowledged to be discord occurs, and a city is divided, if both parties destroy the lands and burn the houses of one another, how wicked does the strife appear! No true lover of his country would bring himself to tear in pieces his own nurse and mother: There might be reason in the conqueror depriving the conquered of their harvest, but still they would have the idea of peace in their hearts, and would not mean to go on fighting forever.

e

Yes, he said, that is a better temper than the other.

And will not the city, which you are founding, be an Hellenic city?

It ought to be, he replied.

Then will not the citizens be good and civilized?

Yes, very civilized.

And will they not be lovers of Hellas, and think of Hellas as their own land, and share in the common temples?

Most certainly.

And any difference which arises among them will be regarded by them as discord only—a quarrel among friends, which is not to be called a war?

471

Certainly not.

Then they will quarrel as those who intend some day to be reconciled?

Certainly.

They will use friendly correction, but will not enslave or destroy their opponents; they will be correctors, not enemies?

Just so.

And as they are Hellenes themselves they will not devastate Hellas, nor will they burn houses, nor ever suppose that the whole population of a city—men, women, and children—are equally their enemies, for they know that the guilt of war is always confined to a few persons and that the many are their friends. And for all these reasons they will be unwilling to waste their lands and raze their houses; their enmity to them will only last until the many innocent sufferers have compelled the guilty few to give satisfaction?

b

I agree, he said, that our citizens should thus deal with their Hellenic enemies; and with barbarians as the Hellenes now deal with one another.

Then let us enact this law also for our guardians: that they are neither to devastate the lands of Hellenes nor to burn their houses.

c

Agreed; and we may agree also in thinking that these, like all our previous enactments, are very good.

But still I must say, Socrates, that if you are allowed to go on in this way you will entirely forget the other question which at the commencement of this discussion you thrust aside: Is such an order of things possible, and how, if at all?21 For I am quite ready to acknowledge that the plan which you propose, if only feasible, would do all sorts of good to the State. I will add, what you have omitted, that your citizens will be the bravest of warriors, and will never leave their ranks, for they will all know one another, and each will call the other father, brother, son; and if you suppose the women to join their armies, whether in the same rank or in the rear, either as a terror to the enemy, or as auxiliaries in case of need, I know that they will then be absolutely invincible; and there are many domestic advantages which might also be mentioned and which I also fully acknowledge: but, as I admit all these advantages and as many more as you please, if only this State of yours were to come into existence, we need say no more about them; assuming then the existence of the State, let us now turn to the question of possibility and ways and means—the rest may be left.

d
e

If I loiter for a moment, you instantly make a raid upon me, I said, and have no mercy; I have hardly escaped the first and second waves, and you seem not to be aware that you are now bringing upon me the third, which is the greatest and heaviest. When you have seen and heard the third wave, I think you will be more considerate and will acknowledge that some fear and hesitation were natural respecting a proposal so extraordinary as that which I have now to state and investigate.

472

The more appeals of this sort which you make, he said, the more determined are we that you shall tell us how such a State is possible: speak out and at once.

b

Let me begin by reminding you that we found our way hither in the search after justice and injustice.

True, he replied; but what of that?

I was only going to ask whether, if we have discovered them, we are to require that the just man should in nothing fail of absolute justice; or may we be satisfied with an approximation, and the attainment in him of a higher degree of justice than is to be found in other men?

c

The approximation will be enough.

We were inquiring into the nature of absolute justice and into the character of the perfectly just, and into injustice and the perfectly unjust, that we might have an ideal. We were to look at these in order that we might judge of our own happiness and unhappiness according to the standard which they exhibited and the degree in which we resembled them, but not with any view of showing that they could exist in fact.

d

True, he said.

Would a painter be any the worse because, after having delineated with consummate art an ideal of a perfectly beautiful man, he was unable to show that any such man could ever have existed?

He would be none the worse.

Well, and were we not creating an ideal of a perfect State?

To be sure.

e

And is our theory a worse theory because we are unable to prove the possibility of a city being ordered in the manner described? 22

Surely not, he replied.

That is the truth, I said. But if, at your request, I am to try and show how and under what conditions the possibility is highest, I must ask you, having this in view, to repeat your former admissions.

What admissions?

Is it possible for anything to be accomplished in deed as it is expressed in word? Or is it inevitable that what is done falls short of what is said in attaining to the truth, even though this is not generally thought to be the case? What do you say?

473

I agree.

Then you must not insist on my proving that the actual State will in every respect coincide with the ideal: if we are only able to discover how a city may be governed nearly as we proposed, you will admit that we have discovered the possibility which you demand; and will be contented. I am sure that I should be contented—will not you?

b

Yes, I will.

Let me next endeavor to show what is that fault in States which is the cause of their present maladministration, and what is the least change which will enable a State to pass into the truer form; and let the change, if possible, be of one thing only, or, if not, of two; at any rate, let the changes be as few and slight as possible.

Certainly, he replied.

c

I think, I said, that there might be a reform of the State if only one change were made, which is not a slight or easy though still a possible one.

What is it? he said.

Now then, I said, I go to meet that which I liken to the greatest of the waves; yet shall the word be spoken, even though the wave break and drown me in laughter and dishonor; and do you mark my words.

Proceed.

I said: “Until philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy, and political greatness and wisdom meet in one, and those commoner natures who pursue either to the exclusion of the other are compelled to stand aside, cities will never have rest from their evils—no, nor the human race, as I believe—and then only will this our State have a possibility of life and behold the light of day.”23 Such was the thought, my dear Glaucon, which I would fain have uttered if it had not seemed too extravagant; for to be convinced that in no other State can there be happiness private or public is indeed a hard thing.

d
e

Socrates, what do you mean? I would have you consider that the word which you have uttered is one at which numerous persons, and very respectable persons too, in a figure pulling off their coats all in a moment, and seizing any weapon that comes to hand, will run at you might and main, before you know where you are, intending to do heaven knows what; and if you don’t prepare an answer, and put yourself in motion, you will be “pared by their fine wits,” and no mistake.

474

You got me into the scrape, I said.

And I was quite right; however, I will do all I can to get you out of it; but I can only give you good-will and good advice, and, perhaps, I may be able to fit answers to your questions better than another—that is all. And now, having such an auxiliary, you must do your best to show the unbelievers that you are right.

b

I ought to try, I said, since you offer me such invaluable assistance. And I think that, if there is to be a chance of our escaping, we must explain to them whom we mean when we say that philosophers are to rule in the State; then we shall be able to defend ourselves : There will be discovered to be some natures who ought to study philosophy and to be leaders in the State; and others who are not born to be philosophers, and are meant to be followers rather than leaders.

c

Then now for a definition, he said.

Follow me, I said, and I hope that I may in some way or other be able to give you a satisfactory explanation.

Proceed.

I dare say that you remember, and therefore I need not remind you, that a lover, if he is worthy of the name, ought to show his love, not to some one part of that which he loves, but to the whole.

I really do not understand, and therefore beg of you to assist my memory.

d

Another person, I said, might fairly reply as you do; but a man of pleasure like yourselfer ought to know that all who are in the flower of youth do somehow or other raise a pang or emotion in a lover’s breast, and are thought by him to be worthy of his affectionate regards. Is not this a way which you have with the fair: one has a snub nose, and you praise his charming face; the hook-nose of another has, you say, a royal look; while he who is neither snub nor hooked has the grace of regularity: the dark visage is manly, the fair are children of the gods; and as to the sweet “honey-pale,” as they are called, what is the very name but the invention of a lover who talks in diminutives, and is not averse to paleness if appearing on the cheek of youth? In a word, there is no excuse which you will not make, and nothing which you will not say, in order not to lose a single flower that blooms in the spring-time of youth.

e
475

If you make me an authority in matters of love, for the sake of the argument, I assent.

And what do you say of lovers of wine? Do you not see them doing the same? They are glad of any pretext of drinking any wine.

Very good.

And the same is true of ambitious men; if they cannot command an army, they are willing to command a file; and if they cannot be honored by really great and important persons, they are glad to be honored by lesser and meaner people—but honor of some kind they must have.

b

Exactly.

Once more let me ask: Does he who desires any class of goods, desire the whole class or a part only?

The whole.

And may we not say of the philosopher that he is a lover, not of a part of wisdom only, but of the whole?

Yes, of the whole.

And he who dislikes learning, especially in youth, when he has no power of judging what is good and what is not, such a one we maintain not to be a philosopher or a lover of knowledge, just as he who refuses his food is not hungry, and may be said to have a bad appetite and not a good one?

c

Very true, he said.

Whereas he who has a taste for every sort of knowledge and who is curious to learn and is never satisfied, may be justly termed a philosopher? Am I not right?

Glaucon said: If curiosity makes a philosopher, you will find many a strange being will have a title to the name. All the lovers of sights have a delight in learning, and must therefore be included. Musical amateurs, too, are a folk strangely out of place among philosophers, for they are the last persons in the world who would come to anything like a philosophical discussion, if they could help, while they run about at the Dionysiac festivals as if they had let out their ears to hear every chorus; whether the performance is in town or country—that makes no difference—they are there. Now are we to maintain that all these and any who have similar tastes, as well as the professors of quite minor arts, are philosophers?

d
e

Certainly not, I replied; they are only an imitation.

He said: Who then are the true philosophers?

Those, I said, who are lovers of the vision of truth.

That is also good, he said; but I should like to know what you mean?

To another, I replied, I might have a difficulty in explaining; but I am sure that you will admit a proposition which I am about to make.

What is the proposition?

That since beauty is the opposite of ugliness, they are two? Certainly.

476

And inasmuch as they are two, each of them is one?

True again.

And of just and unjust, good and evil, and of every other class, the same remark holds: taken singly, each of them is one; but from the various combinations of them with actions and things and with one another, they are seen in all sorts of lights and appear many?

Very true.

And this is the distinction which I draw between the sight-loving, art-loving, practical class and those of whom I am speaking, and who are alone worthy of the name of philosophers.

b

How do you distinguish them? he said.

The lovers of sounds and sights, I replied, are, as I conceive, fond of fine tones and colors and forms and all the artificial products that are made out of them, but their minds are incapable of seeing or loving absolute beauty.

True, he replied.

c

Few are they who are able to attain to the sight of this.

Very true.

And he who, having a sense of beautiful things has no sense of absolute beauty, or who, if another lead him to a knowledge of that beauty is unable to follow—of such a one I ask, Is he awake or in a dream only? Reflect: is not the dreamer, sleeping or waking, one who likens dissimilar things, who puts the copy in the place of the real object?

I should certainly say that such a one was dreaming.

But take the case of the other, who recognizes the existence of absolute beauty and is able to distinguish the idea from the objects which participate in the idea, neither putting the objects in the place of the idea nor the idea in the place of the objects—is he a dreamer, or is he awake?24

d

He is wide awake.

And may we not say that the mind of the one who knows has knowledge, and that the mind of the other, who opines only, has opinion?

Certainly.

But suppose that the latter should quarrel with us and dispute our statement,25 can we administer any soothing cordial or advice to him, without revealing to him that there is sad disorder in his wits?

e

We must certainly offer him some good advice, he replied.

Come, then, and let us think of something to say to him. Shall we begin by assuring him that he is welcome to any knowledge which he may have, and that we are rejoiced at his having it? But we should like to ask him a question: Does he who has knowledge know something or nothing? (You must answer for him).

I answer that he knows something.

Something that is or is not?26

Something that is; for how can that which is not ever be known?27

477

And are we assured, after looking at the matter from many points of view, that absolute being is or may be absolutely known, but that the utterly non-existent is utterly unknown?

Nothing can be more certain.

Good. But if there be anything which is of such a nature as to be and not to be, that will have a place intermediate between pure being and the absolute negation of being?

Yes, between them.

And, as knowledge corresponded to being and ignorance of necessity to not-being, for that intermediate between being and not-being there has to be discovered a corresponding intermediate between ignorance and knowledge, if there be such?

b

Certainly.

Do we admit the existence of opinion?

Undoubtedly.

As being the same with knowledge, or another faculty?

Another faculty.

Then opinion and knowledge have to do with different kinds of matter corresponding to this difference of faculties?

Yes.

And knowledge is relative to being and knows being. But before I proceed further I will make a division.

What division?

I will begin by placing faculties in a class by themselves: they are powers in us, and in all other things, by which we do as we do. Sight and hearing, for example, I should call faculties. Have I clearly explained the class which I mean?

c

Yes, I quite understand.

Then let me tell you my view about them. I do not see them, and therefore the distinctions of figure, color, and the like, which enable me to discern the differences of some things, do not apply to them. In speaking of a faculty I think only of its sphere and its result; and that which has the same sphere and the same result I call the same faculty, but that which has another sphere and another result I call different. Would that be your way of speaking?

d

Yes.

And will you be so very good as to answer one more question? Would you say that knowledge is a faculty, or in what class would you place it?

Certainly knowledge is a faculty, and the mightiest of all faculties.

And is opinion also a faculty?

e

Certainly, he said; for opinion is that with which we are able to form an opinion.

And yet you were acknowledging a little while ago that knowledge is not the same as opinion?

Why, yes, he said: how can any reasonable being ever identify that which is infallible with that which errs?

An excellent answer, proving, I said, that we are quite conscious of a distinction between them.

478

Yes.

Then knowledge and opinion having distinct powers have also distinct spheres or subject-matters?

That is certain.

Being is the sphere or subject-matter of knowledge, and knowledge is to know the nature of being?

Yes.

And opinion is to have an opinion?

Yes.

And do we know what we opine? or is the subject-matter of opinion the same as the subject-matter of knowledge?

Nay, he replied, that has been already disproven; if difference in faculty implies difference in the sphere or subject-matter, and if, as we were saying, opinion and knowledge are distinct faculties, then the sphere of knowledge and of opinion cannot be the same.

b

Then if being is the subject-matter of knowledge, something else must be the subject-matter of opinion?

Yes, something else.

Well, then, is not-being the subject-matter of opinion? or, rather, how can there be an opinion at all about not-being? Reflect: when a man has an opinion, has he not an opinion about something? Can he have an opinion which is an opinion about nothing?

Impossible.

He who has an opinion, has an opinion about some one thing?

Yes.

And not-being is not one thing, but, properly speaking, nothing?

True.

Of not-being, ignorance was assumed to be the necessary correlative; of being, knowledge?

c

True, he said.

Then opinion is not concerned either with being or with not-being?

Not with either.

And can therefore neither be ignorance nor knowledge?

That seems to be true.

But is opinion to be sought without and beyond either of them, in a greater clearness than knowledge, or in a greater darkness than ignorance?

In neither.

Then I suppose that opinion appears to you to be darker than knowledge, but lighter than ignorance?

Both; and in no small degree.

And also to be within and between them?

d

Yes.

Then you would infer that opinion is intermediate?28

No question.

But were we not saying before, that if anything appeared to be of a sort which is and is not at the same time, that sort of thing would appear also to lie in the interval between pure being and absolute not-being; and that the corresponding faculty is neither knowledge nor ignorance, but will be found in the interval between them?

True.

And in that interval there has now been discovered something which we call opinion?

There has.

Then what remains to be discovered is the object which partakes equally of the nature of being and not-being, and cannot rightly be termed either, pure and simple; this unknown term, when discovered, we may truly call the subject of opinion, and assign each to their proper faculty—the extremes to the faculties of the extremes and the mean to the faculty of the mean.

e

True.

This being premised, I would ask the gentleman who is of opinion that there is no absolute or unchangeable idea of beauty—in whose opinion the beautiful is the manifold—he, I say, your lover of beautiful sights, who cannot bear to be told that the beautiful is one, and the just is one, or that anything is one—to him I would appeal, saying, Will you be so very kind, sir, as to tell us whether, of all these beautiful things, there is one which will not be found ugly; or of the just, which will not be found unjust; or of the holy, which will not also be unholy?

479

No, he replied; the beautiful will in some point of view be found ugly; and the same is true of the rest.

b

And may not the many which are doubles be also halves?—doubles, that is, of one thing, and halves of another?

Quite true.

And things great and small, heavy and light, as they are termed, will not be denoted by these any more than by the opposite names?

True; both these and the opposite names will always attach to all of them.

And can any one of those many things which are called by particular names be said to be this rather than not to be this?

He replied: They are like the punning riddles which are asked at feasts or the children’s puzzle about the eunuch aiming at the bat,29 with what he hit him, as they say in the puzzle, and upon what the bat was sitting. The individual objects of which I am speaking are also a riddle, and have a double sense: nor can you fix them in your mind, either as being or not-being, or both, or neither.

c

Then what will you do with them? I said. Can they have a better place than between being and not-being? For they are clearly not in greater darkness or negation than not-being, or more full of light and existence than being.

d

That is quite true, he said.

Thus then we seem to have discovered that the many ideas which the multitude entertain about the beautiful and about all other things are tossing about in some region which is halfway between pure being and pure not-being?

We have.

Yes; and we had before agreed that anything of this kind which we might find was to be described as matter of opinion, and not as matter of knowledge; being the intermediate flux which is caught and detained by the intermediate faculty.

Quite true.

e

Then those who see the many beautiful, and who yet neither see absolute beauty, nor can follow any guide who points the way thither; who see the many just, and not absolute justice, and the like—such persons may be said to have opinion but not knowledge?

That is certain.

But those who see the absolute and eternal and immutable may be said to know, and not to have opinion only?

Neither can that be denied.

The one love and embrace the subjects of knowledge, the other those of opinion? The latter are the same, as I dare say you will remember, who listened to sweet sounds and gazed upon fair colors, but would not tolerate the existence of absolute beauty.

480

Yes, 1 remember.

Shall we then be guilty of any impropriety in calling them lovers of opinion rather than lovers of wisdom, and will they be very angry with us for thus describing them?

I shall tell them not to be angry; no man should be angry at what is true.

But those who love the truth in each thing are to be called lovers of wisdom and not lovers of opinion.

Assuredly.

BOOK 6

AND THUS, GLAUCON, AFTER the argument has gone a weary way, the true and the false philosophers have at length appeared in view.

484

I do not think, he said, that the way could have been shortened.

I suppose not, I said; and yet I believe that we might have had a better view of both of them if the discussion could have been confined to this one subject and if there were not many other questions awaiting us, which he who desires to see in what respect the life of the just differs from that of the unjust must consider.1

b

And what is the next question? he asked.

Surely, I said, the one which follows next in order. Inasmuch as philosophers only are able to grasp the eternal and unchangeable, and those who wander in the region of the many and variable are not philosophers, I must ask you which of the two classes should be the rulers of our State?

And how can we rightly answer that question?

Whichever of the two are best able to guard the laws and institutions of our State—let them be our guardians.

c

Very good.

Neither, I said, can there be any question that the guardian who is to keep anything should have eyes rather than no eyes?

There can be no question of that.

And are not those who are verily and indeed wanting in the knowledge of the true being of each thing, and who have in their souls no clear pattern, and are unable as with a painter’s eye to look at the absolute truth and to that original to repair, and having perfect vision of the other world to order the laws about beauty, goodness, justice in this, if not already ordered, and to guard and preserve the order of them—are not such persons, I ask, simply blind? 2

d

Truly, he replied, they are much in that condition.

And shall they be our guardians when there are others who, besides being their equals in experience and falling short of them in no particular of virtue, also know the very truth of each thing?

There can be no reason, he said, for rejecting those who have this greatest of all great qualities; they must always have the first place unless they fail in some other respect.

Suppose, then, I said, that we determine how far they can unite this and the other excellences.

485

By all means.

In the first place, as we began by observing, the nature of the philosopher has to be ascertained.3 We must come to an understanding about him, and, when we have done so, then, if I am not mistaken, we shall also acknowledge that such a union of qualities is possible, and that those in whom they are united, and those only, should be rulers in the State.

What do you mean?

Let us suppose that philosophical minds always love knowledge of a sort which shows them the eternal nature not varying from generation and corruption.

b

Agreed.

And further, I said, let us agree that they are lovers of all true being; there is no part whether greater or less, or more or less honorable, which they are willing to renounce; as we said before of the lover and the man of ambition.

True.

And if they are to be what we were describing, is there not another quality which they should also possess?

c

What quality?

Truthfulness: they will never intentionally receive into their minds falsehood, which is their detestation, and they will love the truth.

Yes, that may be safely affirmed of them.

“May be,” my friend, I replied, is not the word; say rather, “must be affirmed:” for he whose nature is amorous of anything cannot help loving all that belongs or is akin to the object of his affections.

Right, he said.

And is there anything more akin to wisdom than truth?

How can there be?

Can the same nature be a lover of wisdom and a lover of falsehood?

d

Never.

The true lover of learning then must from his earliest youth, as far as in him lies, desire all truth?

Assuredly.

But then again, as we know by experience, he whose desires are strong in one direction will have them weaker in others; they will be like a stream which has been drawn off into another channel.

True.

He whose desires are drawn toward knowledge in every form will be absorbed in the pleasures of the soul, and will hardly feel bodily pleasure—I mean, if he be a true philosopher and not a sham one.

e

That is most certain.

Such a one is sure to be temperate and the reverse of covetous; for the motives which make another man desirous of having and spending, have no place in his character.

Very true.

Another criterion of the philosophical nature has also to be considered.

486

What is that?

There should be no secret corner of illiberality;4 nothing can be more antagonistic than meanness to a soul which is ever longing after the whole of things both divine and human.

Most true, he replied.

Then how can he who has magnificence of mind and is the spectator of all time and all existence, think much of human life?

He cannot.

Or can such a one account death fearful?

b

No, indeed.

Then the cowardly and mean nature has no part in true philosophy?

Certainly not.

Or again: can he who is harmoniously constituted, who is not covetous or mean, or a boaster, or a coward—can he, I say, ever be unjust or hard in his dealings?

Impossible.

Then you will soon observe whether a man is just and gentle, or rude and unsociable; these are the signs which distinguish even in youth the philosophical nature from the unphilosophical.

True.

There is another point which should be remarked.

c
What point?

Whether he has or has not a pleasure in learning; for no one will love that which gives him pain, and in which after much toil he makes little progress.

Certainly not.

And again, if he is forgetful and retains nothing of what he learns, will he not be an empty vessel?

That is certain.

Laboring in vain, he must end in hating himself and his fruitless occupation?

Yes.

Then a soul which forgets cannot be ranked among genuine philosophic natures; we must insist that the philosopher should have a good memory?

d

Certainly.

And once more, the inharmonious and unseemly nature can only tend to disproportion?

Undoubtedly.

And do you consider truth to be akin to proportion or to disproportion?

To proportion.

Then, besides other qualities, we must try to find a naturally well-proportioned and gracious mind, which will move spontaneously toward the true being of everything.

Certainly.

Well, and do not all these qualities, which we have been enumerating, go together, and are they not, in a manner, necessary to a soul, which is to have a full and perfect participation of being?

e

They are absolutely necessary, he replied.

487

And must not that be a blameless study which he only can pursue who has the gift of a good memory, and is quick to learn—noble, gracious, the friend of truth, justice, courage, temperance, who are his kindred?

The god of jealousyes himself, he said, could find no fault with such a study.

And to men like him, I said, when perfected by years and education, and to these only you will intrust the State.

Here Adeimantus interposed and said: To these statements, Socrates, no one can offer a reply; but when you talk in this way, a strange feeling passes over the minds of your hearers: They fancy that they are led astray a little at each step in the argument, owing to their own want of skill in asking and answering questions; these littles accumulate, and at the end of the discussion they are found to have sustained a mighty overthrow and all their former notions appear to be turned upside down. 5 And as unskilful players of draughts are at last shut up by their more skilful adversaries and have no piece to move, so they too find themselves shut up at last; for they have nothing to say in this new game of which words are the counters; and yet all the time they are in the right. The observation is suggested to me by what is now occurring. For any one of us might say, that although in words he is not able to meet you at each step of the argument, he sees as a fact that the votaries of philosophy, when they carry on the study, not only in youth as a part of education, but as the pursuit of their maturer years, most of them become strange monsters, not to say utter rogues, and that those who may be considered the best of them are made useless to the world by the very study which you extol.

b
c
d

Well, and do you think that those who say so are wrong?

I cannot tell, he replied; but I should like to know what is your opinion.

Hear my answer; I am of opinion that they are quite right.

Then how can you be justified in saying that cities will not cease from evil until philosophers rule in them, when philosophers are acknowledged by us to be of no use to them?

e

You ask a question, I said, to which a reply can only be given in a parable.

Yes, Socrates; and that is a way of speaking to which you are not at all accustomed, I suppose.

I perceive, I said, that you are vastly amused at having plunged me into such a hopeless discussion; but now hear the parable, and then you will be still more amused at the meagreness of my imagination : for the manner in which the best men are treated in their own States is so grievous that no single thing on earth is comparable to it; and therefore, if I am to plead their cause, I must have recourse to fiction, and put together a figure made up of many things, like the fabulous unions of goats and stags which are found in pictures. Imagine then a fleet or a ship in which there is a captain who is taller and stronger than any of the crew, but he is a little deaf and has a similar infirmity in sight, and his knowledge of navigation is not much better.6 The sailors are quarrelling with one another about the steering—everyone is of opinion that he has a right to steer, though he has never learned the art of navigation and cannot tell who taught him or when he learned, and will further assert that it cannot be taught, and they are ready to cut in pieces anyone who says the contrary. They throng about the captain, begging and praying him to commit the helm to them; and if at any time they do not prevail, but others are preferred to them, they kill the others or throw them overboard, and having first chained up the noble captain’s senses with drink or some narcotic drug, they mutiny and take possession of the ship and make free with the stores; thus, eating and drinking, they proceed on their voyage in such manner as might be expected of them. Him who is their partisan and cleverly aids them in their plot for getting the ship out of the captain’s hands into their own whether by force or persuasion, they compliment with the name of sailor, pilot, able seaman, and abuse the other sort of man, whom they call a good-for-nothing; but that the true pilot must pay attention to the year and seasons and sky and stars and winds, and whatever else belongs to his art, if he intends to be really qualified for the command of a ship, and that he must and will be the steerer, whether other people like or not—the possibility of this union of authority with the steerer’s art has never seriously entered into their thoughts or been made part of their calling. Now in vessels which are in a state of mutiny and by sailors who are mutineers, how will the true pilot be regarded? Will he not be called by them a prater, a stargazer, a good-for-nothing?

488
b
c
d
e
489

Of course, said Adeimantus.

Then you will hardly need, I said, to hear the interpretation of the figure, which describes the true philosopher in his relation to the State; for you understand already.

Certainly.

Then suppose you now take this parable to the gentlemanet who is surprised at finding that philosophers have no honor in their cities; explain it to him and try to convince him that their having honor would be far more extraordinary.

b

I will.

Say to him, that, in deeming the best votaries of philosophy to be useless to the rest of the world, he is right; but also tell him to attribute their uselessness to the fault of those who will not use them, and not to themselves. The pilot should not humbly beg the sailors to be commanded by him—that is not the order of nature; neither are “the wise to go to the doors of the rich”—the ingenious author of this sayingeu told a lie—but the truth is, that, when a man is ill, whether he be rich or poor, to the physician he must go, and he who wants to be governed, to him who is able to govern. The ruler who is good for anything ought not to beg his subjects to be ruled by him; although the present governors of mankind are of a different stamp; they may be justly compared to the mutinous sailors, and the true helmsmen to those who are called by them good-for-nothings and star-gazers.

c

Precisely so, he said.

For these reasons, and among men like these, philosophy, the noblest pursuit of all, is not likely to be much esteemed by those of the opposite faction;ev not that the greatest and most lasting injury is done to her by her opponents, but by her own professing followers, the same of whom you suppose the accuser to say that the greater number of them are arrant rogues, and the best are useless; in which opinion I agreed.

d

Yes.

And the reason why the good are useless has now been explained?

True.

Then shall we proceed to show that the corruption of the majority is also unavoidable, and that this is not to be laid to the charge of philosophy any more than the other?

e

By all means.

And let us ask and answer in turn, first going back to the description of the gentle and noble nature. Truth, as you will remember, was his leader, whom he followed always and in all things; failing in this, he was an impostor, and had no part or lot in true philosophy.

490

Yes, that was said.

Well, and is not this one quality, to mention no others, greatly at variance with present notions of him?

Certainly, he said.

And have we not a right to say in his defence, that the true lover of knowledge is always striving after being—that is his nature; he will not rest in the multiplicity of individuals which is an appearance only, but will go on—the keen edge will not be blunted, nor the force of his desire abate until he have attained the knowledge of the true nature of every essence by a sympathetic and kindred power in the soul, and by that power drawing near and mingling and becoming incorporate with very being, having begotten mind and truth, he will have knowledge and will live and grow truly, and then, and not till then, will he cease from his travail.

b

Nothing, he said, can be more just than such a description of him.

And will the love of a lie be any part of a philosopher’s nature? Will he not utterly hate a lie?

He will.

c

And when truth is the captain, we cannot suspect any evil of the band which he leads?

Impossible.

Justice and health of mind will be of the company, and temperance will follow after?

True, he replied.

Neither is there any reason why I should again set in array the philosopher’s virtues, as you will doubtless remember that courage, magnificence, apprehension, memory, were his natural gifts. And you objected that, although no one could deny what I then said, still, if you leave words and look at facts, the persons who are thus described are some of them manifestly useless, and the greater number of them depraved; inquiring into the grounds of these accusations, we have come to the question of why most are bad, and because of this we have begun discussing the nature of true philosophers and have defined it as it must be.

d

Exactly.

e

And we have next to consider the corruptions of the philosophic nature, why so many are spoiled and so few escape spoiling—I am speaking of those who were said to be useless but not wicked—and, when we have done with them, we will speak of the imitators of philosophy, what manner of men are they who aspire after a profession which is above them and of which they are unworthy, and then, by their manifold inconsistencies, bring upon philosophy and upon all philosophers that universal reprobation of which we speak.

491

What are these corruptions? he said.

I will see if I can explain them to you. Everyone will admit that a nature having in perfection all the qualities which we required in a philosopher is a rare plant which is seldom seen among men?

b

Rare indeed.

And what numberless and powerful causes tend to destroy these rare natures!

What causes?

In the first place there are their own virtues, their courage, temperance, and the rest of them, every one of which praiseworthy qualities (and this is a most singular circumstance) destroys and distracts from philosophy the soul which is the possessor of them.

That is very singular, he replied.

Then there are all the ordinary goods of life—beauty, wealth, strength, rank, and great connections in the State—you understand the sort of things—these also have a corrupting and distracting effect.

c

I understand; but I should like to know more precisely what you mean about them.

Grasp the truth as a whole, I said, and in the right way; you will then have no difficulty in apprehending the preceding remarks, and they will no longer appear strange to you.

And how am I to do so? he asked.

Why, I said, we know that all germs or seeds, whether vegetable or animal, when they fail to meet with proper nutriment, or climate, or soil, in proportion to their vigor, are all the more sensitive to the want of a suitable environment, for evil is a greater enemy to what is good than to what is not. 7

d

Very true.

There is reason in supposing that the finest natures, when under alien conditions, receive more injury than the inferior, because the contrast is greater.

Certainly.

And may we not say, Adeimantus, that the most gifted minds, when they are ill-educated, become pre-eminently bad? Do not great crimes and the spirit of pure evil spring out of a fulness of nature ruined by education rather than from any inferiority, whereas weak natures are scarcely capable of any very great good or very great evil?

e

There I think that you are right.

And our philosopher follows the same analogy—he is like a plant which, having proper nurture, must necessarily grow and mature into all virtue, but, if sown and planted in an alien soil, becomes the most noxious of all weeds, unless he be preserved by some divine power. 8 Do you really think, as people so often say, that our youth are corrupted by Sophists, or that private teachers of the art corrupt them in any degree worth speaking of? Are not the public who say these things the greatest of all Sophists? 9 And do they not educate to perfection young and old, men and women alike, and fashion them after their own hearts?

492
b

When is this accomplished? he said.

When they meet together, and the world sits down at an assembly, or in a court of law, or a theatre, or a camp, or in any other popular resort, and there is a great uproar, and they praise some things which are being said or done, and blame other things, equally exaggerating both, shouting and clapping their hands, and the echo of the rocks and the place in which they are assembled redoubles the sound of the praise or blame—at such a time will not a young man’s heart, as they say, leap within him? Will any private training enable him to stand firm against the overwhelming flood of popular opinion? or will he be carried away by the stream? Will he not have the notions of good and evil which the public in general have—he will do as they do, and as they are, such will he be?

c

Yes, Socrates; necessity will compel him.

d

And yet, I said, there is a still greater necessity, which has not been mentioned.

What is that?

The gentle force of loss of citizen-rights, or confiscation, or death, which, as you are aware, these new Sophists and educators, who are the public, apply when their words are powerless.

Indeed they do; and in right good earnest.

Now what opinion of any other Sophist, or of any private person, can be expected to overcome in such an unequal contest?

None, he replied.

e

No, indeed, I said, even to make the attempt is a great piece of folly; there neither is, nor has been, nor is ever likely to be, any different type of character which has had no other training in virtue but that which is supplied by public opinion—I speak, my friend, of human virtue only; what is more than human, as the proverb says, is not included: for I would not have you ignorant that, in the present evil state of governments, whatever is saved and comes to good is saved by the power of God, as we may truly say.

493

I quite assent, he replied.

Then let me crave your assent also to a further observation. What are you going to say?

Why, that all those mercenary individuals, whom the many call Sophists and whom they deem to be their adversaries, do, in fact, teach nothing but the opinion of the many, that is to say, the opinions of their assemblies; and this is their wisdom. I might compare them to a man who should study the tempers and desires of a mighty strong beast who is fed by him—he would learn how to approach and handle him, also at what times and from what causes he is dangerous or the reverse, and what is the meaning of his several cries, and by what sounds, when another utters them, he is soothed or infuriated; and you may suppose further, that when, by continually attending upon him, he has become perfect in all this, he calls his knowledge wisdom, and makes of it a system or art, which he proceeds to teach, although he has no real notion of what he means by the principles or passions of which he is speaking, but calls this honorable and that dishonorable, or good or evil, or just or unjust, all in accordance with the tastes and tempers of the great brute. Good he pronounces to be that in which the beast delights, and evil to be that which he dislikes; and he can give no other account of them but calls mere necessities “just” and “good,” having never himself seen, and having no power of explaining to others, the nature of either, or the difference between them, which is immense. By heaven, would not such a one be a rare educator?

b
c

Indeed, he would.

And in what way does he who thinks that wisdom is the discernment of the tempers and tastes of the motley multitude, whether in painting or in music, or, finally, in politics, differ from him whom I have been describing? For when a man consorts with the many, and exhibits to them his poem or other work of art or the service which he has done the State, making them his judges when he is not obliged, the so-called necessity of Diomede 10 will oblige him to produce whatever they praise. To support their claim that their capitulations to popular opinion are in truth honorable and good, did you ever hear any of them put forth an argument that was not utterly ludicrous?

d

No, nor am I likely to hear.

e

You recognize the truth of what I have been saying? Then let me ask you to consider further whether the world will ever be induced to believe in the existence of absolute beauty rather than of the many beautiful, or of the absolute in each kind rather than of the many in each kind?

494

Certainly not.

Then the world cannot possibly be a philosopher? 11

Impossible.

And therefore philosophers must inevitably fall under the censure of the world?

They must.

And of individuals who consort with the mob and seek to please them?

That is evident.

Then, do you see any way in which the philosopher can be preserved in his calling to the end?—and remember what we were saying of him, that he was to have quickness and memory and courage and magnincence—these were admitted by us to be the true philosopher’s gifts.

b

Yes.

Will not such a one from his early childhood be in all things first among us all, especially if his bodily endowments are like his mental ones?

Certainly, he said.

And his friends and fellow-citizens will want to use him as he gets older for their own purposes?

No question.

Falling at his feet, they will make requests to him and do him honor and flatter him, because they want to get into their hands now the power which he will one day possess.

c

That often happens, he said.

And what will a man such as he is be likely to do under such circumstances, especially if he be a citizen of a great city, rich and noble, and a tall, proper youth?12 Will he not be full of boundless aspirations, and fancy himself able to manage the affairs of Hellenes and of barbarians, and having got such notions into his head will he not dilate and elevate himself in the fulness of vain pomp and senseless pride?

d

To be sure he will.

Now, when he is in this state of mind, if someone gently comes to him and tells him that he is a fool and must get understanding, which can only be got by slaving for it, do you think that, under such adverse circumstances, he will be easily induced to listen?

Far otherwise.

And even if there be someone who through inherent goodness or natural reasonableness has had his eyes opened a little and is humbled and taken captive by philosophy, how will his friends behave when they think that they are likely to lose the advantage which they were hoping to reap from his companionship? Will they not do and say anything to prevent him from yielding to his better nature and to render his teacher powerless, using to this end private intrigues as well as public prosecutions?

e

There can be no doubt of it.

495

And how can one who is thus circumstanced ever become a philosopher?

Impossible.

Then were we not right in saying that even the very qualities which make a man a philosopher, may, if he be ill-educated, divert him from philosophy, no less than riches and their accompaniments and the other so-called goods of life?

We were quite right.

Thus, my excellent friend, is brought about all that ruin and failure which I have been describing of the natures best adapted to the best of all pursuits; they are natures which we maintain to be rare at any time; this being the class out of which come the men who are the authors of the greatest evil to States and individuals; and also of the greatest good when the tide carries them in that direction; but a small man never was the doer of any great thing either to individuals or to States.

b

That is most true, he said.

And so philosophy is left desolate, with her marriage rite incomplete: for her own have fallen away and forsaken her, and while they are leading a false and unbecoming life, other unworthy persons, seeing that she has no kinsmen to be her protectors, enter in and dishonor her; and fasten upon her the reproaches which, as you say, her reprovers utter, who affirm of her votaries that some are good for nothing, and that the greater number deserve the severest punishment.

c

That is certainly what people say.

Yes; and what else would you expect, I said, when you think of the puny creatures who, seeing this land open to them—a land well stocked with fair names and showy titles—like prisoners running out of prison into a sanctuary, take a leap out of their trades into philosophy; those who do so being probably the cleverest hands at their own miserable crafts? For, although philosophy be in this evil case, still there remains a dignity about her which is not to be found in the arts. And many are thus attracted by her whose natures are imperfect and whose souls are maimed and disfigured by their meannesses, as their bodies are by their trades and crafts. Is not this unavoidable?

d
e

Yes.

Are they not exactly like a bald little tinker who has just got out of durance and come into a fortune—he takes a bath and puts on a new coat, and is decked out as a bridegroom going to marry his master’s daughter, who is left poor and desolate?

A most exact parallel.

496

What will be the issue of such marriages? Will they not be vile and bastard?

There can be no question of it.

And when persons who are unworthy of education approach philosophy and make an alliance with her who is in a rank above them, what sort of ideas and opinions are likely to be generated? Will they not be sophisms captivating to the ear, having nothing in them genuine, or worthy of or akin to true wisdom?

No doubt, he said.

Then, Adeimantus, I said, the worthy disciples of philosophy will be but a small remnant: perchance some noble and well-educated person, detained by exile in her service, who in the absence of corrupting influences remains devoted to her; or some lofty soul born in a mean city, the politics of which he contemns and neglects; and there may be a gifted few who leave the arts, which they justly despise, and come to her; or peradventure there are some who are restrained by our friend Theages’s bridle;ew for everything in the life of Theages conspired to divert him from philosophy; but ill-health kept him away from politics. My own case of the internal sign is hardly worth mentioning, for rarely, if ever, has such a monitor been given to any other man. Those who belong to this small class have tasted how sweet and blessed a possession philosophy is, and have also seen enough of the madness of the multitude; and they know that no politician is honest, nor is there any champion of justice at whose side they may fight and be saved. Such a one may be compared to a man who has fallen among wild beasts—he will not join in the wickedness of his fellows, but neither is he able singly to resist all their fierce natures, and therefore seeing that he would be of no use to the State or to his friends, and reflecting that he would have to throw away his life without doing any good either to himself or others, he holds his peace, and goes his own way.13 He is like one who, in the storm of dust and sleet which the driving wind hurries along, retires under the shelter of a wall; and seeing the rest of mankind full of wickedness, he is content, if only he can live his own life and be pure from evil or unrighteousness, and depart in peace and good-will, with bright hopes.

b
c
d
e

Yes, he said, and he will have done a great work before he departs.

497

A great work—yes; but not the greatest, unless he find a State suitable to him; for in a State which is suitable to him, he will have a larger growth and be the saviour of his country, as well as of himself.

The causes why philosophy is in such an evil name have now been sufficiently explained: the injustice of the charges against her has been shown—is there anything more which you wish to say?

Nothing more on that subject, he replied; but I should like to know which of the governments now existing is in your opinion the one adapted to her.

Not any of them, I said; and that is precisely the accusation which I bring against them—not one of them is worthy of the philosophic nature, and hence that nature is warped and estranged; as the exotic seed which is sown in a foreign land becomes denaturalized, and is wont to be overpowered and to lose itself in the new soil, even so this growth of philosophy, instead of persisting, degenerates and receives another character. But if philosophy ever finds in the State that perfection which she herself is, then will be seen that she is in truth divine, and that all other things, whether natures of men or institutions, are but human; and now, I know that you are going to ask, What that State is:

b
c

No, he said; there you are wrong, for I was going to ask another question—whether it is the State of which we are the founders and inventors, or some other?

Yes, I replied, ours in most respects; but you may remember my saying before, that some living authority would always be required in the State having the same idea of the constitution which guided you when as legislator you were laying down the laws.14

d

That was said, he replied.

Yes, but not in a satisfactory manner; you frightened us by interposing objections, which certainly showed that the discussion would be long and difficult; and what still remains is the reverse of easy.

What is there remaining?

The question how the study of philosophy may be so ordered as not to be the ruin of the State: All great attempts are attended with risk; “hard is the good,” as men say.

Still, he said, let the point be cleared up, and the inquiry will then be complete.

e

I shall not be hindered, I said, by any want of will, but, if at all, by a want of power: my zeal you may see for yourselves; and please to remark in what I am about to say how boldly and unhesitatingly I declare that States should pursue philosophy, not as they do now, but in a different spirit.15

In what manner?

At present, I said, the students of philosophy are quite young; beginning when they are hardly past childhood, they devote only the time saved from money-making and housekeeping to such pursuits; and even those of them who are reputed to have most of the philosophic spirit, after they pursue for a time this most difficult subject—I mean dialectic—they abandon it. Later in life, when invited by someone else, they may, perhaps, go and hear a lecture, and about this they make much ado, for philosophy is not considered by them to be their proper business: at last, when they grow old, in most cases they are extinguished more truly than Heracleitus’s sun, inasmuch as they never light up again.ex

498
b

But what ought to be their course?

Just the opposite. In childhood and youth their study, and what philosophy they learn, should be suited to their tender years: during this period while they are growing up toward manhood, the chief and special care should be given to their bodies that they may have them to use in the service of philosophy; as life advances and the intellect begins to mature, let them increase the gymnastics of the soul; but when the strength of our citizens fails and is past civil and military duties, then let them range at will and engage in no serious labor, as we intend them to live happily here, and to crown this life with a similar happiness in another.

c

How truly in earnest you are, Socrates! he said; I am sure of that; and yet most of your hearers, if I am not mistaken, are likely to be still more earnest in their opposition to you, and will never be convinced; Thrasymachus least of all.

Do not make a quarrel, I said, between Thrasymachus and me, who have recently become friends, although, indeed, we were never enemies; for I shall go on striving to the utmost until I either convert him and other men, or do something which may profit them against the day when they live again, and hold the like discourse in another state of existence.16

d

You are speaking of a time which is not very near.

Rather, I replied, of a time which is as nothing in comparison with eternity. Nevertheless, I do not wonder that the many refuse to believe; for they have never seen that of which we are now speaking realized; they have seen only a conventional imitation of philosophy, consisting of words artificially brought together, not like these of ours having a natural unity. But a human being who in word and work is perfectly moulded, as far as he can be, into the proportion and likeness of virtue—such a man ruling in a city which bears the same image, they have never yet seen, neither one nor many of them—do you think that they ever did?

e
499

No indeed.

No, my friend, and they have seldom, if ever, heard free and noble sentiments; such as men utter when they are earnestly and by every means in their power seeking after truth for the sake of knowledge, while they look coldly on the subtleties of controversy, of which the end is opinion and strife, whether they meet with them in the courts of law or in society.

They are strangers, he said, to the words of which you speak.

And this was what we foresaw, and this was the reason why truth forced us to admit, not without fear and hesitation, that neither cities nor States nor individuals will ever attain perfection until the small class of philosophers whom we termed useless but not corrupt are providentially compelled, whether they will or not,17 to take care of the State, and until a like necessity be laid on the State to obey them; or until kings, or if not kings, the sons of kings or princes, are divinely inspired with a true love of true philosophy. That either or both of these alternatives are impossible, I see no reason to affirm: if they were so, we might indeed be justly ridiculed as dreamers and visionaries. Am I not right?

b
c

Quite right.

If then, in the countless ages of the past, or at the present hour in some foreign clime which is far away and beyond our ken, the perfected philosopher is or has been or hereafter shall be compelled by a superior power to have the charge of the State, we are ready to assert to the death, that this our constitution has been, and is—yea, and will be whenever the muse of philosophy is queen. There is no impossibility in all this; that there is a difficulty, we acknowledge ourselves.18

d

My opinion agrees with yours, he said.

But do you mean to say that this is not the opinion of the multitude?

I should imagine not, he replied.

O my friends, I said, do not attack the multitude: they will change their minds,19 if, not in an aggressive spirit, but gently and with the view of soothing them and removing their dislike of over-education, you show them your philosophers as they really are and describe as you were just now doing their character and profession, and then mankind will see that he of whom you are speaking is not such as they supposed—if they view him in this new light, they will surely change their notion of him, and answer in another strain. Who can be at enmity with one who loves him, who that is himself gentle and free from envy will be jealous of one in whom there is no jealousy? Nay, let me answer for you, that in a few this harsh temper may be found, but not in the majority of mankind.

e
500

I quite agree with you, he said.

And do you not also think, as I do, that the harsh feeling which the many entertain toward philosophy originates in the pretenders, who rush in uninvited, and are always abusing them, and finding fault with them, who make persons instead of things the theme of their conversation? and nothing can be more unbecoming in philosophers than this.

b

It is most unbecoming.

For he, Adeimantus, whose mind is fixed upon true being, has surely no time to look down upon the affairs of earth, or to be filled with malice and envy, contending against men; his eye is ever directed toward things fixed and immutable, which he sees neither injuring nor injured by one another, but all in order moving according to reason; these he imitates, and to these he will, as far as he can, conform himself. Can a man help imitating that with which he holds reverential converse?

c

Impossible.

And the philosopher holding converse with the divine order, becomes orderly and divine, as far as the nature of man allows; but like everyone else, he will suffer from detraction.

d

Of course.

And if a necessity be laid upon him of fashioning, not only himself, but human nature generally, whether in States or individuals, into that which he beholds elsewhere, will he, think you, be an unskilful artificer of justice, temperance, and every civil virtue?20

Anything but unskilful.

And if the world perceives that what we are saying about him is the truth, will they be angry with philosophy? Will they disbelieve us, when we tell them that no State can be happy which is not designed by artists who imitate the heavenly pattern?

e

They will not be angry if they understand, he said. But how will they draw out the plan of which you are speaking?

501

They will begin by taking the State and the manners of men, from which, as from a tablet, they will rub out the picture, and leave a clean surface.21 This is no easy task. But whether easy or not, herein will lie the difference between them and every other legislator—they will have nothing to do either with individual or State, and will inscribe no laws, until they have either found, or themselves made, a clean surface.

They will be very right, he said.

Having effected this, they will proceed to trace an outline of the constitution?

No doubt.

And when they are filling in the work, as I conceive, they will often turn their eyes upward and downward: I mean that they will first look at absolute justice and beauty and temperance, and again at the human copy; and will mingle and temper the various elements of life into the image of a man; and this they will conceive according to that other image, which, when existing among men, Homer calls the form and likeness of God.ey

b

Very true, he said.

And one feature they will erase, and another they will put in, until they have made the ways of men, as far as possible, agreeable to the ways of God?

c

Indeed, he said, in no way could they make a fairer picture.

And now, I said, are we beginning to persuade those whom you described as rushing at us with might and main, that the painter of constitutions is such a one as we were praising; at whom they were so very indignant because to his hands we committed the State; and are they growing a little calmer at what they have just heard?

Much calmer, if there is any sense in them.

Why, where can they still find any ground for objection? Will they doubt that the philosopher is a lover of truth and being?

d

They would not be so unreasonable.

Or that his nature, being such as we have delineated, is akin to the highest good?

Neither can they doubt this.

But again, will they tell us that such a nature, placed under favorable circumstances, will not be perfectly good and wise if any ever was? Or will they prefer those whom we have rejected?

Surely not.

e

Then will they still be angry at our saying, that, until philosophers bear rule, States and individuals will have no rest from evil, nor will this our imaginary State ever be realized?

I think that they will be less angry.

Shall we assume that they are not only less angry but quite gentle, and that they have been converted and for very shame, if for no other reason, cannot refuse to come to terms?

502

By all means, he said.

Then let us suppose that the reconciliation has been effected. Will anyone deny the other point, that there may be sons of kings or princes who are by nature philosophers?22

Surely no man, he said.

And when they have come into being will anyone say that they must of necessity be destroyed; that they can hardly be saved is not denied even by us; but that in the whole course of ages no single one of them can escape—who will venture to affirm this?

b

Who indeed!

But, said I, one is enough; let there be one man who has a city obedient to his will, and he might bring into existence the ideal polity about which the world is so incredulous.

Yes, one is enough.

The ruler may impose the laws and institutions which we have been describing, and the citizens may possibly be willing to obey them?

Certainly.

And that others should approve, of what we approve, is no miracle or impossibility?

I think not.

c

But we have sufficiently shown, in what has preceded, that all this, if only possible, is assuredly for the best.

We have.

And now we say not only that our laws, if they could be enacted, would be for the best, but also that the enactment of them, though difficult, is not impossible.

Very good.

And so with pain and toil we have reached the end of one subject, but more remains to be discussed; how and by what studies and pursuits will the saviours of the constitution be created, and at what ages are they to apply themselves to their several studies?

d

Certainly.

I omitted the troublesome business of the possession of women, and the procreation of children, and the appointment of the rulers, because I knew that the perfect State would be eyed with jealousy and was difficult of attainment; but that piece of cleverness was not of much service to me, for I had to discuss them all the same. The women and children are now disposed of, but the other question of the rulers must be investigated from the very beginning. We were saying, as you will remember, that they were to be lovers of their country,ez tried by the test of pleasures and pains, and neither in hardships, nor in dangers, nor at any other critical moment were to lose their patriotism—he was to be rejected who failed, but he who always came forth pure, like gold tried in the refiner’s fire, was to be made a ruler, and to receive honors and rewards in life and after death. This was the sort of thing which was being said, and then the argument turned aside and veiled its face; not liking to stir the question which has now arisen.

e
503
b

I perfectly remember, he said.

Yes, my friend, I said, and I then shrank from hazarding the bold word; but now let me dare to say—that the perfect guardian must be a philosopher.23

Yes, he said, let that be affirmed.

And do not suppose that there will be many of them;24 for the gifts which were deemed by us to be essential rarely grow together; they are mostly found in shreds and patches.

What do you mean? he said.

c

You are aware, I replied, that quick intelligence, memory, sagac ity, cleverness, and similar qualities, do not often grow together, and that persons who possess them and are at the same time high-spirited and magnanimous are not so constituted by nature as to live orderly and in a peaceful and settled manner; they are driven any way by their impulses, and all solid principle goes out of them.

Very true, he said.

On the other hand, those steadfast natures which can better be depended upon, which in a battle are impregnable to fear and immovable, are equally immovable when there is anything to be learned; they are always in a torpid state, and are apt to yawn and go to sleep over any intellectual toil.

d

Quite true.

And yet we were saying that both qualities were necessary in those to whom the higher education is to be imparted, and who are to share in any office or command.

Certainly, he said.

And will they be a class which is rarely found?

Yes, indeed.

Then the aspirant must not only be tested in those labors and dangers and pleasures which we mentioned before, but there is another kind of probation which we did not mention—he must be exercised also in many kinds of knowledge, to see whether the soul will be able to endure the highest of all, or will faint under them, as in any other studies and exercises.

e
504

Yes, he said, you are quite right in testing them. But what do you mean by the highest of all knowledge?

You may remember, I said, that we divided the soul into three parts; and distinguished the several natures of justice, temperance, courage, and wisdom?

Indeed, he said, if I had forgotten, I should not deserve to hear more.

And do you remember the word of caution which preceded the discussion of them?

To what do you refer?

We were saying, if I am not mistaken, that he who wanted to see them in their perfect beauty must take a longer and more circuitous way, at the end of which they would appear;25 but that we could add on a popular exposition of them on a level with the discussion which had preceded. And you replied that such an exposition would be enough for you, and so the inquiry was continued in what to me seemed to be a very inaccurate manner; whether you were satisfied or not, it is for you to say.

b

Yes, he said, I thought and the others thought that you gave us a fair measure of truth.

But, my friend, I said, a measure of such things which in any degree falls short of the whole truth is not fair measure; for nothing imperfect is the measure of anything, although persons are too apt to be contented and think that they need search no further.

c

Not an uncommon case when people are indolent.

Yes, I said; and there cannot be any worse fault in a guardian of the State and of the laws.

True.

The guardian then, I said, must be required to take the longer circuit, and toil at learning as well as at gymnastics, or he will never reach the highest knowledge of all which, as we were just now saying, is his proper calling.

d

What, he said, is there a knowledge still higher than this—higher than justice and the other virtues?

Yes, I said, there is. And of the virtues too we must behold not the outline merely, as at present—nothing short of the most finished picture should satisfy us. When little things are elaborated with an infinity of pains, in order that they may appear in their full beauty and utmost clearness, how ridiculous that we should not think the highest truths worthy of attaining the highest accuracy!

e

A right noble thought; but do you suppose that we shall refrain from asking you what is this highest knowledge?

Nay, I said, ask if you will; but I am certain that you have heard the answer many times, and now you either do not understand me or, as I rather think, you are disposed to be troublesome; for you have often been told that the idea of good is the highest knowledge, and that all other things become useful and advantageous only by their use of this.26 You can hardly be ignorant that of this I was about to speak, concerning which, as you have often heard me say, we know so little; and, without which, any other knowledge or possession of any kind will profit us nothing. Do you think that the possession of all other things is of any value if we do not possess the good? or the knowledge of all other things if we have no knowledge of beauty and goodness?

505
b

Assuredly not.

You are further aware that most people affirm pleasure to be the good,27 but the finer sort of wits say it is knowledge?

Yes.

And you are aware too that the latter cannot explain what they mean by knowledge, but are obliged after all to say knowledge of the good?

How ridiculous!

Yes, I said, that they should begin by reproaching us with our ignorance of the good, and then presume our knowledge of it—for the good they define to be knowledge of the good, just as if we understood them when they use the term “good”—this is of course ridiculous.

c

Most true, he said.

And those who make pleasure their good are in equal perplexity; for they are compelled to admit that there are bad pleasures as well as good.

Certainly.

And therefore to acknowledge that bad and good are the same? True.

d

There can be no doubt about the numerous difficulties in which this question is involved.

There can be none.

Further, do we not see that many are willing to do or to have or to seem to be what is just and honorable without the reality; but no one is satisfied with the appearance of good—the reality is what they seek; in the case of the good, appearance is despised by everyone.

Very true, he said.

Of this then, which every soul of man pursues and makes the end of all his actions, having a presentiment that there is such an end, and yet hesitating because neither knowing the nature nor having the same assurance of this as of other things, and therefore losing whatever good there is in other things—of a principle such and so great as this ought the best men in our State, to whom everything is intrusted, to be in the darkness of ignorance?

e
506

Certainly not, he said.

I am sure, I said, that he who does not know how the beautiful and the just are likewise good will be but a sorry guardian of them; and I suspect that no one who is ignorant of the good will have a true knowledge of them.

That, he said, is a shrewd suspicion of yours.

And if we only have a guardian who has this knowledge, our State will be perfectly ordered?

b

Of course, he replied; but I wish that you would tell me whether you conceive this supreme principle of the good to be knowledge or pleasure, or different from either?

Aye, I said, I knew all along that a fastidious gentleman like you would not be contented with the thoughts of other people about these matters.

True, Socrates; but I must say that one who like you has passed a lifetime in the study of philosophy should not be always repeating the opinions of others, and never telling his own.

c

Well, but has anyone a right to say positively what he does not know?

Not, he said, with the assurance of positive certainty; he has no right to do that: but he may say what he thinks, as a matter of opinion.

And do you not know, I said, that all mere opinions are bad, and the best of them blind? You would not deny that those who have any true notion without intelligence are only like blind men who feel their way along the road?

Very true.

And do you wish to behold what is blind and crooked and base, when others will tell you of brightness and beauty?

d

Still, I must implore you, Socrates, said Glaucon, not to turn away just as you are reaching the goal; if you will only give such an explanation of the good as you have already given of justice and temperance and the other virtues, we shall be satisfied.

Yes, my friend, and I shall be at least equally satisfied, but I cannot help fearing that I shall fail, and that my indiscreet zeal will bring ridicule upon me. No, sweet sirs, let us not at present ask what is the actual nature of the good, for to reach what is now in my thoughts would be an effort too great for me. But of the child of the good who is likest him, I would fain speak, if I could be sure that you wished to hear—otherwise, not.

e

By all means, he said, tell us about the child, and you shall remain in our debt for the account of the parent.

I do indeed wish, I replied, that I could pay, and you receive, the account of the parent, and not, as now, of the offspring only; take, however, this latter by way of interest,fa and at the same time have a care that I do not render a false account, although I have no intention of deceiving you.

507

Yes, we will take all the care that we can: proceed.

Yes, I said, but I must first come to an understanding with you, and remind you of what I have mentioned in the course of this discussion, and at many other times.

What?

b

The old story, that there is many a beautiful and many a good, and so of other things which we describe and define; to all of them the term “many” is implied.

True, he said.

And there is an absolute beauty and an absolute good, and of other things to which the term “many” is applied there is an absolute; for they may be brought under a single idea, which is called the essence of each.

Very true.

The many, as we say, are seen but not known, and the ideas are known but not seen.

Exactly.

And what is the organ with which we see the visible things?

c

The sight, he said.

And with the hearing, I said, we hear, and with the other senses perceive the other objects of sense?

True.

But have you remarked that sight is by far the most costly and complex piece of workmanship which the artificer of the senses ever contrived?28

No, I never have, he said.

Then reflect: has the ear or voice need of any third or additional nature in order that the one may be able to hear and the other to be heard?

d

Nothing of the sort.

No, indeed, I replied; and the same is true of most, if not all, the other senses—you would not say that any of them requires such an addition?

Certainly not.

But you see that without the addition of some other nature there is no seeing or being seen?

How do you mean?

Sight being, as I conceive, in the eyes, and he who has eyes wanting to see; color being also present in them, still unless there be a third nature specially adapted to the purpose, the owner of the eves will see nothing and the colors will be invisible.

e

Of what nature are you speaking?

Of that which you term light, I replied.

True, he said.

Noble, then, is the bond which links together sight and visibility, and great beyond other bonds by no small difference of nature; for light is their bond, and light is no ignoble thing?

508

Nay, he said, the reverse of ignoble.

And which, I said, of the gods in heaven would you say was the lord of this element? Whose is that light which makes the eye to see perfectly and the visible to appear?

You mean the sun, as you and all mankind say.

May not the relation of sight to this deityfb be described as follows?

How?

Neither sight nor the eye in which sight resides is the sun?

b

No.

Yet of all the organs of sense the eye is the most like the sun?

By far the most like.

And the power which the eye possesses is a sort of effluence which is dispensed from the sun?29

Exactly.

Then the sun is not sight, but the author of sight who is recognized by sight?

True, he said.

And this is he whom I call the child of the good, whom the good begat in his own likeness,fc to be in the visible world, in relation to sight and the things of sight, what the good is in the intellectual world in relation to mind and the things of mind. 30

c

Will you be a little more explicit? he said.

Why, you know, I said, that the eyes, when a person directs them toward objects on which the light of day is no longer shining, but the moon and stars only, see dimly, and are nearly blind; they seem to have no clearness of vision in them?

Very true.

But when they are directed toward objects on which the sun shines, they see clearly and there is sight in them?

d

Certainly.

And the soul is like the eye: when resting upon that on which truth and being shine, the soul perceives and understands, and is radiant with intelligence; but when turned toward the twilight of becoming and perishing, then she has opinion only, and goes blinking about, and is first of one opinion and then of another, and seems to have no intelligence?

Just so.

Now, that which imparts truth to the known and the power of knowing to the knower is what I would have you term the idea of good, and this you will deem to be the cause of science, and of truth in so far as the latter becomes the subject of knowledge; beautiful too, as are both truth and knowledge, you will be right in esteeming this other nature as more beautiful than either; and, as in the previous instance, light and sight may be truly said to be like the sun, and yet not to be the sun, so in this other sphere, science and truth may be deemed to be like the good, but not the good; the good has a place of honor yet higher.

e
509

What a wonder of beauty that must be, he said, which is the author of sciencefd and truth, and yet surpasses them in beauty; for you surely cannot mean to say that pleasure is the good?

God forbid, I replied; but may I ask you to consider the image in another point of view?

In what point of view?

b

You would say, would you not? that the sun is not only the author of visibility in all visible things, but of generation and nourishment and growth, though he himself is not generation?

Certainly.

In like manner the good may be said to be not only the author of knowledge to all things known, but of their being and essence, and yet the good is not essence, but far exceeds essence in dignity and power.

Glaucon said, with a ludicrous earnestness: By the light of heaven, how amazing!31

c

Yes, I said, and the exaggeration may be set down to you; for you made me utter my fancies.

And pray continue to utter them; at any rate let us hear if there is anything more to be said about the similitude of the sun.

Yes, I said, there is a great deal more.

Then omit nothing, however slight.

I will do my best, I said; but I should think that a great deal will have to be omitted.

I hope not, he said.

You have to imagine, then, that there are two ruling powers, and that one of them is set over the intellectual world, the other over the visible. I do not say heaven, lest you should fancy that I am playing upon the namefe May I suppose that you have this distinction of the visible and intelligible fixed in your mind?

d

I have.

Now take a line which has been cut into two unequal parts, and divide each of them again in the same proportion, and suppose the two main divisions to answer, one to the visible and the other to the intelligible, and then compare the subdivisions in respect of their clearness and want of clearness, and you will find that the first section in the sphere of the visible consists of images.32 And by images I mean, in the first place, shadows, and in the second place, reflections in water and in solid, smooth and polished bodies and the like: Do you understand?

e
510

Yes, I understand.

Imagine, now, the other section, of which this is only the resemblance, to include the animals which we see, and everything that grows or is made.

Very good.

Would you not admit that both the sections of this division have different degrees of truth, and that the copy is to the original as the sphere of opinion is to the sphere of knowledge?

Most undoubtedly.

b

Next proceed to consider the manner in which the sphere of the intellectual is to be divided.

In what manner?

Thus: There are two subdivisions, in the lower of which the soul uses the figures given by the former division as images; the inquiry can only be hypothetical, and instead of going upward to a principle descends to the other end; in the higher of the two, the soul passes out of hypotheses, and goes up to a principle which is above hypotheses, making no use of images as in the former case, but proceeding only in and through the ideas themselves.33

I do not quite understand your meaning, he said.

Then I will try again; you will understand me better when I have made some preliminary remarks. You are aware that students of geometry, arithmetic, and the kindred sciences assume the odd, and the even, and the figures, and three kinds of angles, and the like, in their several branches of science; these are their hypotheses, which they and everybody are supposed to know, and therefore they do not deign to give any account of them either to themselves or others; but they begin with them, and go on until they arrive at last, and in a consistent manner, at their conclusion?

c
d

Yes, he said, I know.

And do you not know also that although they make use of the visible forms and reason about them, they are thinking not of these, but of the ideals which they resemble; not of the figures which they draw, but of the absolute square and the absolute diameter, and so on—the forms which they draw or make, and which have shadows and reflections in water of their own, are converted by them into images, but they are really seeking to behold the things themselves, which can only be seen with the eye of the mind?

e
511

That is true.

And of this kind I spoke as the intelligible, although in the search after it the soul is compelled to use hypotheses; not ascending to a first principle, because she is unable to rise above the region of hypothesis, but employing the objects of which the shadows below are resemblances in their turn as images, they having in relation to the shadows and reflections of them a greater distinctness, and therefore a higher value.

I understand, he said, that you are speaking of the province of geometry and the sister arts.

b

And when I speak of the other division of the intelligible, you will understand me to speak of that other sort of knowledge which reason itself attains by the power of dialectic,34 using the hypotheses not as first principles, but only as hypotheses—that is to say, as steps and points of departure into a world which is above hypotheses, in order that she may soar beyond them to the first principle of the whole; and clinging to this and then to that which depends on this, by successive steps she descends again without the aid of any sensible object, from ideas, through ideas, and in ideas she ends.

c

I understand you, he replied; not perfectly, for you seem to me to be describing a task which is really tremendous; but, at any rate, I understand you to say that knowledge and being, which the science of dialectic contemplates, are clearer than the notions of the arts, as they are termed, which proceed from hypotheses only: these are also contemplated by the understanding, and not by the senses: yet, because they start from hypotheses and do not ascend to a principle, those who contemplate them appear to you not to exercise the higher reason upon them, although when a first principle is added to them they are cognizable by the higher reason. And the habit which is concerned with geometry and the cognate sciences I suppose that you would term understanding, and not reason, as being intermediate between opinion and reason.

d

You have quite conceived my meaning, I said; and now, corresponding to these four divisions, let there be four faculties in the soul—reason answering to the highest, understanding to the second, faith (or conviction) to the third, and perception of shadows to the last—and let there be a scale of them, and let us suppose that the several faculties have clearness in the same degree that their objects have truth.35

e

I understand, he replied, and give my assent, and accept your arrangement.

BOOK 7

AND NOW, I SAID, let me show in a figure how far our nature is enlightened or unenlightened: Behold! human beings living in an underground den,1 which has a mouth open toward the light and reaching all along the den; here they have been from their childhood, and have their legs and necks chained so that they cannot move, and can only see before them, being prevented by the chains from turning round their heads. Above and behind them a fire is blazing at a distance, and between the fire and the prisoners there is a raised way; and you will see, if you look, a low wall built along the way, like the screen which marionette-players have in front of them, over which they show the puppets.

514
b

I see.

And do you see, I said, men passing along the wall carrying all sorts of vessels, and statues and figures of animals made of wood and stone and various materials, which appear over the wall? Some of them are talking, others silent.

c
515

You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners.

Like ourselves, I replied; and they see only their own shadows, or the shadows of one another, which the fire throws on the opposite wall of the cave?

True, he said; how could they see anything but the shadows if they were never allowed to move their heads?

b

And of the objects which are being carried in like manner they would only see the shadows?

Yes, he said.

And if they were able to converse with one another, would they not suppose that they were naming what was actually before them?

Very true.

And suppose further that the prison had an echo which came from the other side, would they not be sure to fancy when one of the passers-by spoke that the voice which they heard came from the passing shadow?

No question, he replied.

To them, I said, the truth would be literally nothing but the shadows of the images.

c

That is certain.

And now look again, and see what will naturally follow if the prisoners are released and disabused of their error. At first, when any of them is liberated and compelled suddenly to stand up and turn his neck round and walk and look toward the light, he will suffer sharp pains; the glare will distress him, and he will be unable to see the realities of which in his former state he had seen the shadows; and then conceive someone saying to him, that what he saw before was an illusion, but that now, when he is approaching nearer to being and his eye is turned toward more real existence, he has a clearer vision—what will be his reply? And you may further imagine that his instructor is pointing to the objects as they pass and requiring him to name them—will he not be perplexed? Will he not fancy that the shadows which he formerly saw are truer than the objects which are now shown to him?

d

far truer.

And if he is compelled to look straight at the light, will he not have a pain in his eyes which will make him turn away to take refuge in the objects of vision which he can see, and which he will conceive to be in reality clearer than the things which are now being shown to him?

e

True, he said.

And suppose once more, that he is reluctantly dragged up a steep and rugged ascent,2 and held fast until he is forced into the presence of the sun himself, is he not likely to be pained and irritated? When he approaches the light his eyes will be dazzled, and he will not be able to see anything at all of what are now called realities.

516

Not all in a moment, he said.

He will require to grow accustomed to the sight of the upper world. And first he will see the shadows best, next the reflections of men and other objects in the water, and then the objects themselves; then he will gaze upon the light of the moon and the stars and the spangled heaven; and he will see the sky and the stars by night better than the sun or the light of the sun by day?

b

Certainly.

Last of all he will be able to see the sun, and not mere reflections of him in the water, but he will see him in his own proper place, and not in another; and he will contemplate him as he is.ff

Certainly.

He will then proceed to argue that this is he who gives the season and the years, and is the guardian of all that is in the visible world, and in a certain way the cause of all things which he and his fellows have been accustomed to behold?

c

Clearly, he said, he would first see the sun and then reason about him.

And when he remembered his old habitation, and the wisdom of the den and his fellow-prisoners, do you not suppose that he would felicitate himself on the change, and pity them?

Certainly, he would.

And if they were in the habit of conferring honors among themselves on those who were quickest to observe the passing shadows and to remark which of them went before, and which followed after, and which were together; and who were therefore best able to draw conclusions as to the future, do you think that he would care for such honors and glories, or envy the possessors of them? Would he not say with Homer, and to endure anything, rather than think as they do and live after their manner?

d
“Better to be the poor servant of a poor master,”fg

Yes, he said, I think that he would rather suffer anything than entertain these false notions and live in this miserable manner.

e

Imagine once more, I said, such a one coming suddenly out of the sun to be replaced in his old situation; would he not be certain to have his eyes full of darkness?

To be sure, he said.

And if there were a contest, and he had to compete in measuring the shadows with the prisoners who had never moved out of the den, while his sight was still weak, and before his eyes had become steady (and the time which would be needed to acquire this new habit of sight might be very considerable), would he not be ridiculous? Men would say of him that up he went and down he came without his eyes; and that it was better not even to think of ascending; and if anyone tried to loose another and lead him up to the light, let them only catch the offender, and they would put him to death.

517

wo question, he said.

This entire allegory, I said, you may now append, dear Glaucon, to the previous argument; the prison-house is the world of sight, the light of the fire is the sun, and you will not misapprehend me if you interpret the journey upward to be the ascent of the soul into the intellectual world, in my view, at least, which, at your desire, I have expressed—whether rightly or wrongly, God knows.3 But, whether true or false, my opinion is that in the world of knowledge the idea of good appears last of all, and is seen only with an effort; and, when seen, is also inferred to be the universal author of all things beautiful and right, parent of light and of the lord of light in this visible world, and the immediate source of reason and truth in the intellectual; and that this is the power upon which he who would act rationally either in public or private life must have his eye fixed.

b
c

I agree, he said, as far as I am able to understand you. Moreover, I said, you must not wonder that those who attain to this beatific vision are unwilling to descend to human affairs; for their souls are ever hastening into the upper world where they desire to dwell; which desire of theirs is very natural, if our allegory may be trusted.

d

Yes, very natural.

And is there anything surprising in one who passes from divine contemplations to the degraded state of man, behaving himself in a ridiculous manner; if, while his eyes are blinking and before he has become accustomed to the surrounding darkness, he is compelled to fight in courts of law, or in other places, about the images or the shadows of images of justice, and is endeavoring to meet the conceptions of those who have never yet seen absolute justice?

e

Anything but surprising, he replied.

Anyone who has common sense will remember that the bewilderments of the eyes are of two kinds, and arise from two causes, either from coming out of the light or from going into the light, which is true of the mind’s eye, quite as much as of the bodily eye; and he who remembers this when he sees anyone whose vision is perplexed and weak, will not be too ready to laugh; he will first ask whether that soul of man has come out of the brighter life, and is unable to see because unaccustomed to the dark, or having turned from darkness to the day is dazzled by excess of light. And he will count the one happy in his condition and state of being, and he will pity the other; or, if he have a mind to laugh at the soul which comes from below into the light, there will be more reason in this than in the laugh which greets him who returns from above out of the light into the den.

518
b

That, he said, is a very just distinction.

But then, if I am right, certain professors of education4 must be wrong when they say that they can put a knowledge into the soul which was not there before, like sight into blind eyes.

c

They undoubtedly say this, he replied.

Whereas, our argument shows that the power and capacity of learning exists in the soul already; and that just as the eye was unable to turn from darkness to light without the whole body, so too the instrument of knowledge can only by the movement of the whole soul be turned from the world of becoming into that of being, and learn by degrees to endure the sight of being, and of the brightest and best of being, or, in other words, of the good.

d

Very true.

And must there not be some art which will effect conversion in the easiest and quickest manner; not implanting the faculty of sight, for that exists already, but has been turned in the wrong direction, and is looking away from the truth?

Yes, he said, such an art may be presumed.

And whereas the other so-called virtues of the soul seem to be akin to bodily qualities, for even when they are not originally innate they can be implanted later by habit and exercise, the virtue of wisdom more than anything else contains a divine element which always remains, and by this conversion is rendered useful and profitable; or, on the other hand, hurtful and useless. Did you never observe the narrow intelligence flashing from the keen eye of a clever rogue—how eager he is, how clearly his paltry soul sees the way to his end; he is the reverse of blind, but his keen eyesight is forced into the service of evil, and he is mischievous in proportion to his cleverness?

e
519

Very true, he said.

But what if there had been a circumcision of such natures in the days of their youth;fh and they had been severed from those sensual pleasures, such as eating and drinking, which, like leaden weights, were attached to them at their birth, and which drag them down and turn the vision of their souls upon the things that are below—if, I say, they had been released from these impediments and turned in the opposite direction, the very same faculty in them would have seen the truth as keenly as they see what their eyes are turned to now.

b

Very likely.

Yes, I said; and there is another thing which is likely, or rather a necessary inference from what has preceded, that neither the uneducated and uninformed of the truth, nor yet those who never make an end of their education, will be able ministers of the State; not the former, because they have no single aim of duty which is the rule of all their actions, private as well as public; nor the latter, because they will not act at all except upon compulsion, fancying that they are already dwelling apart in the islands of the blessed. fi

c

Very true, he replied.

Then, I said, the business of us who are the founders of the State will be to compel the best minds to attain that knowledge which we have already shown to be the greatest of all—they must continue to ascend until they arrive at the good; but when they have ascended and seen enough we must not allow them to do as they do now

d

What do you mean?

I mean that they remain in the upper world: but this must not be allowed; they must be made to descend again among the prisoners in the den, and partake of their labors and honors, whether they are worth having or not.

But is not this unjust? he said; ought we to give them a worse life, when they might have a better?

You have again forgotten, my friend, I said, the intention of the law,fj which did not aim at making any one class in the State happy above the rest; the happiness was to be in the whole State, and he held the citizens together by persuasion and necessity, making them benefactors of the State, and therefore benefactors of one another; to this end he created them, not to please themselves, but to be his instruments in binding up the State.

e
520

True, he said, I had forgotten.

Observe, Glaucon, that there will be no injustice in compelling our philosophers to have a care and providence of others; we shall explain to them that in other States, men of their class are not obliged to share in the toils of politics: and this is reasonable, for they grow up at their own sweet will, and the government would rather not have them. Being self-taught, they cannot be expected to show any gratitude for a culture which they have never received. But we have brought you into the world to be rulers of the hive, kings of yourselves and of the other citizens, and have educated you far better and more perfectly than they have been educated, and you are better able to share in the double duty. Wherefore each of you, when his turn comes, must go down to the general underground abode, and get the habit of seeing in the dark.5 When you have acquired the habit, you will see ten thousand times better than the inhabitants of the den, and you will know what the several images are, and what they represent, because you have seen the beautiful and just and good in their truth. And thus our State, which is also yours, will be a reality, and not a dream only, and will be administered in a spirit unlike that of other States, in which men fight with one another about shadows only and are distracted in the struggle for power, which in their eyes is a great good. Whereas the truth is that the State in which the rulers are most reluctant to govern is always the best and most quietly governed, and the State in which thev are most eager, the worst.

b
c
d

Quite true, he replied.

And will our pupils, when they hear this, refuse to take their turn at the toils of State, when they are allowed to spend the greater part of their time with one another in the heavenly light?

Impossible, he answered; for they are just men, and the commands which we impose upon them are just; there can be no doubt that every one of them will take office as a stern necessity, and not after the fashion of our present rulers of State.

e

Yes, my friend, I said; and there lies the point. You must contrive for your future rulers another and a better life than that of a ruler, and then you may have a well-ordered State; for only in the State which offers this, will they rule who are truly rich, not in silver and gold, but in virtue and wisdom, which are the true blessings of life. Whereas, if they go to the administration of public affairs, poor and hungering after their own private advantage, thinking that hence they are to snatch the chief good, order there can never be; for they will be fighting about office, and the civil and domestic broils which thus arise will be the ruin of the rulers themselves and of the whole State.

521

Most true, he replied.

And the only life which looks down upon the life of political ambition is that of true philosophy Do you know of any other?

b

Indeed, I do not, he said.

And those who govern ought not to be lovers of the task? For, if they are, there will be rival lovers, and they will fight.

No question.

Who, then, are those whom we shall compel to be guardians? Surely they will be the men who are wisest about affairs of State, and by whom the State is best administered, and who at the same time have other honors and another and a better life than that of politics?

They are the men, and I will choose them, he replied.

And now shall we consider in what way such guardians will be produced, and how they are to be brought from darkness to light—as some are said to have ascended from the world below to the gods?6

c

By all means, he replied.

The process, I said, is not the turning over of an oyster-shell,7 but the turning round of a soul passing from a day which is little better than night to the true day of being, that is, the ascent from below, which we affirm to be true philosophy?

Quite so.

And should we not inquire what sort of knowledge has the power of effecting such a change?

d

Certainly.

What sort of knowledge is there which would draw the soul from becoming to being? And another consideration has just occurred to me: You will remember that our young men are to be warrior athletes?

Yes, that was said.

Then this new kind of knowledge must have an additional quality?

What quality?

Usefulness in war.8

Yes, if possible.

There were two parts in our former scheme of education, were there not?

e

Just so.

There was gymnastics, which presided over the growth and decay of the body, and may therefore be regarded as having to do with generation and corruption?

True.

Then that is not the knowledge which we are seeking to discover?

No.

522

But what do you say of music, what also entered to a certain extent into our former scheme?

Music,fk he said, as you will remember, was the counterpart of gymnastics, and trained the guardians by the influences of habit, by harmony making them harmonious, by rhythm rhythmical, but not giving them science; and the words, whether fabulous or possibly true, had kindred elements of rhythm and harmony in them. But in music there was nothing which tended to that good which you are now seeking.

b

You are most accurate, I said, in your recollection; in music there certainly was nothing of the kind. But what branch of knowledge is there, my dear Glaucon, which is of the desired nature; since all the useful arts were reckoned mean by us?

Undoubtedly; and yet if music and gymnastics are excluded, and the arts are also excluded, what remains?

Well, I said, there may be nothing left of our special subjects; and then we shall have to take something which is not special, but of the universal application.

What may that be?

A something which all arts and sciences and intelligences use in common, and which everyone first has to learn among the elements of education.

c

What is that?

The little matter of distinguishing one, two, and three—in a word, number and calculation: do not all arts and sciences necessarily partake of them?9

Yes.

Then the art of war partakes of them?

To be sure.

Then Palamedes,fl whenever he appears in tragedy, proves Agamemnon ridiculously unfit to be a general. Did you never remark how he declares that he had invented number, and had numbered the ships and set in array the ranks of the army at Troy; which implies that they had never been numbered before, and Agamemnon must be supposed literally to have been incapable of counting his own fleet—how could he if he was ignorant of number? And if that is true, what sort of general must he have been?

d

I should say a very strange one, if this was as you say.

Can we deny that a warrior should have a knowledge of arithmetic?

e

Certainly he should, if he is to have the smallest understanding of military tactics, or indeed, I should rather say, if he is to be a man at all.

I should like to know whether you have the same notion which I have of this study?

What is your notion?

It appears to me to be a study of the kind which we are seeking, and which leads naturally to reflection, but never to have been rightly used; for the true use of it is simply to draw the soul toward being.10

523

Will you explain your meaning? he said.

I will try, I said; and I wish you would share the inquiry with me, and say “yes” or “no” when I attempt to distinguish in my own mind what branches of knowledge have this attracting power, in order that we may have clearer proof that arithmetic is, as I suspect, one of them.

Explain, he said.

I mean to say that objects of sense are of two kinds; some of them do not invite thought because the sense is an adequate judge of them; while in the case of other objects sense is so untrustworthy that further inquiry is imperatively demanded.

b

You are clearly referring, he said, to the manner in which the senses are imposed upon by distance, and by painting in light and shade.

No, I said, that is not at all my meaning.

Then what is your meaning?

When speaking of uninviting objects, I mean those which do not pass from one sensation to the opposite; inviting objects are those which do; in this latter case the sense coming upon the object, whether at a distance or near, does not reveal any particular attribute more clearly than its opposite. An illustration will make my meaning clearer: here are three fingers—a little finger, a second finger, and a middle finger.

c

Very good.

You may suppose that they are seen quite close: And here comes the point.

What is it?

Each of them equally appears a finger, whether seen in the middle or at the extremity, whether white or black, or thick or thin—it makes no difference; a finger is a finger all the same. In these cases a man is not compelled to ask of thought the question, What is a finger? for the sight never intimates to the mind that a finger is other than a finger.

d

True.

And therefore, I said, as we might expect, there is nothing here which invites or excites intelligence.

e

There is not, he said.

But is this equally true of the greatness and smallness of the fingers ? Can sight adequately perceive them? and is no difference made by the circumstance that one of the fingers is in the middle and the other at the extremity? And in like manner does the touch adequately perceive the qualities of thickness or thinness, of softness or hardness? And so of the other senses; do they give perfect intimations of such matters? Is not their mode of operation on this wise—the sense which is concerned with the quality of hardness is necessarily concerned also with the quality of softness, and only intimates to the soul that the same thing is felt to be both hard and soft?

524

You are quite right, he said.

And must not the soul be perplexed at this intimation which the sense gives of a hard which is also soft? What, again, is the meaning of light and heavy, if that which is light is also heavy, and that which is heavy, light?

Yes, he said, these intimations which the soul receives are very curious and require to be explained.

b

Yes, I said, and in these perplexities the soul naturally summons to her aid calculation and intelligence, that she may see whether the several objects announced to her are one or two.

True.

And if they turn out to be two, is not each of them one and different?

Certainly.

And if each is one, and both are two, she will conceive the two as in a state of division, for if they were undivided they could only be conceived of as one?

c

True.

The eye certainly did see both small and great, but only in a confused manner; they were not distinguished.

Yes.

Whereas the thinking mind, intending to light up the chaos, was compelled to reverse the process, and look at small and great as separate and not confused.

Very true.

Was not this the beginning of the inquiry, “What is great?” and “What is small?”

Exactly so.

And thus arose the distinction of the visible and the intelligible.

Most true.

d

This was what I meant when I spoke of impressions which invited the intellect, or the reverse—those which are simultaneous with opposite impressions, invite thought; those which are not simultaneous do not.

I understand, he said, and agree with you.

And to which class do unity and number belong?11

I do not know, he replied.

Think a little and you will see that what has preceded will supply the answer; for if simple unity could be adequately perceived by the sight or by any other sense, then, as we were saying in the case of the finger, there would be nothing to attract toward being; but when there is some contradiction always present, and one is the reverse of one and involves the conception of plurality, then thought begins to be aroused within us, and the soul perplexed and wanting to arrive at a decision asks, “What is absolute unity?”12 This is the way in which the study of the one has a power of drawing and converting the mind to the contemplation of true being.

e
525

And surely, he said, this occurs notably in the case of one; for we see the same thing to be both one and infinite in multitude?

Yes, I said; and this being true of one must be equally true of all number?

Certainly.

And all arithmeticfm and calculation have to do with number?

Yes.

And they appear to lead the mind toward truth?

b

Yes, in a very remarkable manner.

Then this is knowledge of the kind for which we are seeking, having a double use, military and philosophical; for the man of war must learn the art of number or he will not know how to array his troops, and the philosopher also must learn it, because he has to rise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being, or else he will never become a true reckoner.

That is true.

And our guardian is both warrior and philosopher?

Certainly.

Then this is a kind of knowledge which legislation may fitly prescribe; and we must endeavor to persuade those who are to be the principal men of our State to go and learn arithmetic, not as amateurs, but they must carry on the study until they see the nature of numbers with the mind only; nor again, like merchants or retail-traders, with a view to buying or selling, but for the sake of their military use, and of the soul herself; and because this will be the easiest way for her to pass from becoming to truth and being.

That is excellent, he said.

c

Yes, I said, and now having spoken of it, I must add how charming the science is! and in how many ways it conduces to our desired end, if pursued in the spirit of a philosopher, and not of a shopkeeper!

d

How do you mean?

I mean, as I was saying, that arithmetic has a very great and elevating effect, compelling the soul to reason about abstract number, and rebelling against the introduction of visible or tangible objects into the argument. You know how steadily the masters of the art repel and ridicule anyone who attempts to divide absolute unity13 when he is calculating, and if you divide, they multiply, taking care that one shall continue one and not become lost in fractions.

e

That is very true.

Now, suppose a person were to say to them: O my friends, what are these wonderful numbers about which you are reasoning, in which, as you say, there is a unity such as you demand, and each unit is equal, invariable, indivisible—what would they answer?

526

They would answer, as I should conceive, that they were speaking of those numbers which can only be realized in thought.

Then you see that this knowledge may be truly called necessary, necessitating as it clearly does the use of the pure intelligence in the attainment of pure truth?

b

Yes; that is a marked characteristic of it.

And have you further observed that those who have a natural talent for calculation are generally quick at every other kind of knowledge; and even the dull, if they have had an arithmetical training, although they may derive no other advantage from it, always become much quicker than they would otherwise have been?

Very true, he said.

And indeed, you will not find many studies more difficult, nor will you find them easily.

c

You will not.

And, for all these reasons, arithmetic is a kind of knowledge in which the best natures should be trained, and which must not be given up.

I agree.

Let this then be made one of our subjects of education. And next, shall we inquire whether the kindred science also concerns us?

You mean geometry?fn

Exactly so.

Clearly, he said, we are concerned with that part of geometry which relates to war; for in pitching a camp or taking up a position or closing or extending the lines of an army, or any other military manoeuvre, whether in actual battle or on a march, it will make all the difference whether a general is or is not a geometrician.

Yes, I said, but for that purpose a very little of either geometry or calculation will be enough; the question relates rather to the greater and more advanced part of geometry—whether that tends in any degree to make more easy the vision of the idea of good; and thither, as I was saying, all things tend which compel the soul to turn her gaze toward that place, where is the full perfection of being, which she ought, by all means, to behold.

d
e

True, he said.

Then if geometry compels us to view being, it concerns us; if becoming only, it does not concern us?

Yes, that is what we assert.

Yet anybody who has the least acquaintance with geometry will not deny that such a conception of the science is in flat contradiction to the ordinary language of geometricians.

527

How so?

They have in view practice only, and are always speaking, in a narrow and ridiculous manner, of squaring and extending and applying and the like—they confuse the necessities of geometry with those of daily life; whereas knowledge is the real object of the whole science.14

b

Certainly, he said.

Then must not a further admission be made?

What admission?

That the knowledge at which geometry aims is knowledge of the eternal, and not of aught perishing and transient.

That, he replied, may be readily allowed, and is true.

Then, my noble friend, geometry will draw the soul toward truth, and create the spirit of philosophy, and raise up that which is now unhappily allowed to fall down.

Nothing will be more likely to have such an effect.

Then nothing should be more sternly laid down than that the inhabitants of your fair city should by all means learn geometry Moreover, the science has indirect effects, which are not small.

c

Of what kind? he said.

There are the military advantages of which you spoke, I said; and in all departments of knowledge, as experience proves, anyone who has studied geometry is infinitely quicker of apprehension than one who has not.

Yes, indeed, he said, there is an infinite difference between them.

Then shall we propose this as a second branch of knowledge which our youth will study?

Let us do so, he replied.

And suppose we make astronomy the third—what do you say?

d

I am strongly inclined to it, he said; the observation of the seasons and of months and years is as essential to the general as it is to the farmer or sailor.

I am amused, I said, at your fear of the world, which makes you guard against the appearance of insisting upon useless studies;15 and I quite admit the difficulty of believing that in every man there is an eye of the soul which, when by other pursuits lost and dimmed, is by these purified and reillumined; and is more precious far than ten thousand bodily eyes, for by it alone is truth seen. Now there are two classes of persons: one class of those who will agree with you and will take your words as a revelation; another class to whom they will be utterly unmeaning, and who will naturally deem them to be idle tales, for they see no sort of profit which is to be obtained from them. And therefore you had better decide at once with which of the two you are proposing to argue. You will very likely say with neither, and that your chief aim in carrying on the argument is your own improvement; at the same time you do not grudge to others any benefit which they may receive.

e
528

I think that I should prefer to carry on the argument mainly on my own behalf.

Then take a step backward, for we have gone wrong in the order of the sciences.16

What was the mistake? he said.

After plane geometry, I said, we proceeded at once to solids in revolution, instead of taking solids in themselves; whereas after the second dimension, the third, which is concerned with cubes and dimensions of depth, ought to have followed.

b

That is true, Socrates; but so little seems to be known as yet about these subjects.17

Why, yes, I said, and for two reasons: in the first place, no government patronizes them; this leads to a want of energy in the pursuit of them, and they are difficult; in the second place, students cannot learn them unless they have a director. But then a director can hardly be found, and, even if he could, as matters now stand, the students, who are very conceited, would not attend to him. That, however, would be otherwise if the whole State became the director of these studies and gave honor to them; then disciples would want to come, and there would be continuous and earnest search, and discoveries would be made; since even now, disregarded as they are by the world, and maimed of their fair proportions, and although none of their votaries can tell the use of them, still these studies force their way by their natural charm, and very likely, if they had the help of the State, they would some day emerge into light.

c

Yes, he said, there is a remarkable charm in them. But I do not clearly understand the change in the order. First you began with a geometry of plane surfaces?

d

Yes, I said.

And you placed astronomy next, and then you made a step backward?

Yes, and I have delayed you by my hurry; the ludicrous state of solid geometry, which, in natural order, should have followed, made me pass over this branch and go on to astronomy, or motion of solids.

e

True, he said.

Then assuming that the science now omitted would come into existence if encouraged by the State, let us go on to astronomy, which will be fourth.

The right order, he replied. And now, Socrates, as you rebuked the vulgar manner in which I praised astronomy before, my praise shall be given in your own spirit. For everyone, as I think, must see that astronomy compels the soul to look upward and leads us from this world to another.

Everyone but myself, I said; to everyone else this may be clear, but not to me.

529

And what, then, would you say?

I should rather say that those who elevate astronomy into philosophy appear to me to make us look downward, and not upward.

What do you mean? he asked.

You, I replied, have in your mind a truly sublime conception of our knowledge of the things above. And I dare say that if a person were to throw his head back and study the fretted ceiling, you would still think that his mind was the percipient, and not his eyes. And you are very likely right, and I may be a simpleton: but, in my opinion, that knowledge only which is of being and of the unseen can make the soul look upward, and whether a man gapes at the heavens or blinks on the ground, seeking to learn some particular of sense, I would deny that he can learn, for nothing of that sort is matter of science;18 his soul is looking downward, not upward, whether his way to knowledge is by water or by land, whether he floats or only lies on his back.

b
c

I acknowledge, he said, the justice of your rebuke. Still, I should like to ascertain how astronomy can be learned in any manner more conducive to that knowledge of which we are speaking?

I will tell you, I said: The starry heaven which we behold is wrought upon a visible ground, and therefore, although the fairest and most perfect of visible things, must necessarily be deemed inferior far to the true motions of absolute swiftness and absolute slowness, which are relative to each other, and carry with them that which is contained in them, in the true number and in every true figure. Now, these are to be apprehended by reason and intelligence, but not by sight.

d

True, he replied.

The spangled heavens should be used as a pattern and with a view to that higher knowledge; their beauty is like the beauty of figures or pictures excellently wrought by the hand of Dædalus,fo or some other great artist, which we may chance to behold; any geometrician who saw them would appreciate the exquisiteness of their workmanship, but he would never dream of thinking that in them he could find the true equal or the true double, or the truth of any other proportion.

e
530

No, he replied, such an idea would be ridiculous.

And will not a true astronomer have the same feeling when he looks at the movements of the stars? Will he not think that heaven and the things in heaven are framed by the Creatorfp of them in the most perfect manner? But he will never imagine that the proportions of night and day, or of both to the month, or of the month to the year, or of the stars to these and to one another, and any other things that are material and visible can also be eternal and subject to no deviation—that would be absurd; and it is equally absurd to take so much pains in investigating their exact truth.

b

I quite agree, though I never thought of this before.

Then, I said, in astronomy, as in geometry, we should employ problems, and let the heavens alone if we would approach the subject in the right way and so make the natural gift of reason to be of any real use.

c

That, he said, is a work infinitely beyond our present astronomers. Yes, I said; and there are many other things which must also have a similar extension given to them, if our legislation is to be of any value. But can you tell me of any other suitable study?

No, he said, not without thinking.

Motion, I said, has many forms, and not one only; two of them are obvious enough even to wits no better than ours; and there are others, as I imagine, which may be left to wiser persons.

d

But where are the two?

There is a second, I said, which is the counterpart of the one already named.19

And what may that be?

The second, I said, would seem relatively to the ears to be what the first is to the eyes; for I conceive that as the eyes are designed to look up at the stars, so are the ears to hear harmonious motions; and these are sister sciences—as the Pythagoreans say,20 and we, Glaucon, agree with them?

Yes, he replied.

But this, I said, is a laborious study, and therefore we had better go and learn of them; and they will tell us whether there are any other applications of these sciences. At the same time, we must not lose sight of our own higher object.

e

What is that?

There is a perfection which all knowledge ought to reach, and which our pupils ought also to attain, and not to fall short of, as I was saying that they did in astronomy. For in the science of harmony, as you probably know, the same thing happens. The teachers of harmony compare the sounds and consonances which are heard only, and their labor, like that of the astronomers, is in vain.21

Yes, by heaven! he said; and ‘tis as good as a play to hear them talking about their condensed notes, as they call them;22 they put their ears close alongside of the strings like persons catching a sound from their neighbor’s s wall—one set of them declaring that they distinguish an intermediate note and have found the least interval which should be the unit of measurement;23 the others insisting that the two sounds have passed into the same—either party setting their ears before their understanding.

531
b

You mean, I said, those gentlemen who tease and torture the strings and rack them on the pegs of the instrument: I might carry on the metaphor and speak after their manner of the blows which the plectrum24 gives, and make accusations against the strings, both of backwardness and forwardness to sound; but this would be tedious, and therefore I will only say that these are not the men, and that I am referring to the Pythagoreans, of whom I was just now proposing to inquire about harmony. For they too are in error, like the astronomers; they investigate the numbers of the harmonies which are heard, but they never attain to problems—that is to say, they never reach the natural harmonies of number, or reflect why some numbers are harmonious and others not.

c

That, he said, is a thing of more than mortal knowledge.

A thing, I replied, which I would rather call useful; that is, if sought after with a view to the beautiful and good; but if pursued in any other spirit, useless.

Very true, he said.

Now, when all these studies reach the point of intercommunion and connection with one another, and come to be considered in their mutual affinities, then, I think, but not till then, will the pursuit of them have a value for our objects; otherwise there is no profit in them.

d

I suspect so; but you are speaking, Socrates, of a vast work.

What do you mean? I said; the prelude, or what?25 Do you not know that all this is but the prelude to the actual strain which we have to learn? For you surely would not regard the skilled mathematician as a dialectician?26

e

Assuredly not, he said; I have hardly ever known a mathematician who was capable of reasoning.

But do you imagine that men who are unable to give and take a reason will have the knowledge which we require of them?

Neither can this be supposed.

And so, Glaucon, I said, we have at last arrived at the hymn of dialectic. This is that strain which is of the intellect only, but which the faculty of sight will nevertheless be found to imitate; for sight, as you may remember, was imagined by us after a while to behold the real animals and stars, and last of all the sun himself. And so with dialectic; when a person starts on the discovery of the absolute by the light of reason only, and without any assistance of sense, and perseveres until by pure intelligence he arrives at the perception of the absolute good, he at last finds himself at the end of the intellectual world, as in the case of sight at the end of the visible.

532
b

Exactly, he said.

Then this is the progress which you call dialectic?

True.

But the release of the prisoners from chains, and their translation from the shadows to the images and to the light, and the ascent from the underground den to the sun, while in his presence they are vainly trying to look on animals and plants and the light of the sun, but are able to perceive even with their weak eyes the images in the water (which are divine), and are the shadows of true existence (not shadows of images cast by a light of fire, which compared with the sun is only an image)—this power of elevating the highest principle in the soul to the contemplation of that which is best in existence, with which we may compare the raising of that faculty which is the very light of the body to the sight of that which is brightest in the material and visible world—this power is given, as I was saying, by all that study and pursuit of the arts which have been described.

c
d

I agree in what you are saying, he replied, which may be hard to believe, yet, from another point of view, is harder still to deny. This, however, is not a theme to be treated of in passing only, but will have to be discussed again and again. And so, whether our conclusion be true or false, let us assume all this, and proceed at once from the prelude or preamble to the chief strain, and describe that in like manner.27 Say, then, what is the nature and what are the divisions of dialectic, and what are the paths which lead thither; for these paths will also lead to our final rest.

Dear Glaucon, I said, you will not be able to follow me here, though I would do my best, and you should behold not an image only, but the absolute truth, according to my notion. Whether what I told you would or would not have been a reality I cannot venture to say; but you would have seen something like reality; of that I am confident.

e
533

Doubtless, he replied.

But I must also remind you that the power of dialectic alone can reveal this, and only to one who is a disciple of the previous sciences.

Of that assertion you may be as confident as of the last.

And assuredly no one will argue that there is any other method of comprehending by any regular process all true existence, or of ascertaining what each thing is in its own nature; for the arts in general are concerned with the desires or opinions of men, or are cultivated with a view to production and construction, or for the preservation of such productions and constructions; and as to the mathematical sciences which, as we were saying, have some apprehension of true being—geometry and the like—they only dream about being, but never can they behold the waking reality so long as they leave the hypotheses which they use unexamined, and are unable to give an account of them. For when a man knows not his own first principle, and when the conclusion and intermediate steps are also constructed out of he knows not what, how can he imagine that such a fabric of convention can ever become science?

b
c

Impossible, he said.

Then dialectic, and dialectic alone, goes directly to the first principle and is the only science which does away with hypotheses in order to make her ground secure; the eye of the soul, which is literally buried in an outlandish slough, is by her gentle aid lifted upward; and she uses as handmaids and helpers in the work of conversion, the sciences which we have been discussing. Custom terms them sciences,28 but they ought to have some other name, implying greater clearness than opinion and less clearness than science: and this, in our previous sketch, was called understanding. But why should we dispute about names when we have realities of such importance to consider?

d
e

Why, indeed, he said, when any name will do which expresses the thought of the mind with clearness?

At any rate, we are satisfied, as before, to have four divisions; two for intellect and two for opinion, and to call the first division science, the second understanding, the third belief, and the fourth perception of shadows, opinion being concerned with becoming, and intellect with being; and so to make a proportion:

534
“As being is to becoming, so is pure intellect to opinion.
And as intellect is to opinion, so is science to belief, and understanding to the perception of shadows.“fq

But let us pass over the correlations of the objects that each faculty apprehends and their respective subdivisions, for it will be a long inquiry, many times longer than this has been.

As far as I understand, he said, I agree.

b

And do you also agree, I said, in describing the dialectician as one who attains a conception of the essence of each thing? And he who does not possess and is therefore unable to impart this conception, in whatever degree he is unable, may in that degree also be said to fail in intelligence? Will you admit so much?

Yes, he said; how can I deny it?

And you would say the same of the conception of the good? Until the person is able to abstract and define rationally the idea of good, and unless he can run the gauntlet of all objections, and is ready to disprove them, not by appeals to opinion, but to absolute truth, never faltering at any step of the argument—unless he can do all this, you would say that he knows neither the idea of good nor any other good; he apprehends only a shadow, if anything at all, which is given by opinion, and not by science;fr dreaming and slumbering in this life, before he is well awake here, he arrives at the world below, and has his final quietus.

c
d

In all that I should most certainly agree with you.

And surely you would not have the children of your ideal State, whom you are nurturing and educating—if the ideal ever becomes a reality—you would not allow the future rulers to be like posts, having no reason in them, and yet to be set in authority over the highest matters?29

Certainly not.

Then you will make a law that they shall have such an education as will enable them to attain the greatest skill in asking and answering questions?

Yes, he said, you and I together will make it.

e

Dialectic, then, as you will agree, is the coping-stone of the sciences, and is set over them; no other science can be placed higher—the nature of knowledge can no further go?

535

I agree, he said.

But to whom we are to assign these studies, and in what way they are to be assigned, are questions which remain to be considered.

Yes, clearly.

You remember, I said, how the rulers were chosen before?fs Certainly, he said.

The same natures must still be chosen, and the preference again given to the surest and the bravest, and, if possible, to the fairest; and, having noble and generous tempers, they should also have the natural gifts which will facilitate their education.

b

And what are these?

Such gifts as keenness and ready powers of acquisition; for the mind more often faints from the severity of study than from the severity of gymnastics: the toil is more entirely the mind’s own, and is not shared with the body.

Very true, he replied.

Further, he of whom we are in search should have a good memory, and be an unwearied solid man who is a lover of labor in any line; or he will never be able to endure the great amount of bodily exercise and to go through all the intellectual discipline and study which we require of him.

c

Certainly, he said; he must have natural gifts.

The mistake at present is that those who study philosophy have no vocation, and this, as I was before saying, is the reason why she has fallen into disrepute: her true sons should take her by the hand, and not bastards.

What do you mean?

In the first place, her votary should not have a lame or halting industry—I mean, that he should not be half industrious and half idle: as, for example, when a man is a lover of gymnastics and hunting, and all other bodily exercises, but a hater rather than a lover of the labor of learning or listening or inquiring. Or the occupation to which he devotes himself may be of an opposite kind, and he may have the other sort of lameness.

d

Certainly, he said.

And as to truth, I said, is not a soul equally to be deemed halt and lame which hates voluntary falsehood and is extremely indignant at herself and others when they tell lies, but is patient of involuntary falsehood, and does not mind wallowing like a swinish beast in the mire of ignorance, and has no shame at being de tected?

e

To be sure.

And, again, in respect of temperance, courage, magnificence,ft and every other virtue, should we not carefully distinguish between the true son and the bastard? for where there is no discernment of such qualities, States and individuals unconsciously err; and the State makes a ruler, and the individual a friend, of one who, being defective in some part of virtue, is in a figure lame or a bastard.

536

That is very true, he said.

b

All these things, then, will have to be carefully considered by us; and if only those whom we introduce to this vast system of education and training are sound in body and mind, justice herself will have nothing to say against us, and we shall be the saviours of the constitution and of the State; but, if our pupils are men of another stamp, the reverse will happen, and we shall pour a still greater flood of ridicule on philosophy than she has to endure at present.

That would not be creditable.

Certainly not, I said; and yet perhaps, in thus turning jest into earnest I am equally ridiculous.

In what respect?

C

I had forgotten, I said, that we were not serious, and spoke with too much excitement. For when I saw philosophy so undeservedly trampled under foot of men30 I could not help feeling a sort of indignation at the authors of her disgrace: and my anger made me too vehement.

d

Indeed! I was listening, and did not think so.

But I, who am the speaker, felt that I was. And now let me remind you that, although in our former selectionfu we chose old men, we must not do so in this. Solonfv was under a delusion when he said that a man when he grows old may learn many things—for he can no more learn much than he can run much; youth is the time for any extraordinary toil.

e

Of course.

And, therefore, calculation and geometry and all the other elements of instruction, which are a preparation for dialectic, should be presented to the mind in childhood; not, however, under any notion of forcing our system of education.

Why not?

Because a freeman ought not to be a slave in the acquisition of knowledge of any kind. Bodily exercise, when compulsory, does no harm to the body; but knowledge which is acquired under compulsion obtains no hold on the mind.

Very true.

Then, my good friend, I said, do not use compulsion, but let early education be a sort of amusement; you will then be better able to find out the natural bent.

537

That is a very rational notion, he said.

Do you remember that the children, too, were to be taken to see the battle on horseback;fw and that if there were no danger they were tc be brought close up and, like young hounds, have a taste of blood given them?

Yes, I remember.

The same practice may be followed, I said, in all these things—labors, lessons, dangers—and he who is most at home in all of them ought to be enrolled in a select number.

At what age?

b

At the age when the necessary gymnastics are over: the period, whether of two or three years, which passes in this sort of training is useless for any other purpose; for sleep and exercise are unpro pitious to learning; and the trial of who is first in gymnastic exercises is one of the most important tests to which our youth are subjected.

Certainly, he replied.

After that time those who are selected from the class of twenty years old will be promoted to higher honor, and the sciences which they learned without any order in their early education will now be brought together, and they will be able to see the natural relationship of them to one another and to true being.

c

Yes, he said, that is the only kind of knowledge which takes lasting root.

Yes, I said; and the capacity for such knowledge is the great criterion of dialectical talent: the comprehensive mind is always the dialectical.

I agree with you, he said.

These, I said, are the points which you must consider; and those who have most of this comprehension, and who are most steadfast in their learning, and in their military and other appointed duties, when they have arrived at the age of thirty will have to be chosen by you out of the select class, and elevated to higher honor; and you will have to prove them by the help of dialectic, in order to learn which of them is able to give up the use of sight and the other senses, and in company with truth to attain absolute being: And here, my friend, great caution is required.

d

Why great caution?

Do you not remark, I said, how great is the evil which dialectic has introduced?31

e

What evil? he said.

The students of the art are filled with lawlessness.

Quite true, he said.

Do you think that there is anything so very unnatural or inexcusable in their case? or will you make allowance for them?

In what way make allowance?

I want you, I said, by way of parallel, to imagine a suppositi tious son who is brought up in great wealth; he is one of a great and numerous family, and has many flatterers. When he grows up to manhood, he learns that his alleged are not his real parents; but who the real are he is unable to discover. Can you guess how he will be likely to behave toward his flatterers and his supposed parents, first of all during the period when he is ignorant of the false relation, and then again when he knows? Or shall I guess for you?

538

If you please.

Then I should say that while he is ignorant of the truth he will be likely to honor his father and his mother and his supposed relations more than the flatterers; he will be less inclined to neglect them when in need, or to do or say anything against them; and he will be less willing to disobey them in any important matter.

b

He will.

But when he has made the discovery, I should imagine that he would diminish his honor and regard for them, and would become more devoted to the flatterers; their influence over him would greatly increase; he would now live after their ways, and openly associate with them, and, unless he were of an unusually good disposition, he would trouble himself no more about his supposed parents or other relations.

c

Well, all that is very probable. But how is the image applicable to the disciples of philosophy?

In this way: you know that there are certain principles about justice and honor, which were taught us in childhood, and under their parental authority we have been brought up, obeying and honoring them.

That is true.

There are also opposite maxims and habits of pleasure which flatter and attract the soul, but do not influence those of us who have any sense of right, and they continue to obey and honor the maxims of their fathers.

d

True.

Now, when a man is in this state, and the questioning spirit asks what is fair or honorable, and he answers as the legislator has taught him, and then arguments many and diverse refute his words, until he is driven into believing that nothing is honorable any more than dishonorable, or just and good any more than the reverse, and so of all the notions which he most valued, do you think that he will still honor and obey them as before?

e

Impossible.

And when he ceases to think them honorable and natural as heretofore, and he fails to discover the true, can he be expected to pursue any life other than that which flatters his desires?

539

He cannot.

And from being a keeper of the law he is converted into a breaker of it?

Unquestionably.

Now all this is very natural in students of philosophy such as I have described, and also, as I was just now saying, most excusable.

Yes, he said; and, I may add, pitiable.

Therefore, that your feelings may not be moved to pity about our citizens who are now thirty years of age, every care must be taken in introducing them to dialectic.

Certainly.

There is a danger lest they should taste the dear delight too early; for youngsters, as you may have observed, when they first get the taste in their mouths, argue for amusement, and are always contradicting and refuting others in imitation of those who refute them; like puppy-dogs, they rejoice in pulling and tearing at all who come near them.

b

Yes, he said, there is nothing which they like better.

And when they have made many conquests and received defeats at the hands of many, they violently and speedily get into a way of not believing anything which they believed before, and hence, not only they, but philosophy and all that relates to it is apt to have a bad name with the rest of the world.

c

Too true, he said.

But when a man begins to get older, he will no longer be guilty of such insanity; he will imitate the dialectician who is seeking for truth, and not the eristic,fx who is contradicting for the sake of amusement; and the greater moderation of his character will increase instead of diminishing the honor of the pursuit.

d

Very true, he said.

And did we not make special provision for this, when we said that the disciples of philosophy were to be orderly and steadfast, not, as now, any chance aspirant or intruder?

Very true.

Suppose, I said, the study of philosophy to take the place of gymnastics and to be continued diligently and earnestly and exclusively for twice the number of years which were passed in bodily exercise—will that be enough?

Would you say six or four years? he asked.

e

Say five years, I replied; at the end of the time they must be sent down again into the den and compelled to hold any military or other office which young men are qualified to hold: in this way they will get their experience of life, and there will be an opportunity of trying whether, when they are drawn all manner of ways by temptation, they will stand firm or flinch.

540

And how long is this stage of their lives to last?

Fifteen years, I answered; and when they have reached fifty years of age, then let those who still survive and have distinguished themselves in every action of their lives, and in every branch of knowledge, come at last to their consummation: the time has now arrived at which they must raise the eye of the soul to the universal light which lightens all things, and behold the absolute good; for that is the pattern according to which they are to order the State and the lives of individuals, and the remainder of their own lives also; making philosophy their chief pursuit, but, when their turn comes, toiling also at politics and ruling for the public good, doing this not as if it were something fine but as a necessary task;fy and when they have brought up in each generation others like themselves and left them in their place to be governors of the State, then they will depart to the Islands of the Blessed and dwell there; and the city will give them public memorials and sacrifices and honor them, if the Pythian oraclefz consent, as demigods, but if not, as in any case blessed and divine.

b
c

You are a sculptor, Socrates, and have made statues of our governors faultless in beauty.

Yes, I said, Glaucon, and of our governesses too;ga for you must not suppose that what I have been saying applies to men only and not to women as far as their natures can go.

There you are right, he said, since we have made them to share in all things like the men.

Well, I said, and you would agree (would you not?) that what has been said about the State and the government is not a mere dream, and although difficult, not impossible;gb but only possible in the way which has been supposed; that is to say, when the true philosopher-kings are born in a State, one or more of them, despising the honors of this present world which they deem mean and worthless, esteeming above all things right and the honor that springs from right, and regarding justice as the greatest and most necessary of all things, whose ministers they are, and whose principles will be exalted by them when they set in order their own city?

d
e

How will they proceed?

541

They will begin by sending out into the country all the inhabitants of the city who are more than ten years old, and will take possession of their children, who will be unaffected by the habits of their parents; these they will train in their own habits and laws, I mean in the laws which we have given them: and in this way the State and constitution of which we were speaking will soonest and most easily attain happiness, and the nation which has such a constitution will gain most.

b

Yes, that will be the best way. And I think, Socrates, that you have very well described how, if ever, such a constitution might come into being.

Enough, then, of the perfect State, and of the man who bears its image—there is no difficulty in seeing how we shall describe him.

There is no difficulty, he replied; and I agree with you in thinking that nothing more need be said.

BOOK 8

AND SO, GLAUCON, WE have arrived at the conclusion that in the perfect State wives and children are to be in common; and that all education and the pursuits of war and peace are also to be common, and the best philosophers and the bravest warriors are to be their kings?

543

That, replied Glaucon, has been acknowledged.

Yes, I said; and we have further acknowledged that the governors, when appointed themselves, will take their soldiers and place them in houses such as we were describing, which are common to all, and contain nothing private, or individual; and about their property, you remember what we agreed?

b

Yes, I remember that no one was to have any of the ordinary possessions of mankind; they were to be warrior athletes and guardians, receiving from the other citizens, in lieu of annual payment, only their maintenance, and they were to take care of themselves and of the whole State.

C

True, I said; and now that this division of our task is concluded, let us find the point at which we digressed, that we may return into the old path.gc

There is no difficulty in returning; you implied, then as now, that you had finished the description of the State: you said that such a State was good, and that the man was good who answered to it, although, as now appears, you had more excellent things to relate both of State and man. And you said further, that if this was the true form, then the others were false; and of the false forms, you said, as I remember, that there were four principal ones, and that their defects, and the defects of the individuals corresponding to them, were worth examining. When we had seen all the individuals, and finally agreed as to who was the best and who was the worst of them, we were to consider whether the best was not also the happiest, and the worst the most miserable. I asked you what were the four forms of government of which you spoke, and then Polemarchus and Adeimantus put in their word; and you began again, and have found your way to the point at which we have now arrived.

d
544
b

Your recollection, I said, is most exact.

Then, like a wrestler,gd he replied, you must put yourself again in the same position; and let me ask the same questions, and do you give me the same answer which you were about to give me then.

Yes, if I can, I will, I said.

I shall particularly wish to hear what were the four constitutions of which you were speaking.

That question, I said, is easily answered: the four governments of which I spoke, so far as they have distinct names, are first, those of Crete and Sparta, which are generally applauded;1 what is termed oligarchy comes next; this is not equally approved, and is a form of government which teems with evils: thirdly, democracy, which naturally follows oligarchy, although very different: and lastly comes tyranny, great and famous, which differs from them all, and is the fourth and worst disorder of a State. I do not know, do you? of any other constitution which can be said to have a distinct character. There are lordships and principalities which are bought and sold, and some other intermediate forms of government. But these are nondescripts and may be found equally among Hellenes and among barbarians.

c
d

Yes, he replied, we certainly hear of many curious forms of government which exist among them.

Do you know, I said, that governments vary as the dispositions of men vary, and that there must be as many of the one as there are of the other? For we cannot suppose that States are made of “oak and rock,”ge and not out of the human natures which are in them, and which in a figure turn the scale and draw other things after them?

e

Yes, he said, the States are as the men are; they grow out of human characters.

Then if the constitutions of States are five, the dispositions of individual minds will also be five?

Certainly.

Him who answers to aristocracy, and whom we rightly call just and good, we have already described.

We have.

Then let us now proceed to describe the inferior sort of natures, being the contentious and ambitious, who answer to the Spartan polity; also the oligarchical, democratical, and tyrannical. Let us place the most just by the side of the most unjust, and when we see them we shall be able to compare the relative happiness or unhappiness of him who leads a life of pure justice or pure injustice. The inquiry will then be completed. And we shall know whether we ought to pursue injustice, as Thrasymachus advises,gf or in accordance with the conclusions of the argument to prefer justice.

545
b

Certainly, he replied, we must do as you say.

Shall we follow our old plan, which we adopted with a view to clearness, of taking the State first and then proceeding to the individual, and begin with the government of honor?—I know of no name for such a government other than timocracy or perhaps timarchy.gg We will compare with this the like character in the individual; and, after that, consider oligarchy and the oligarchical man; and then again we will turn our attention to democracy and the democratical man; and lastly, we will go and view the city of tyranny, and once more take a look into the tyrant’s soul, and try to arrive at a satisfactory decision.

c

That way of viewing and judging of the matter will be very suitable.

First, then, I said, let us inquire how timocracy (the government of honor) arises out of aristocracy (the government of the best).gh Clearly, all political changes originate in divisions of the actual governing power; a government which is united, however small, cannot be moved.2

d

Very true, he said.

In what way, then, will our city be moved, and in what manner will the two classes of auxiliaries and rulers disagree among themselves or with one another? Shall we, after the manner of Homer, pray the muses to tell us “how discord first arose”?gi Shall we imagine them in solemn mockery, to play and jest with us as if we were children, and to address us in a lofty tragic vein, making believe to be in earnest?3

e

How would they address us?

After this manner: A city which is thus constituted can hardly be shaken; but, seeing that everything which has a beginning has also an end, even a constitution such as yours will not last forever, but will in time be dissolved. And this is the dissolution: In plants that grow in the earth, as well as in animals that move on the earth’s surface, fertility and sterility of soul and body occur when the circumferences of the circles of each are completed, which in short-lived existences pass over a short space, and in long-lived ones over a long space.4 But to the knowledge of human fecundity and sterility all the wisdom and education of your rulers will not attain; the laws which regulate them will not be discovered by an intelligence which is alloyed with sense, but will escape them, and they will bring children into the world when they ought not. Now that which is of divine birthgj has a period which is contained in a perfect number,gk but the period of human birth is comprehended in a number5 in which first increments by involution and evolution (or squared and cubed)gl obtaining three intervals and four termsgm of like and unlike, waxing and waning numbers,gn make all the terms commensurable and agreeable to one another. The base of these with a third added, when combined with five and raised to the third power, furnishes two harmonies,go the first a square which is 100 times as great,gp and the other a figure having one side equal to the former, but oblong, consisting of 100 numbers squared upon rational diameters of a square (i.e., omitting fractions), the side of which is five, each of them being less by onegq or less by two perfect squares of irrational diameters;gr and 100 cubes of three.gs Now this number represents a geometrical figure which has control over the good and evil of births.6 For when your guardians are ignorant of the law of births, and unite bride and bridegroom out of season, the children will not be goodly or fortunate. And though only the best of them will be appointed by their predecessor, still they will be unworthy to hold their father’s places, and when they come into power as guardians they will soon be found to fail in taking care of us, the muses, first by undervaluing music;gt which neglect will soon extend to gymnastics; and hence the young men of your State will be less cultivated. In the succeeding generation rulers will be appointed who have lost the guardian power of testing the metal of your different races, which, like Hesiod‘s, are of gold and silver and brass and iron.gu And so iron will be mingled with silver, and brass with gold, and hence there will arise dissimilarity and inequality and irregularity, which always and in all places are causes of hatred and war. This the Muses affirm to be the stock from which discord has sprung, wherever arising; and this is their answer to us.

546
b
c
d
e
547

Yes, and we may assume that they answer truly.

Why, yes, I said, of course they answer truly; how can the Muses speak falsely?

And what do the Muses say next?

b

When discord arose, then the two races were drawn different ways: the iron and brass fell to acquiring money, and land, and houses, and gold, and silver; but the gold and silver races, not wanting money, but having the true riches in their own nature, inclined toward virtue and the ancient order of things. There was a battle between them, and at last they agreed to distribute their land and houses among individual owners; and they enslaved their friends and maintainers, whom they had formerly protected in the condition of freemen, and made of them subjects and servants; and they themselves were engaged in war and in keeping a watch against them.7

c

I believe that you have rightly conceived the origin of the change.

And the new government which thus arises will be of a form intermediate between oligarchy and aristocracy?

Very true.

Such will be the change, and after the change has been made, how will they proceed? Clearly, the new State, being in a mean between oligarchy and the perfect State, will partly follow one and partly the other, and will also have some peculiarities.

d

True, he said.

In the honor given to rulers, in the abstinence of the warrior-class from agriculture, handicrafts, and trade in general, in the institution of common meals, and in the attention paid to gymnastics and military training—in all these respects this State will resemble the former.8

True.

But in the fear of admitting philosophers to power, because they are no longer to be had simple and earnest, but are made up of mixed elements; and in turning from them to passionate and less complex characters, who are by nature fitted for war rather than peace; and in the value set by them upon military stratagems and contrivances, and in the waging of everlasting wars—this State will be for the most part peculiar.

e
548

Yes.

Yes, I said; and men of this stamp will be covetous of money, like those who live in oligarchies; they will have a fierce secret longing after gold and silver, which they will hoard in dark places, having magazines and treasuries of their own for the deposit and concealment of them; also castles which are just nests for their eggs, and in which they will spend large sums on their wives, or on any others whom they please.

b

That is most true, he said.

And they are miserly because they have no means of openly acquiring the money which they prize; they will spend that which is another man’s on the gratification of their desires, stealing their pleasures and running away like children from the law, their father: they have been schooled not by gentle influences but by force, for they have neglected her who is the true muse, the companion of reason and philosophy, and have honored gymnastics more than music.

c

Undoubtedly, he said, the form of government which you describe is a mixture of good and evil.

Why, there is a mixture, I said; but one thing, and one thing only, is predominantly seen—the spirit of contention and ambition; and these are due to the prevalence of the passionate or spirited element.

Assuredly, he said.

Such is the origin and such the character of this State, which has been described in outline only; the more perfect execution was not required, for a sketch is enough to show the type of the most perfectly just and most perfectly unjust; and to go through all the States and all the characters of men, omitting none of them, would be an interminable labor.

d

Very true, he replied.

Now what man answers to this form of government—how did he come into being, and what is he like?

I think, said Adeimantus, that in the spirit of contention which characterizes him, he is not unlike our friend Glaucon.

Perhaps, I said, he may be like him in that one point; but there are other respects in which he is very different.

e

In what respects?

He should have more of self -assertion and be less cultivated and yet a friend of culture; and he should be a good listener but no speaker. Such a person is apt to be rough with slaves, unlike the educated man, who is too proud for that; and he will also be courteous to freemen, and remarkably obedient to authority; he is a lover of power and a lover of honor; claiming to be a ruler, not because he is eloquent, or on any ground of that sort, but because he is a soldier and has performed feats of arms; he is also a lover of gymnastic exercises and of the chase.

Yes, that is the type of character that answers to timocracy.

Such a one will despise riches only when he is young; but as he gets older he will be more and more attracted to them, because he has a piece of the avaricious nature in him, and is not single-minded toward virtue, having lost his best guardian.9

549
b

Who was that? said Adeimantus.

Philosophy, I said, tempered with music, who comes and takes up her abode in a man, and is the only saviour of his virtue throughout life.

Good, he said.

Such, I said, is the timocratical youth, and he is like the timocratical State.

Exactly.

His origin is as follows: 10 He is often the young son of a brave father, who dwells in an ill-governed city, of which he declines the honors and offices, and will not go to law, or exert himself in any way, but is ready to waive his rights in order that he may escape trouble.

c

And how does the son come into being?

The character of the son begins to develop when he hears his mother complaining that her husband has no place in the government, of which the consequence is that she has no precedence among other women. Further, when she sees her husband not very eager about money, and instead of battling and railing in the law courts or assembly, taking whatever happens to him quietly; and when she observes that his thoughts always centre in himself, while he treats her with very considerable indifference, she is annoyed, and says to her son that his father is only half a man and far too easy-going: adding all the other complaints about her own ill-treatment which women are so fond of rehearsing.

d
e

Yes, said Adeimantus, they give us plenty of them, and their complaints are so like themselves.

And you know, I said, that the old servants also, who are supposed to be attached to the family, from time to time talk privately in the same strain to the son; and if they see anyone who owes money to his father, or is wronging him in any way, and he fails to prosecute them, they tell the youth that when he grows up he must retaliate upon people of this sort, and be more of a man than his father. He has only to walk abroad and he hears and sees the same sort of thing: those who do their own business in the city are called simpletons, and held in no esteem, while the busy-bodies are honored and applauded. The result is that the young man, hearing and seeing all these things—hearing, too, the words of his father, and having a nearer view of his way of life, and making comparisons of him and others—is drawn opposite ways: while his father is watering and nourishing the rational principle in his soul, the others are encouraging the passionate and appetitive; and he being not originally of a bad nature, but having kept bad company, is at last brought by their joint influence to a middle point, and gives up the kingdom which is within him to the middle principle of con tentiousness and passion, and becomes arrogant and ambitious.

550
b

You seem to me to have described his origin perfectly.

Then we have now, I said, the second form of government and the second type of character?

c

We have.

Next, let us look at another man who, as Æschylus says, or rather, as our plan requires, begin with the State.

“Is set over against another State;”gv

By all means.

I believe that oligarchy follows next in order.

And what manner of government do you term oligarchy?

A government resting on a valuation of property, in which the rich have power and the poor man is deprived of it.

d

1 understand, he replied.

Ought I not to begin by describing how the change from timocracy to oligarchy arises?

Yes.

Well, I said, no eyes are required in order to see how the one passes into the other.

How?

The accumulation of gold in the treasury of private individuals is the ruin of timocracy; they invent illegal modes of expenditure; for what do they or their wives care about the law?

Yes, indeed.

And then one, seeing another grow rich, seeks to rival him, and thus the great mass of the citizens become lovers of money.

e

Likely enough.

And so they grow richer and richer, and the more they think of making a fortune the less they think of virtue; for when riches and virtue are placed together in the scales of the balance the one always rises as the other falls.11

True.

And in proportion as riches and rich men are honored in the State, virtue and the virtuous are dishonored.

551

Clearly.

And what is honored is cultivated, and that which has no honor is neglected.

That is obvious.

And so at last, instead of loving contention and glory, men become lovers of trade and money; they honor and look up to the rich man, and make a ruler of him, and dishonor the poor man.

They do so.

They next proceed to make a law which fixes a sum of money as the qualification of citizenship;12 the sum is higher in one place and lower in another, as the oligarchy is more or less exclusive; and they allow no one whose property falls below the amount fixed to have any share in the government. These changes in the constitution they effect by force of arms, if intimidation has not already done their work.

b

Very true.

And this, speaking generally, is the way in which oligarchy is established.

Yes, he said; but what are the characteristics of this form of government, and what are the defects of which we were speaking?gw

c

First of all, I said, consider the nature of the qualification. Just think what would happen if pilots were to be chosen according to their property, and a poor man were refused permission to steer, even though he were a better pilot?

You mean that they would shipwreck?

Yes; and is not this true of the government of anything?

I should imagine so.

Except a city?—or would you include a city?

Nay, he said, the case of a city is the strongest of all, inasmuch as the rule of a city is the greatest and most difficult of all.

This, then, will be the first great defect of oligarchy?

d

Clearly.

And here is another defect which is quite as bad.

What defect?

The inevitable division: such a State is not one, but two States, the one of poor, the other of rich men; and they are living on the same spot and always conspiring against one another.13

That, surely, is at least as bad.

Another discreditable feature is, that, for a like reason, they are incapable of carrying on any war. Either they arm the multitude, and then they are more afraid of them than of the enemy; or, if they do not call them out in the hour of battle, they are oligarchs indeed, few to fight as they are few to rule. And at the same time their fondness for money makes them unwilling to pay taxes.

e

How discreditable!

And, as we said before, under such a constitution the same persons have too many callings—they are husbandmen, tradesmen, warriors, all in one. Does that look well?

552

Anything but well.

There is another evil which is, perhaps, the greatest of all, and to which this State first begins to be liable.

What evil?

A man may sell all that he has, and another may acquire his property; yet after the sale he may dwell in the city of which he is no longer a part, being neither trader, nor artisan, nor horseman, nor hoplite,14 but only a poor, helpless creature.

Yes, that is an evil which also first begins in this State.

b

The evil is certainly not prevented there; for oligarchies have both the extremes of great wealth and utter poverty.

True.

But think again: In his wealthy days, while he was spending his money, was a man of this sort a whit more good to the State for the purposes of citizenship? Or did he only seem to be a member of the ruling body, although in truth he was neither ruler nor subject, but just a spendthrift?

As you say, he seemed to be a ruler, but was only a spendthrift.

May we not say that this is the drone in the house who is like the drone in the honeycomb, and that the one is the plague of the city as the other is of the hive?15

c

Just so, Socrates.

And God has made the flying drones, Adeimantus, all without stings, whereas of the walking drones he has made some without stings, but others have dreadful stings; of the stingless class are those who in their old age end as paupers; of the stingers come all the criminal class, as they are termed.

d

Most true, he said.

Clearly then, whenever you see paupers in a State, somewhere in that neighborhood there are hidden away thieves and cut purses and robbers of temples, and all sorts of malefactors.

Clearly.

Well, I said, and in oligarchical States do you not find paupers?

Yes, he said; nearly everybody is a pauper who is not a ruler.

And may we be so bold as to affirm that there are also many criminals to be found in them, rogues who have stings, and whom the authorities are careful to restrain by force?

e

Certainly, we may be so bold.

The existence of such persons is to be attributed to want of education, ill-training, and an evil constitution of the State?

True.

Such, then, is the form and such are the evils of oligarchy; and there may be many other evils.

Very likely.

Then oligarchy, or the form of government in which the rulers are elected for their wealth, may now be dismissed. Let us next proceed to consider the nature and origin of the individual who answers to this State.

553

By all means.

Does not the timocratical man change into the oligarchical on this wise?

How?

A time arrives when the representative of timocracy has a son: at first he begins by emulating his father and walking in his foot-steps, but presently he sees him of a sudden foundering against the State as upon a sunken reef, and he and all that he has are lost; he may have been a general or some other high officer who is brought to trial under a prejudice raised by informers, and either put to death or exiled or deprived of the privileges of a citizen, and all his property taken from him.

b

Nothing more likely.

And the son has seen and known all this—he is a ruined man, and his fear has taught him to knock ambition and passion head-foremost from his bosom’s throne; humbled by poverty he takes to money-making, and by mean and miserly savings and hard work gets a fortune together. Is not such a one likely to seat the concupiscent and covetous element on the vacant throne and to suffer it to play the great king within him, girt with tiara and chain and scimitar?

c

Most true, he replied.

And when he has made reason and spirit sit down on the ground obediently on either side of their sovereign, and taught them to know their place, he compels the one to think only of how lesser sums may be turned into larger ones, and will not allow the other to worship and admire anything but riches and rich men, or to be ambitious of anything so much as the acquisition of wealth and the means of acquiring it.

d

There is no swifter nor surer way of changing an ambitious youth into an avaricious one.

And the avaricious, I said, is the oligarchical youth?

e

Yes, he said; at any rate the individual out of whom he came is like the State out of which oligarchy came.

Let us then consider whether there is any likeness between them.

Very good.

554

First, then, they resemble one another in the value which they set upon wealth?

Certainly.

Also in their penurious, laborious character; the individual only satisfies his necessary appetites,gx and confines his expenditure to them; his other desires he subdues, under the idea that they are unprofitable.

True.

He is a shabby fellow, who saves something out of everything and makes a purse for himself; and this is the sort of man whom the vulgar applaud. Is he not a true image of the State which he represents?

He appears to me to be so; at any rate money is highly valued bv him as well as bv the State.

b

You see that he is not a man of cultivation, I said.

I imagine not, he said; had he been educated he would never have made a blind godgy director of his chorus, or given him chief honor.

Excellent! I said. Yet consider: Must we not further admit that owing to this want of cultivation there will be found in him drone-like desires as of pauper and rogue, which are forcibly kept down by his general habit of life?

c

True.

Do you know where you will have to look if you want to discover his rogueries?

Where must I look?

You should see him where he has some great opportunity of acting dishonestly, as in the guardianship of an orphan.

Aye.

It will be clear enough then that in his ordinary dealings which give him a reputation for honesty, he coerces his bad passions by an enforced virtue; not making them see that they are wrong, or taming them by reason, but by necessity and fear constraining them, and because he trembles for his possessions.

d

To be sure.

Yes, indeed, my dear friend, but you will find that the natural desires of the drone commonly exist in him all the same whenever he has to spend what is not his own.

Yes, and they will be strong in him, too.

The man, then, will be at war with himself; he will be two men, and not one;16 but, in general, his better desires will be found to prevail over his inferior ones.

e

True.

For these reasons such a one will be more respectable than most people; yet the true virtue of a unanimous and harmonious soul will flee far away and never come near him.

I should expect so.

And surely the miser individually will be an ignoble competitor in a State for any prize of victory, or other object of honorable ambition; he will not spend his money in the contest for glory; so afraid is he of awakening his expensive appetites and inviting them to help and join in the struggle; in true oligarchical fashion he fights with a small part only of his resources, and the result commonly is that he loses the prize and saves his money.

555

Very true.

Can we any longer doubt, then, that the miser and money-maker answers to the oligarchical State?

b

There can be no doubt.

Next comes democracy; of this the origin and nature have still to be considered by us; and then we will inquire into the ways of the democratic man, and bring him up for judgment.

That, he said, is our method.

Well, I said, and how does the change from oligarchy into democracy arise? Is it not on this wise: the good at which such a State aims is to become as rich as possible, a desire which is insatiable?

What then?

The rulers being aware that their power rests upon their wealth, refuse to curtail by law the extravagance of the spendthrift youth because they gain by their ruin; they take interest from them and buy up their estates and thus increase their own wealth and importance?

c

To be sure.

There can be no doubt that the love of wealth and the spirit of moderation cannot exist together in citizens of the same State to any considerable extent; one or the other will be disregarded.

d

That is tolerably clear.

And in oligarchical States, from the general spread of carelessness and extravagance, men of good family have often been reduced to beggary?

Yes, often.

And still they remain in the city; there they are, ready to sting and fully armed, and some of them owe money, some have forfeited their citizenship; a third class are in both predicaments; and they hate and conspire against those who have got their property, and against everybody else, and are eager for revolution.

e

That is true.

On the other hand, the men of business, stooping as they walk, and pretending not even to see those whom they have already ruined, insert their sting—that is, their money—into someone else who is not on his guard against them, and recover the parent sumgz many times over multiplied into a family of children: and so they make drone and pauper to abound in the State.

556

Yes, he said, there are plenty of them—that is certain.

The evil blazes up like a fire; and they will not extinguish it either by restricting a man’s use of his own property, or by another remedy.17

What other?

One which is the next best, and has the advantage of compelling the citizens to look to their characters: Let there be a general rule that everyone shall enter into voluntary contracts at his own risk, and there will be less of this scandalous money-making, and the evils of which we were speaking will be greatly lessened in the State.

b

Yes, they will be greatly lessened.

At present the governors, induced by the motives which I have named, treat their subjects badly; while they and their adherents, especially the young men of the governing class, are habituated to lead a life of luxury and idleness both of body and mind; they do nothing, and are incapable of resisting either pleasure or pain.

c

Very true.

They themselves care only for making money, and are as indifferent as the pauper to the cultivation of virtue.

Yes, quite as indifferent.

Such is the state of affairs which prevails among them. And often rulers and their subjects may come in one another’s way, whether on a journey or on some other occasion of meeting, on a pilgrimage or a march, as fellow-soldiers or fellow-sailors; aye, and they may observe the behavior of each other in the very moment of danger—for where danger is, there is no fear that the poor will be despised by the rich—and very likely the wiry, sunburnt poor man may be placed in battle at the side of a wealthy one who has never spoilt his complexion and has plenty of superfluous flesh—when he sees such a one puffing and at his wits‘-end, how can he avoid drawing the conclusion that men like him are only rich because no one has the courage to despoil them? And when they meet in private will not people be saying to one another, “Our warriors are not good for much”?

d
e

Yes, he said, I am quite aware that this is their way of talking. And, as in a body which is diseased the addition of a touch from without may bring on illness, and sometimes even when there is no external provocation, a commotion may arise within—in the same way wherever there is weakness in the State there is also likely to be illness, of which the occasion may be very slight, the one party introducing from without their oligarchical, the other their democratical allies, and then the State falls sick, and is at war with herself; and may be at times distracted, even when there is no external cause.

Yes, surely.

557

And then democracy comes into being after the poor have conquered their opponents, slaughtering some and banishing some,18 while to the remainder they give an equal share of freedom and power; and this is the form of government in which the magistrates are commonly elected by lot.

Yes, he said, that is the nature of democracy, whether the revolution has been effected by arms, or whether fear has caused the opposite party to withdraw.

And now what is their manner of life, and what sort of a government have they? for as the government is, such will be the man.

b

Clearly, he said.

In the first place, are they not free; 19 and is not the city full of freedom and frankness—a man may say and do what he likes?

‘Tis said so, he replied.

And where freedom is, the individual is clearly able to order for himself his own life as he pleases?

Clearly.

Then in this kind of State there will be the greatest variety of human natures?

c

There will.

This, then, seems likely to be the fairest of States, being like an embroidered robe which is spangled with every sort of flower. And just as women and children think a variety of colors to be of all things most charming, so there are many men to whom this State, which is spangled with the manners and characters of mankind, will appear to be the fairest of States.

Yes.

Yes, my good sir, and there will be no better in which to look for a government.

d

Why?

Because of the liberty which reigns there—they have a complete assortment of constitutions; and he who has a mind to establish a State, as we have been doing, must go to a democracy as he would to a bazaar at which they sell them, and pick out the one that suits him; then, when he has made his choice, he may found his State.

He will be sure to have patterns enough.

e

And there being no necessity, I said, for you to govern in this State, even if you have the capacity, or to be governed, unless you like, or to go to war when the rest go to war, or to be at peace when others are at peace, unless you are so disposed—there being no necessity also, because some law forbids you to hold office or be a dicast, that you should not hold office or be a dicast, if you have a fancy—is not this a way of life which for the moment is supremely delightful?

558

For the moment, yes.

And is not their humanity to the condemned in some cases quite charming?20 Have you not observed how, in a democracy, many persons, although they have been sentenced to death or exile, just stay where they are and walk about the world—the gentleman parades like a hero, and nobody sees or cares?

Yes, he replied, many and many a one.

See, too, I said, the “considerateness” of democracy, and the “don’t care” about trifles, and the disregard which she shows of all the fine principles which we solemnly laid down at the foundation of the city—as when we said that, except in the case of some rarely gifted nature,ha there never will be a good man who has not from his childhood been used to play amid things of beauty and make of them a joy and a study—how grandly does she trample all these fine notions of ours under her feet, never giving a thought to the pursuits which make a statesman, and promoting to honor anyone who professes to be the people’s friend.

b
c

Yes, she is of a noble spirit.

These and other kindred characteristics are proper to democracy, which is a charming form of government, full of variety and disorder and dispensing a sort of equality to equals and unequals alike.21

We know her well.

Consider now, I said, what manner of man the individual is, or rather consider, as in the case of the State, how he comes into being.

Very good, he said.

Is not this the way—he is the son of the miserly and oligarchical father who has trained him in his own habits?

d

Exactly.

And, like his father, he keeps under by force the pleasures which are of the spending and not of the getting sort, being those which are called unnecessary?

Obviously.

Would you like, for the sake of clearness, to distinguish which are the necessary and which are the unnecessary pleasures?

I should.

Are not necessary pleasures those of which we cannot get rid, and of which the satisfaction is a benefit to us? And they are rightly called so, because we are framed by nature to desire both what is beneficial and what is necessary, and cannot help it.

e

True.

We are not wrong therefore in calling them necessary?

559

We are not.

And the desires of which a man may get rid, if he takes pains from his youth upward—of which the presence, moreover, does no good, and in some cases the reverse of good—shall we not be right in saying that all these are unnecessary?

Yes, certainly.

Suppose we select an example of either kind, in order that we may have a general notion of them?

Very good.

Will not the desire of eating, that is, of simple food and condiments, in so far as they are required for health and strength, be of the necessary class?

b

That is what I should suppose.

The pleasure of eating is necessary in two ways; it does us good and it is essential to the continuance of life?

Yes.

But the condiments are only necessary in so far as they are good for health?

Certainly.

And the desire which goes beyond this, of more delicate food, or other luxuries, which might generally be got rid of, if controlled and trained in youth, and is hurtful to the body, and hurtful to the soul in the pursuit of wisdom and virtue, may be rightly called unnecessary?

c

Very true.

May we not say that these desires spend, and that the others make money because they conduce to production?

Certainly.

And of the pleasures of love, and all other pleasures, the same holds good?

True.

And the drone of whom we spoke was he who was surfeited in pleasures and desires of this sort, and was the slave of the unnecessary desires, whereas he who was subject to the necessary only was miserly and oligarchical?

d

Very true.

Again, let us see how the democratical man goes out of the oligarchical: the following, as I suspect, is commonly the process.

What is the process?

When a young man who has been brought up as we were just now describing, in a vulgar and miserly way, has tasted drones’ honey and has come to associate with fierce and crafty natures who are able to provide for him all sorts of refinements and varieties of pleasure—then, as you may imagine, the change will begin of the oligarchical principle within him into the democratical?

e

Inevitably.

And as in the city like was helping like, and the change was effected by an alliance from without assisting one division of the citizens, so too the young man is changed by a class of desires coming from without to assist the desires within him, that which is akin and alike again helping that which is akin and alike?

Certainly.

And if there be any ally which aids the oligarchical principle within him, whether the influence of a father or of kindred, advising or rebuking him, then there arise in his soul a faction and an opposite faction, and he goes to war with himself.22

560

It must be so.

And there are times when the democratical principle gives way to the oligarchical, and some of his desires die, and others are banished; a spirit of reverence enters into the young man’s soul, and order is restored.

Yes, he said, that sometimes happens.

And then, again, after the old desires have been driven out, fresh ones spring up, which are akin to them, and because his father does not know how to educate him, wax fierce and numerous.

b

Yes, he said, that is apt to be the way.

They draw him to his old associates, and holding secret intercourse with them, breed and multiply in him.

Very true.

At length they seize upon the citadel of the young man’s soul, which they perceive to be void of all accomplishments and fair pursuits and true words, which make their abode in the minds of men who are dear to the gods, and are their best guardians and sentinels.

None better.

c

False and boastful conceits and phrases mount upward and take their place.

They are certain to do so.

And so the young man returns into the country of the lotus-eaters, hb and takes up his dwelling there, in the face of all men; and if any help be sent by his friends to the oligarchical part of him, the aforesaid vain conceits shut the gate of the King’s fastness; 23 and they will neither allow the embassy itself to enter, nor if private advisers offer the fatherly counsel of the aged will they listen to them or receive them. There is a battle and they gain the day, and then modesty, which they call silliness, is ignominiously thrust into exile by them, and temperance, which they nick-name unmanliness, is trampled in the mire and cast forth; they persuade men that moderation and orderly expenditure are vulgarity and meanness, and so, by the help of a rabble of evil appetites, they drive them beyond the border.24

d

Yes, with a will.

And when they have emptied and swept clean the soul of him who is now in their power and who is being initiated by them in great mysteries, the next thing is to bring back to their house insolence and anarchy and waste and impudence in bright array, having garlands on their heads, and a great company with them, hymning their praises and calling them by sweet names; insolence they term “breeding,” and anarchy “liberty,” and waste “magnificence,” and impudence “courage.” And so the young man passes out of his original nature, which was trained in the school of necessity, into the freedom and libertinism of useless and unnecessary pleasures.

e
561

Yes, he said, the change in him is visible enough.

After this he lives on, spending his money and labor and time on unnecessary pleasures quite as much as on necessary ones; but if he be fortunate, and is not too much disordered in his wits, when years have elapsed, and the heyday of passion is over—supposing that he then readmits into the city some part of the exiled virtues, and does not wholly give himself up to their successors—in that case he balances his pleasures and lives in a sort of equilibrium, putting the government of himself into the hands of the one which comes first and wins the turn; and when he has had enough of that, then into the hands of another; he despises none of them, but encourages them all equally.

b

Very true, he said.

Neither does he receive or let pass into the fortress any true word of advice;25 if anyone says to him that some pleasures are the satisfactions of good and noble desires, and others of evil desires, and that he ought to use and honor some, and chastise and master the others—whenever this is repeated to him he shakes his head and says that they are all alike, and that one is as good as another.

c

Yes, he said; that is the way with him.

Yes, I said, he lives from day to day indulging the appetite of the hour; and sometimes he is lapped in drink and strains of the flute; then he becomes a water-drinker, and tries to get thin; then he takes a turn at gymnastics; sometimes idling and neglecting everything, then once more living the life of a philosopher; often he is busy with politics, and starts to his feet and says and does whatever comes into his head; and, if he is emulous of anyone who is a warrior, off he is in that direction, or of men of business, once more in that. His life has neither law nor order; and this distracted existence he terms joy and bliss and freedom; and so he goes on.

d

Yes, he replied, he is all liberty and equality.

e

Yes, I said; his life is motley and manifold and an epitome of the lives of many; he answers to the State which we described as fair and spangled. And many a man and many a woman will take him for their pattern, and many a constitution and many an example of manners are contained in him.

Just so.

Let him then be set over against democracy; he may truly be called the democratic man.

562

Let that be his place, he said.

Last of all comes the most beautiful of all, man and State alike, tyranny and the tyrant; these we have now to consider.

Quite true, he said.

Say then, my friend, in what manner does tyranny arise?—that it has a democratic origin is evident.

Clearly.

And does not tyranny spring from democracy in the same manner as democracy from oligarchy—I mean, after a sort?26

How?

The good which oligarchy proposed to itself and the means by which it was maintained was excess of wealth—am I not right?

b

Yes.

And the insatiable desire of wealth and the neglect of all other things for the sake of money-getting were also the ruin of oligarchy?

True.

And democracy has her own good, of which the insatiable desire brings her to dissolution?

What good?

Freedom, I replied; which, as they tell you in a democracy, is the glory of the State—and that therefore in a democracy alone will the freeman of nature deign to dwell.

c

Yes; the saying is in everybody’s mouth.

I was going to observe, that the insatiable desire of this and the neglect of other things introduce the change in democracy, which occasions a demand for tyranny.

How so?

When a democracy which is thirsting for freedom has evil cup-bearers presiding over the feast, and has drunk too deeply of the strong wine of freedom,hc then, unless her rulers are very amenable and give a plentiful draught, she calls them to account and punishes them, and says that they are cursed oligarchs.

d

Yes, he replied, a very common occurrence.

Yes, I said; and loyal citizens are insultingly termed by her “slaves” who hug their chains, and men of naught; she would have subjects who are like rulers, and rulers who are like subjects: these are men after her own heart, whom she praises and honors both in private and public. Now, in such a State, can liberty have any limit?

e

Certainly not.

By degrees the anarchy finds a way into private houses, and ends by getting among the animals and infecting them.27

How do you mean?

I mean that the father grows accustomed to descend to the level of his sons and to fear them, and the son is on a level with his father, he having no respect or reverence for either of his parents; and this is his freedom; and the metic is equal with the citizen, and the citizen with the metic, and the stranger is quite as good as either.

563

Yes, he said, that is the way.

And these are not the only evils, I said—there are several lesser ones: In such a state of society the master fears and flatters his students, and the students despise their masters and tutors; young and old are all alike; and the young man is on a level with the old, and is ready to compete with him in word or deed; and old men condescend to the young and are full of pleasantry and gayety; they are loth to be thought morose and authoritative, and therefore they adopt the manners of the young.

b

Quite true, he said.

The last extreme of popular liberty is when the slave bought with money, whether male or female, is just as free as his or her purchaser; nor must I forget to tell of the liberty and equality of the two sexes in relation to each other.

Why not, as Æschylus says, utter the word which rises to our lips?hd

c

That is what I am doing, I replied; and I must add that no one who does not know would believe how much greater is the liberty which the animals who are under the dominion of man have in a democracy than in any other State: for, truly, the she-dogs, as the proverb says, are as good as their she-mistresses,he and the horses and asses have a way of marching along with all the rights and dig nities of freemen; and they will run at anybody who comes in their way if he does not leave the road clear for them: and all things are just ready to burst with liberty.

d

When I take a country walk, he said, I often experience what you describe. You and I have dreamed the same thing.

And above all, I said, and as the result of all, see how sensitive the citizens become; they chafe impatiently at the least touch of authority, and at length, as you know, they cease to care even for the laws, written or unwritten; they will have no one over them.

e

Yes, he said, I know it too well.

Such, my friend, I said, is the fair and glorious beginning out of which springs tyranny.

Glorious indeed, he said. But what is the next step?

The ruin of oligarchy is the ruin of democracy; the same disease magnified and intensified by liberty overmasters democracy—the truth being that the excessive increase of anything often causes a reaction in the opposite direction; and this is the case not only in the seasons and in vegetable and animal life, but above all in forms of government.

564

True.

The excess of liberty, whether in States or individuals, seems only to pass into excess of slavery.

Yes, the natural order.

And so tyranny naturally arises out of democracy, and the most aggravated form of tyranny and slavery out of the most extreme form of liberty?

As we might expect.

That, however, was not, as I believe, your question—you rather desired to know what is that disorder which is generated alike in oligarchy and democracy, and is the ruin of both?

b

Just so, he replied.

Well, I said, I meant to refer to the class of idle spendthrifts, of whom the more courageous are the leaders and the more timid the followers, the same whom we were comparing to drones, some stingless, and others having stings.

A very just comparison.

These two classes are the plagues of every city in which they are generated, being what phlegm and bile are to the body. And the good physician and lawgiver of the State ought, like the wise bee-master, to keep them at a distance and prevent, if possible, their ever coming in; and if they have anyhow found a way in, then he should have them and their cells cut out as speedily as possible.

c

Yes, by all means, he said.

Then, in order that we may see clearly what we are doing, let us imagine democracy to be divided, as indeed it is, into three classes; for in the first place freedom creates rather more drones in the democratic than there were in the oligarchical State.

d

That is true.

And in the democracy they are certainly more intensified.

How so?

Because in the oligarchical State they are disqualified and driven from office, and therefore they cannot train or gather strength; whereas in a democracy they are almost the entire ruling power, and while the keener sort speak and act, the rest keep buzzing about the bemahf and do not suffer a word to be said on the other side; hence in democracies almost everything is managed by the drones.

e

Very true, he said.

Then there is another class which is always being severed from the mass.

What is that?

They are the orderly class, which in a nation of traders is sure to be the richest.

Naturally so.

They are the most squeezable persons and yield the largest amount of honey to the drones.

Why, he said, there is little to be squeezed out of people who have little.

And this is called the wealthy class, and the drones feed upon them.

That is pretty much the case, he said.

The people are a third class, consisting of those who work with their own hands; they are not politicians, and have not much to live upon. This, when assembled, is the largest and most powerful class in a democracy.

565

True, he said; but then the multitude is seldom willing to congregate unless they get a little honey.

And do they not share? I said. Do not their leaders deprive the rich of their estates and distribute them among the people; at the same time taking care to reserve the larger part for themselves?

Why, yes, he said, to that extent the people do share.

b

And the persons whose property is taken from them are compelled to defend themselves before the people as they best can?

What else can they do?

And then, although they may have no desire of change, the others charge them with plotting against the people and being friends of oligarchy?

True.

And the end is that when they see the people, not of their own accord, but through ignorance, and because they are deceived by informers, seeking to do them wrong, then at last they are forced to become oligarchs in reality; they do not wish to be, but the sting of the drones torments them and breeds revolution in them.28

c

That is exactly the truth.

Then come impeachments and judgments and trials of one another.

True.

The people have always some championhg whom they set over them and nurse into greatness.

Yes, that is their way.

This, and no other, is the root from which a tyrant springs; when he first appears above ground he is a protector.

d

Yes, that is quite clear.

How, then, does a protector begin to change into a tyrant?

Clearly when he does what the man is said to do in the tale of the Arcadian temple of Lycæan Zeus.hh

What tale?

The tale is that he who has tasted the entrails of a single human victim minced up with the entrails of other victims is destined to become a wolf. Did you never hear it?

e

Oh, yes.

And the protector of the people is like him; having a mob entirely at his disposal, he is not restrained from shedding the blood of kinsmen; by the favorite method of false accusation he brings them into court and murders them, making the life of man to disappear, and with unholy tongue and lips tasting the blood of his fellow-citizens; some he kills and others he banishes, at the same time hinting at the abolition of debts and partition of lands: and after this, what will be his destiny? Must he not either perish at the hands of his enemies, or from being a man become a wolf—that is, a tyrant?

566

Inevitably.

This, I said, is he who begins to make a party against the rich?

The same.

After a while he is driven out, but comes back, in spite of his enemies, a tyrant full grown.29

That is clear.

And if they are unable to expel him, or to get him condemned to death by a public accusation, they conspire to assassinate him.

b

Yes, he said, that is their usual way.

Then comes the famous request for a body-guard,30 which is the device of all those who have got thus far in their tyrannical career—“Let not the people’s friend,” as they say, “be lost to them.”

Exactly.

The people readily assent; all their fears are for him—they have none for themselves.

Very true.

c

And when a man who is wealthy and is also accused of being an enemy of the people sees this, then, my friend, as the oracle said to Crœsus,

“By pebbly Hermus’s shore he flees and rests not, and is not ashamed to be a coward.”31

And quite right too, said he, for if he were, he would never be ashamed again.

But if he is caught he dies.

Of course.

And he, the protector of whom we spoke, is to be seen, not “larding the plain” with his bulk, but himself the overthrower of many, standing up in the chariot of State with the reins in his hand, no longer protector, but tvrant absolute.

d

No doubt, he said.

And now let us consider the happiness of the man, and also of the State in which a creature like him is generated.

Yes, he said, let us consider that.

At first, in the early days of his power, he is full of smiles, and he salutes everyone whom he meets; he to be called a tyrant, who is making promises in public and also in private! liberating debtors, and distributing land to the people and his followers, and wanting to be so kind and good to everyone!

e

Of course, he said.

But when he has disposed of foreign enemies by conquest or treaty, and there is nothing to fear from them, then he is always stirring up some war or other, in order that the people may require a leader.

To be sure.

Has he not also another object, which is that they may be impoverished by payment of taxes, and thus compelled to devote themselves to their daily wants and therefore less likely to conspire against him?

567

Clearly.

And if any of them are suspected by him of having notions of freedom, and of resistance to his authority, he will have a good pretext for destroying them by placing them at the mercy of the enemy; and for all these reasons the tyrant must be always getting up a war.

He must.

Now he begins to grow unpopular.

A necessary result.

b

Then some of those who joined in setting him up, and who are in power, speak their minds to him and to one another, and the more courageous of them cast in his teeth what is being done.

Yes, that may be expected.

And the tyrant, if he means to rule, must get rid of them; he cannot stop while he has a friend or an enemy who is good for anything.

He cannot.

And therefore he must look about him and see who is valiant, who is high-minded, who is wise, who is wealthy; happy man, he is the enemy of them all, and must seek occasion against them whether he will or no, until he has made a purgation of the State.32

c

Yes, he said, and a rare purgation.

Yes, I said, not the sort of purgation which the physicians make of the body; for they take away the worse and leave the better part, but he does the reverse.

If he is to rule, I suppose that he cannot help himself.

What a blessed alternative, I said: to be compelled to dwell only with the many bad, and to be by them hated, or not to live at all!

d

Yes, that is the alternative.

And the more detestable his actions are to the citizens the more satellites and the greater devotion in them will he require?

Certainly.

And who are the devoted band, and where will he procure them?

They will flock to him, he said, of their own accord, if he pays them.

By the dog! I said, here are more drones, of every sort and from every land.

e

Yes, he said, there are.

But will he not desire to get them on the spot?

How do you mean?

He will rob the citizens of their slaves; he will then set them free and enrol them in his body-guard.

To be sure, he said; and he will be able to trust them best of all.

What a blessed creature, I said, must this tyrant be; he has put to death the others and has these for his trusted friends.

568

Yes, he said; they are quite of his sort.

Yes, I said, and these are the new citizens whom he has called into existence, who admire him and are his companions, while the good hate and avoid him.

Of course.

Verily, then, tragedy is a wise thing and Euripides a great tragedian.

Why so?

Why, because he is the author of the pregnant saying, and he clearly meant to say that they are the wise whom the tyrant makes his companions.

“Tyrants are wise by living with the wise;”33
b

Yes, he said, and he also praises tyranny as godlike; and many other things of the same kind are said by him and by the other poets.

And therefore, I said, the tragic poets being wise men will forgive us and any others who live after our manner, if we do not receive them into our State, because they are the eulogists of tyranny.

Yes, he said, those who have the wit will doubtless forgive us.

But they will continue to go to other cities and attract mobs, and hire voices fair and loud and persuasive, and draw the cities over to tyrannies and democracies.34

c

Very true.

Moreover, they are paid for this and receive honor—the greatest honor, as might be expected, from tyrants, and the next greatest from democracies; but the higher they ascend our constitution hill, the more their reputation fails, and seems unable from shortness of breath to proceed farther.

d

True.

But we are wandering from the subject: Let us therefore return and inquire how the tyrant will maintain that fair, and numerous, and various, and ever-changing army of his.

If, he said, there are sacred treasures in the city, he will confiscate and spend them; and in so far as the fortunes of attainted persons may suffice, he will be able to diminish the taxes which he would otherwise have to impose upon the people.

And when these fail?

e

Why, clearly, he said, then he and his boon companions, whether male or female, will be maintained out of his father’s estate.35

You mean to say that the people, from whom he has derived his being, will maintain him and his companions?

Yes, he said; they cannot help themselves.

But what if the people fly into a passion, and aver that a grown-up son ought not to be supported by his father, but that the father should be supported by the son? The father did not bring him into being, or settle him in life, in order that when his son became a man he should himself be the servant of his own servants and should support him and his rabble of slaves and companions; but that his son should protect him, and that by his help he might be emancipated from the government of the rich and aristocratic, as they are termed. And so he bids him and his companions depart, just as any other father might drive out of the house a riotous son and his undesirable associates.

569

By heaven, he said, then the parent will discover what a monster he has been fostering in his bosom; and, when he wants to drive him out, he will find that he is weak and his son strong.

b

Why, you do not mean to say that the tyrant will use violence? What! beat his father if he opposes him?

Yes, he will, having first disarmed him.

Then he is a parricide, and a cruel guardian of an aged parent; and this is real tyranny, about which there can be no longer a mistake: as the saying is, the people who would escape the smoke which is the slavery of freemen, has fallen into the fire which is the tyranny of slaves. Thus liberty, getting out of all order and reason, passes into the harshest and bitterest form of slavery.

c

True, he said.

Very well; and may we not rightly say that we have sufficiently discussed the nature of tyranny, and the manner of the transition from democracy to tyranny?

Yes, quite enough, he said.

BOOK 9

LAST OF ALL COMES the tyrannical man; about whom we have once more to ask, how is he formed out of the democratical? and how does he live, in happiness or in misery?

571

Yes, he said, he is the only one remaining.

There is, however, I said, a previous question which remains unanswered.

What question?

I do not think that we have adequately determined the nature and number of the appetites, and until this is accomplished the inquiry will always be confused.

b

Well, he said, it is not too late to supply the omission.

Very true, I said; and observe the point which I want to understand: Certain of the unnecessary pleasures and appetites I conceive to be unlawful; everyone appears to have them, but in some persons they are controlled by the laws and by reason, and the better desires prevail over them—either they are wholly banished or they become few and weak; while in the case of others they are stronger, and there are more of them.

c

Which appetites do you mean?

I mean those which are awake when the reasoning and human and ruling power is asleep; then the wild beast within us, gorged with meat or drink, starts up and, having shaken off sleep, goes forth to satisfy his desires; and there is no conceivable folly or crime—not excepting incest or any other unnatural union, or parricide, or the eating of forbidden food—which at such a time, when he has parted company with all shame and sense, a man may not be ready to commit.

d

Most true, he said.

But when a man’s pulse is healthy and temperate, and when before going to sleep he has awakened his rational powers, and fed them on noble thoughts and inquiries, collecting himself in meditation; after having first indulged his appetites neither too much nor too little, but just enough to lay them to sleep, and prevent them and their enjoyments and pains from interfering with the higher principlehi—which he leaves in the solitude of pure abstraction, free to contemplate and aspire to the knowledge of the unknown, whether in past, present, or future: when again he has allayed the passionate element, if he has a quarrel against anyone—I say, when, after pacifying the two irrational principles, he rouses up the third, which is reason, before he takes his rest, then, as you know, he attains truth most nearly, and is least likely to be the sport of fantastic and lawless visions.

e
572
b

I quite agree.

In saying this I have been running into a digression; but the point which I desire to note is that in all of us, even in good men, there is a lawless wild-beast nature, which peers out in sleep.1 Pray, consider whether I am right, and you agree with me.

Yes, I agree.

And now remember the character which we attributed to the democratic man. He was supposed from his youth upward to have been trained under a miserly parent, who encouraged the saving appetites in him, but discountenanced the unnecessary, which aim only at amusement and ornament?

c

True.

And then he got into the company of a more refined, licentious sort of people, and taking to all their wanton ways rushed into the opposite extreme from an abhorrence of his father’s meanness. At last, being a better man than his corruptors, he was drawn in both directions until he halted midway and led a life, not of vulgar and slavish passion, but of what he deemed moderate indulgence in various pleasures. After this manner the democrat was generated out of the oligarch?

d

Yes, he said; that was our view of him, and is so still.

And now, I said, years will have passed away, and you must conceive this man, such as he is, to have a son, who is brought up in his father’s principles.

I can imagine him.

Then you must further imagine the same thing to happen to the son which has already happened to the father: he is drawn into a perfectly lawless life, which by his seducers is termed perfect liberty; and his father and friends take part with his moderate desires, and the opposite party assist the opposite ones. As soon as these dire magicians and tyrant-makers find that they are losing their hold on him, they contrive to implant in him a master-passion, to be lord over his idle and spendthrift lusts—a sort of monstrous winged drone—that is the only image which will adequately describe him.

e
573

Yes, he said, that is the only adequate image of him.

And when his other lusts, amid clouds of incense and perfumes and garlands and wines, and all the pleasures of a dissolute life, now let loose, come buzzing around him, nourishing to the utmost the sting of desire which they implant in his drone-like nature, then at last this lord of the soul, having Madness for the captain of his guard, breaks out into a frenzy; and if he finds in himself any good opinions or appetites in process of formation, and there is in him any sense of shame remaining, to these better principles he puts an end, and casts them forth until he has purged away temperance and brought in madness to the full.

b

Yes, he said, that is the way in which the tyrannical man is generated.

And is not this the reason why, of old, love has been called a tyrant?2

c

I should not wonder.

Further, I said, has not a drunken man also the spirit of a tyrant?

He has.

And you know that a man who is deranged, and not right in his mind, will fancy that he is able to rule, not only over men, but also over the gods?

That he will.

And the tyrannical man in the true sense of the word comes into being when, either under the influence of nature or habit, or both, he becomes drunken, lustful, passionate? O my friend, is not that so?

Assuredly.

Such is the man and such is his origin. And next, how does he live?

Suppose, as people facetiously say, you were to tell me.

I imagine, I said, at the next step in his progress, that there will be feasts and carousals and revellings and courtesans, and all that sort of thing; Love is the lord of the house within him, and orders all the concerns of his soul.3

d

That is certain.

Yes; and every day and every night desires grow up many and formidable, and their demands are many.

They are indeed, he said.

His revenues, if he has any, are soon spent.

True.

Then come debt and the cutting down of his property.

e

Of course.

When he has nothing left, must not his desires, crowding in the nest like young ravens, be crying aloud for food; and he, goaded on by them, and especially by love himself, who is in a manner the captain of them, is in a frenzy, and would fain discover whom he can defraud or despoil of his property, in order that he may gratify them?

574

Yes, that is sure to be the case.

He must have money, no matter how, if he is to escape horrid pains and pangs.

He must.

And as in himself there was a succession of pleasures, and the new got the better of the old and took away their rights, so he being younger will claim to have more than his father and his mother, and if he has spent his own share of the property, he will take a slice of theirs.

No doubt he will.

And if his parents will not give way, then he will try first of all to cheat and deceive them.

b

Very true.

And if he fails, then he will use force and plunder them.

Yes, probably.

And if the old man and woman fight for their own, what then, my friend? Will the creature feel any compunction at tyrannizing over them?

Nay, he said, I should not feel at all comfortable about his parents.

But, O heavens! Adeimantus, on account of some newfangled love of a harlot, who is anything but a necessary connection, can you believe that he would strike the mother who is his ancient friend and necessary to his very existence, and would place her under the authority of the other, when she is brought under the same roof with her; or that, under like circumstances, he would do the same to his withered old father, first and most indispensable of friends, for the sake of some newly found blooming youth who is the reverse of indispensable?

c

Yes, indeed, he said; I believe that he would.

Truly, then, I said, a tyrannical son is a blessing to his father and mother.

He is indeed, he replied.

He first takes their property, and when that fails, and pleasures are beginning to swarm in the hive of his soul, then he breaks into a house, or steals the garments of some nightly wayfarer; next he proceeds to clear a temple.4 Meanwhile the old opinions which he had when a child, and which gave judgment about good and evil, are overthrown by those others which have just been emancipated, and are now the body-guard of lovehj and share his empire. These in his democratic days, when he was still subject to the laws and to his father, were only let loose in the dreams of sleep. But now that he is under the dominion of Love, he becomes always and in waking reality what he was then very rarely and in a dream only; he will commit the foulest murder, or eat forbidden food, or be guilty of any other horrid act. Love is his tyrant, and lives lordly in him and lawlessly, and being himself a king, leads him on, as a tyrant leads a State, to the performance of any reckless deed by which he can maintain himself and the rabble of his associates, whether those whom evil communications have brought in from without, or those whom he himself has allowed to break loose within him by reason of a similar evil nature in himself. Have we not here a picture of his way of life?

d
e
575

Yes, indeed, he said.

And if there are only a few of them in the State, and the rest of the people are well disposed, they go away and become the body guard of mercenary soldiers of some other tyrant who may probably want them for a war; and if there is no war, they stay at home and do many little pieces of mischief in the city.

b

What sort of mischief?

For example, they are the thieves, burglars, cut-purses, footpads, robbers of temples, man-stealers of the community; or if they are able to speak, they turn informers and bear false witness and take bribes.

You describe a small catalogue of evils, if the perpetrators of them are few in number.

C

Yes, I said; but small and great are comparative terms, and all these things, in the misery and evil which they inflict upon a State, do not come within a thousand miles of the tyrant; when this noxious class and their followers grow numerous and become conscious of their strength, assisted by the infatuation of the people, they choose from among themselves the one who has most of the tyrant in his own soul, and him they create their tyrant.

d

Yes, he said, and he will be the most fit to be a tyrant.

If the people yield, well and good; but if they resist him, as he began by beating his own father and mother, so now, if he has the power, he beats them, and will keep his dear old fatherland or motherland, as the Cretans say,hk in subjection to his young retainers whom he has introduced to be their rulers and masters. This is the end of his passions and desires.

Exactly.

e

When such men are only private individuals and before they get power, this is their character; they associate entirely with their own flatterers or ready tools; or if they want anything from anybody, they in their turn are equally ready to bow down before them: they profess every sort of affection for them; but when they have gained their point they know them no more.

576

Yes, truly.

They are always either the masters or servants and never the friends of anybody; the tyrant never tastes of true freedom or friendship.

Certainly not.

And may we not rightly call such men treacherous?

No question.

Also they are utterly unjust, if we were right in our notion of justice?

b

Yes, he said, and we were perfectly right.

Let us, then, sum up in a word, I said, the character of the worst man: he is the waking reality of what we dreamed.

Most true.

And this is he who being by nature most of a tyrant bears rule, and the longer he lives the more of a tyrant he becomes.

That is certain, said Glaucon, taking his turn to answer.

And will not he who has been shown to be the wickedest, be also the most miserable? and he who has tyrannized longest and most, most continually and truly miserable; although this may not be the opinion of men in general?hl

C

Yes, he said, inevitably.

And must not the tyrannical man be like the tyrannical State, and the democratical man like the democratical State; and the same of the others?

Certainly.

And as State is to State in virtue and happiness, so is man in relation to man?

To be sure.

d

Then comparing our original city, which was under a king, and the city which is under a tyrant, how do they stand as to virtue?hm

They are the opposite extremes, he said, for one is the very best and the other is the very worst.

There can be no mistake, I said, as to which is which, and therefore I will at once inquire whether you would arrive at a similar decision about their relative happiness and misery.5 And let us not be astounded as we look upon the tyrant, who is only one man, not even if there are some few around him who seem content; but let us go as we ought into every corner of the city and look all about, and then we will give our opinion.

e

A fair invitation, he replied; and I see, as everyone must, that a tyranny is the wretchedest form of government, and the rule of a king the happiest.

And in estimating the men, too, may I not fairly make a like request, that I should have a judge whose mind can enter into and see through human nature? he must not be like a child who looks at the outside and is dazzled at the pompous aspect which the tyrannical nature assumes to the beholder, but let him be one who has a clear insight.6 May I suppose that the judgment is given in the hearing of us all by one who is able to judge, and has dwelt in the same place with him, and been present at his daily life and known him in his family relations, where he may be seen stripped of his tragedy attire,7 and again in the hour of public danger—he shall tell us about the happiness and misery of the tyrant when compared with other men?

577
b

That again, he said, is a very fair proposal.

Shall I assume that we ourselves are able and experienced judges and have before now met with such a person? We shall then have someone who will answer our inquiries.

By all means.

Let me ask you not to forget the parallel of the individual and the State; bearing this in mind, and glancing in turn from one to the other of them, will you tell me their respective conditions?

c

What do you mean? he asked.

Beginning with the State, I replied, would you say that a city which is governed by a tyrant is free or enslaved?

No city, he said, can be more completely enslaved.

And yet, as you see, there are freemen as well as masters in such a State?

Yes, he said, I see that there are—a few; but the people, speaking generally, and the best of them are miserably degraded and enslaved.

Then if the man is like the State, I said, must not the same rule prevail? His soul is full of meanness and vulgarity—the best elements in him are enslaved; and there is a small ruling part, which is also the worst and maddest.

d

Inevitably.

And would you say that the soul of such a one is the soul of a freeman or of a slave?

He has the soul of a slave, in my opinion.

And the State which is enslaved under a tyrant is utterly incapable of acting voluntarily?

Utterly incapable.

And also the soul which is under a tyrant (I am speaking of the soul taken as a whole) is least capable of doing what she desires; there is a gadfly which goads her, and she is full of trouble and remorse?

e

Certainly.

And is the city which is under a tyrant rich or poor?

Poor.

And the tyrannical soul must be always poor and insatiable?

578

True.

And must not such a State and such a man be always full of fear? Yes, indeed.

Is there any State in which you will find more of lamentation and sorrow and groaning and pain?

Certainly not.

And is there any man in whom you will find more of this sort of misery than in the tyrannical man, who is in a fury of passions and desires?

Impossible.

Reflecting upon these and similar evils, you held the tyrannical State to be the most miserable of States?

And I was right, he said.

Certainly, I said. And when you see the same evils in the tyrannical man, what do you say of him?

b

I say that he is by far the most miserable of all men.

There, I said, I think that you are beginning to go wrong.

What do you mean?

I do not think that he has as yet reached the utmost extreme of misery.

Then who is more miserable?

One of whom I am about to speak.

Who is that?

He who is of a tyrannical nature, and instead of leading a private life has been cursed with the further misfortune of being a public tyrant.

c

From what has been said, I gather that you are right.

Yes, I replied, but in this high argument you should be a little more certain, and should not conjecture only; for of all questions, this respecting good and evil is the greatest.

Very true, he said.

Let me then offer you an illustration, which may, I think, throw a light upon this subject.

d

What is your illustration?

The case of rich individuals in cities who possess many slaves: from them you may form an idea of the tyrant’s condition, for they both have slaves; the only difference is that he has more slaves.

Yes, that is the difference.

You know that they live securely and have nothing to apprehend from their servants?

What should they fear?

Nothing. But do you observe the reason of this?

Yes; the reason is, that the whole city is leagued together for the protection of each individual.

Very true, I said. But imagine one of these owners, the master say of some fifty slaves, together with his family and property and slaves, carried off by a god into the wilderness, where there are no freemen to help him—will he not be in an agony of fear lest he and his wife and children should be put to death by his slaves?

e

Yes, he said, he will be in the utmost fear.

The time has arrived when he will be compelled to flatter several of his slaves, and make many promises to them of freedom and other things, much against his will—he will have to cajole his own servants.

579

Yes, he said, that will be the only way of saving himself.

And suppose the same god, who carried him away, to surround him with neighbors who will not suffer one man to be the master of another, and who, if they could catch the offender, would take his life?

His case will be still worse, if you suppose him to be everywhere surrounded and watched by enemies.

b

And is not this the sort of prison in which the tyrant will be bound—he who being by nature such as we have described, is full of all sorts of fears and lusts? His soul is dainty and greedy, and yet alone, of all men in the city, he is never allowed to go on a journey, or to see the things which other freemen desire to see, but he lives in his hole like a woman hidden in the house,8 and is jealous of any other citizen who goes into foreign parts and sees anything of interest.

c

Very true, he said.

And by virtue of evils such as these, will not he who is ill-governed in his own person—the tyrannical man, I mean—whom you just now decided to be the most miserable of all—will not he be yet more miserable when, instead of leading a private life, he is constrained by fortune to be a public tyrant? He has to be master of others when he is not master of himself: he is like a diseased or paralytic man who is compelled to pass his life, not in retirement, but fighting and combating with other men.

d

Yes, he said, the similitude is most exact.

Is not his case utterly miserable? and does not the actual tyrant lead a worse life than he whose life you determined to be the worst?

Certainly.

He who is the real tyrant, whatever men may think, is the real slave, and is obliged to practise the greatest adulation and servility, and to be the flatterer of the vilest of mankind. He has desires which he is utterly unable to satisfy, and has more wants than anyone, and is truly poor, if you know how to inspect the whole soul of him: all his life long he is beset with fear and is full of convulsions and distractions, even as the State which he resembles: and surely the resemblance holds?

e

Very true, he said.

Moreover, as we were saying before, he grows worse from having power: he becomes and is of necessity more jealous, more faithless, more unjust, more friendless, more impious, than he was at first; he is the purveyor and cherisher of every sort of vice, and the consequence is that he is supremely miserable, and that he makes everybody else as miserable as himself.

580

No man of any sense will dispute your words.

Come, then, I said, and as the general umpire in theatrical contests proclaims the result,9 do you also decide who in your opinion is first in the scale of happiness, and who second, and in what order the others follow: there are five of them in all—they are the royal,10 timocratical, oligarchical, democratical, tyrannical.

b

The decision will be easily given, he replied; they shall be choruses coming on the stage, and I must judge them in the order in which they enter, by the criterion of virtue and vice, happiness and misery.

Need we hire a herald, or shall I announce that the son of Ariston (the best)hn has decided that the best and justest is also the happiest, and that this is he who is the most royal man and king over himself; and that the worst and most unjust man is also the most miserable, and that this is he who being the greatest tyrant of himself is also the greatest tyrant of his State?

c

Make the proclamation yourself, he said.

And shall I add, “whether seen or unseen by gods and men”?

Let the words be added.

Then this, I said, will be our first proof; and there is another, which may also have some weight.11

d

What is that?

The second proof is derived from the nature of the soul: seeing that the individual soul, like the State, has been divided by us into three principles, the division may, I think, furnish a new demonstration.

Of what nature?

It seems to me that to these three principles three pleasures correspond; also three desires and governing powers.

How do you mean? he said.

There is one principle with which, as we were saying, a man learns, another with which he is angry; the third, having many forms, has no special name, but is denoted by the general term appetitive, from the extraordinary strength and vehemence of the desires of eating and drinking and the other sensual appetites which are the main elements of it; also money-loving, because such desires are generally satisfied by the help of money.

e
581

That is true, he said.

If we were to say that the loves and pleasures of this third part were concerned with gain, we should then be able to fall back on a single notion; and might truly and intelligibly describe this part of the soul as loving gain or money.

I agree with you.

Again, is not the passionate elementho wholly set on ruling and conquering and getting fame?

True.

b

Suppose we call it the contentious or ambitious—would the term be suitable?

Extremely suitable.

On the other hand, everyone sees that the principle of knowledge is wholly directed to the truth, and cares less than either of the others for gain or fame.

Far less.

“Lover of wisdom,” “lover of knowledge,” are titles which we may fitly apply to that part of the soul?

Certainly.

One principle prevails in the souls of one class of men, another in others, as may happen?

C

Yes.

Then we say that the three primary classes of men are the wisdom-loving, the honor-loving, and the profit-loving?

Exactly.

And there are three kinds of pleasure, which are their several objects?

Very true.

Now, if you examine the three classes of men, and ask of them in turn which of their lives is pleasantest, each will be found praising his own and depreciating that of others: the money-maker will contrast the vanity of honor or of learning if they bring no money with the solid advantages of gold and silver?

d

True, he said.

And the lover of honor—what will be his opinion? Will he not think that the pleasure of riches is vulgar, while the pleasure of learning, if it brings no distinction, is all smoke and nonsense to him?

Very true.

And how, may we suppose, will the philosopher estimate the value of the other pleasures in comparison to the pleasure of knowing how the truth stands and of always being in such a happy state while he learns? Will he not estimate that they are very far away from true pleasure? Does he not call the other pleasures necessary, under the idea that if there were no necessity for them, he would rather not have them?

e

There can be no doubt of that, he replied.

Since, then, the pleasures of each class and the life of each are in dispute, and the question is not which life is more or less honorable, or better or worse, but which is the more pleasant or painless—how shall we know who speaks truly?

582

I cannot myself tell, he said.

Well, but what ought to be the criterion? Is any better than experience, and wisdom, and reason?

There cannot be a better, he said.

Then, I said, reflect. Of the three individuals, which has the greatest experience of all the pleasures which we enumerated? Has the lover of gain, in learning the nature of essential truth, greater experience of the pleasure of knowledge than the philosopher has of the pleasure of gain?

b

The philosopher, he replied, has greatly the advantage; for he has of necessity always known the taste of the other pleasures from his childhood upward: but the lover of gain in all his experience has not of necessity tasted—or, I should rather say, even had he desired, could hardly have tasted—the sweetness of learning and knowing truth.

Then the lover of wisdom has a great advantage over the lover of gain, for he has a double experience?

Yes, very great.

c

Again, has he greater experience of the pleasures of honor, or the lover of honor of the pleasures of wisdom?

Nay, he said, all three are honored in proportion as they attain their object; for the rich man and the brave man and the wise man alike have their crowd of admirers, and as they all receive honor they all have experience of the pleasures of honor; but the delight which is to be found in the knowledge of true being is known to the philosopher only.

His experience, then, will enable him to judge better than anyone? 12

d

Far better.

And he is the only one who has wisdom as well as experience?

Certainly.

Further, the very faculty which is the instrument of judgment is not possessed by the covetous or ambitious man, but only by the philosopher?

What faculty?

Reason, with whom, as we were saying, the decision ought to rest.

Yes.

And reasoning is peculiarly his instrument?

Certainly.

If wealth and gain were the criterion, then the praise or blame of the lover of gain would surely be the most trustworthy?

e

Assuredly.

Or if honor, or victory, or courage, in that case the judgment of the ambitious or pugnacious would be the truest?

Clearly.

But since experience and wisdom and reason are the judges—The only inference possible, he replied, is that pleasures which are approved by the lover of wisdom and reason are the truest.

And so we arrive at the result, that the pleasure of the intelligent part of the soul is the pleasantest of the three, and that he of us in whom this is the ruling principle has the pleasantest life.

583

Unquestionably, he said, the wise man speaks with authority when he approves of his own life.

And what does the judge affirm to be the life which is next, and the pleasure which is next?

Clearly that of the soldier and lover of honor; who is nearer to himself than the money-maker.

Last comes the lover of gain?

Very true, he said.

Twice in succession, then, has the just man overthrown the unjust in this conflict;13 and now comes the third trial, which is dedicated to Olympian Zeus the saviour:hp a sage whispers in my ear that no pleasure except that of the wise is quite true and pure—all others are a shadow only; and surely this will prove the greatest and most decisive of falls?

b

Yes, the greatest; but will you explain yourself?

I will work out the subject and you shall answer my questions.

Proceed.

c

Say, then, is not pleasure opposed to pain?

True.

And there is a neutral state which is neither pleasure nor pain? There is.

A state which is intermediate, and a sort of repose of the soul about either—that is what you mean?

Yes.

You remember what people say when they are sick?

What do they say?

That after all nothing is pleasanter than health. But then they never knew this to be the greatest of pleasures until they were ill.

d

Yes, I know, he said.

And when persons are suffering from acute pain, you must have heard them say that there is nothing pleasanter than to get rid of their pain?

I have.

And there are many other cases of suffering in which the mere rest and cessation of pain, and not any positive enjoyment, are extolled by them as the greatest pleasure?

Yes, he said; at the time they are pleased and well content to be at rest.

Again, when pleasure ceases, that sort of rest or cessation will be painful?

e

Doubtless, he said.

Then the intermediate state of rest will be pleasure and will also be pain?

So it would seem.

But can that which is neither become both?

I should say not.

And both pleasure and pain are motions of the soul, are they not?

Yes.

But that which is neither was just now shown to be rest and not motion, and in a mean between them?

584

Yes.

How, then, can we be right in supposing that the absence of pain is pleasure, or that the absence of pleasure is pain?

Impossible.

This, then, is an appearance only, and not a reality; that is to say, the rest is pleasure at the moment and in comparison of what is painful, and painful in comparison of what is pleasant; but all these representations, when tried by the test of true pleasure, are not real, but a sort of imposition?

That is the inference.

Look at the other class of pleasures which have no antecedent pains and you will no longer suppose, as you perhaps may at present, that pleasure is only the cessation of pain, or pain of pleasure.

What are they, he said, and where shall I find them?

b

There are many of them: take as an example, the pleasures of smell, which are very great and have no antecedent pains; they come in a moment, and when they depart leave no pain behind them.

Most true, he said.

Let us not, then, be induced to believe that pure pleasure is the cessation of pain, or pain of pleasure.

c

No.

Still, the more numerous and violent pleasures which reach the soul through the body are generally of this sort—they are reliefs of pain.

That is true.

And the anticipations of future pleasures and pains are of a like nature?

Yes.

Shall I give you an illustration of them?

d

Let me hear.

You would allow, I said, that there is in nature an upper and lower and middle region?

I should.

And if a person were to go from the lower to the middle region, would he not imagine that he is going up; and he who is standing in the middle and sees whence he has come, would imagine that he is already in the upper region, if he has never seen the true upper world?

To be sure, he said; how can he think otherwise?

But if he were taken back again he would imagine, and truly imagine, that he was descending?

e

No doubt.

All that would arise out of his ignorance of the true upper and middle and lower regions?

Yes.

Then can you wonder that persons who are inexperienced in the truth, as they have wrong ideas about many other things, should also have wrong ideas about pleasure and pain and the intermediate state ;14 so that when they are only being drawn toward the painful they feel pain and think the pain which they experience to be real, and in like manner, when drawn away from pain to the neutral or intermediate state, they firmly believe that they have reached the goal of satiety and pleasure; they, not knowing pleasure, err in contrasting pain with the absence of pain, which is like contrasting black with gray instead of white—can you wonder, I say, at this?

585

No, indeed; I should be much more disposed to wonder at the opposite.

Look at the matter thus: Hunger, thirst, and the like, are privations hq of the bodily state?

b

Yes.

And ignorance and folly are inanitions of the soul?

True.

And food and wisdom are the corresponding satisfactions of either?

Certainly.

And is the satisfaction derived from that which has less or from that which has more existence the truer?

Clearly, from that which has more.

What classes of things have a greater share of pure existence, in your judgment—those of which food and drink and condiments and all kinds of sustenance are examples, or the class which contains true opinion and knowledge and mind and all the different kinds of virtue? Put the question in this way: Which has a more pure being—that which is concerned with the invariable, the immortal, and the true, and is of such a nature, and is found in such natures; or that which is concerned with and found in the variable and mortal, and is itself variable and mortal ?

c

Far purer, he replied, is the being of that which is concerned with the invariable.

And does the essence of the invariable partake of knowledge in the same degree as of essence?

Yes, of knowledge in the same degree.

And of truth in the same degree?

Yes.

And, conversely, that which has less of truth will also have less of essence?

Necessarily.

Then, in general, those kinds of things which are in the service of the body have less of truth and essence than those which are in the service of the soul?

d

Far less.

And has not the body itself less of truth and essence than the soul?

Yes.

What is filled with more real existence, and actually has a more real existence, is more really filled than that which is filled with less real existence and is less real?

Of course.

And if there be a pleasure in being filled with that which is according to nature, that which is more really filled with more real being will more really and truly enjoy true pleasure; whereas that which participates in less real being will be less truly and surely satisfied, and will participate in an illusory and less real pleasure?

e

Unquestionably.

Those, then, who know not wisdom and virtue, and are always busy with gluttony and sensuality, go down and up again as far as the mean; and in this region they move at random throughout life, but they never pass into the true upper world; thither they neither look, nor do they ever find their way, neither are they truly filled with true being, nor do they taste of pure and abiding pleasure. Like cattle, with their eyes always looking down and their heads stooping to the earth, that is, to the dining-table, they fatten and feed and breed,15 and, in their excessive love of these delights, they kick and butt at one another with horns and hoofs which are made of iron; and they kill one another by reason of their insatiable lust. For they fill themselves with that which is not substantial, and the part of themselves which they fill is also unsubstantial and incontinent.

586
b

Verily, Socrates, said Glaucon, you describe the life of the many like an oracle.

Their pleasures are mixed with pains—how can they be otherwise? For they are mere shadows and pictures of the true, and are colored by contrast, which exaggerates both light and shade, and so they implant in the minds of fools insane desires of themselves; and they are fought about as Stesichorus says that the Greeks fought about the shadow of Helen at Troy, in ignorance of the truth.16

c

Something of that sort must inevitably happen.

And must not the like happen with the spirited or passionate element of the soul? Will not the passionate man who carries his passion into action, be in the like case, whether he is envious and ambitious, or violent and contentious, or angry and discontented, if he be seeking to attain honor and victory and the satisfaction of his anger without reason or sense?

d

Yes, he said, the same will happen with the spirited element also.

Then may we not confidently assert that the lovers of money and honor, when they seek their pleasures under the guidance and in the company of reason and knowledge, and pursue after and win the pleasures which wisdom shows them, will also have the truest pleasures in the highest degree which is attainable to them, inasmuch as they follow truth; and they will have the pleasures which are natural to them, if that which is best for each one is also most natural to him? 17

e

Yes, certainly; the best is the most natural.

And when the whole soul follows the philosophical principle, and there is no division, the several parts are just, and do each of them their own business, and enjoy severally the best and truest pleasures of which they are capable?

587

Exactly.

But when either of the two other principles prevails, it fails in attaining its own pleasure, and compels the rest to pursue after a pleasure which is a shadow only and which is not their own?

True.

And the greater the interval which separates them from philosophy and reason, the more strange and illusive will be the pleasure?

Yes.

And is not that farthest from reason which is at the greatest distance from law and order?

Clearly.

And the lustful and tyrannical desires are, as we saw, at the greatest distance?

b

Yes.

And the royal and orderly desires are nearest?

Yes.

Then the tyrant will live at the greatest distance from true or natural pleasure, and the king at the least?

Certainly.

But if so, the tyrant will live most unpleasantly, and the king most pleasantly?

Inevitably.

Would you know the measure of the interval which separates them?

Will you tell me?

There appear to be three pleasures, one genuine and two spurious : now the transgression of the tyrant reaches a point beyond the spurious; he has run away from the region of law and reason, and taken up his abode with certain slave pleasures which are his satellites, and the measure of his inferiority can only be expressed in a figure.18

c

How do you mean?

I assume, I said, that the tyrant is in the third place from the oligarch;hr the democrat was in the middle?

Yes.

And if there is truth in what has preceded, he will be wedded to an image of pleasure which is thrice removed as to truth from the pleasure of the oligarch?

He will.

And the oligarch is third from the royal; hs since we count as one royal and aristocratical?

d

Yes, he is third.

Then the tyrant is removed from true pleasure by the space of a number which is three times three?

Manifestly.

The shadow, then, of tyrannical pleasure determined by the number of length will be a plane figure.

Certainly.

And if you raise the power and make the plane a solid, there is no difficulty in seeing how vast is the interval by which the tyrant is parted from the king.

Yes; the arithmetician will easily do the sum.

Or if some person begins at the other end and measures the interval by which the king is parted from the tyrant in truth of pleasure, he will find him, when the multiplication is completed, living 729 times more pleasantly, and the tyrant more painfully by this same interval.ht

e

What a wonderful calculation! And how enormous is the distance which separates the just from the unjust in regard to pleasure and pain!

588

Yet a true calculation, I said, and a number which nearly concerns human life, if human beings are concerned with days and nights and months and years.

Yes, he said, human life is certainly concerned with them. Then if the good and just man be thus superior in pleasure to the evil and unjust, his superiority will be infinitely greater in propriety of life and in beauty and virtue?

Immeasurably greater.

Well, I said, and now having arrived at this stage of the argument, we may revert to the words which brought us hither: Was not someone saying that injustice was a gain to the perfectly unjust who was reputed to be just?

b

Yes, that was said.

Now, then, having determined the power and quality of justice and injustice, let us have a little conversation with him.

What shall we say to him?

Let us make an image of the soul that he may have his own words presented before his eyes. 19

Of what sort?

c

An ideal image of the soul, like the composite creations of ancient mythology, such as the Chimera, or Scylla, or Cerberus, hu and there are many others in which two or more different natures are said to grow into one.

There are said to have been such unions.

Then do you now model the form of a multitudinous, many-headed monster, having a ring of heads of all manner of beasts, tame and wild, which he is able to generate and metamorphose at will.

You suppose marvellous powers in the artist; but, as language is more pliable than wax or any similar substance, let there be such a model as you propose.

d

Suppose now that you make a second form as of a lion, and a third of a man, the second smaller than the first, and the third smaller than the second.

That, he said, is an easier task; and I have made them as you say.

And now join them, and let the three grow into one.

That has been accomplished.

Next fashion the outside of them into a single image, as of a man, so that he who is not able to look within, and sees only the outer hull, may believe the beast to be a single human creature.

e

I have done so, he said.

And now, to him who maintains that it is profitable for the human creature to be unjust, and unprofitable to be just, let us reply that, if he be right, it is profitable for this creature to feast the multitudinous monster and strengthen the lion and the lion-like qualities, but to starve and weaken the man, who is consequently liable to be dragged about at the mercy of either of the other two; and he is not to attempt to familiarize or harmonize them with one another—he ought rather to suffer them to fight, and bite and devour one another.

589

Certainly, he said; that is what the approver of injustice says.

To him the supporter of justice makes answer that he should ever so speak and act as to give the man within him in some way or other the most complete mastery over the entire human creature. He should watch over the many-headed monster like a good husbandman, fostering and cultivating the gentle qualities, and preventing the wild ones from growing; he should be making the lion-heart his ally, and in common care of them all should be uniting the several parts with one another and with himself.

b

Yes, he said, that is quite what the maintainer of justice will say.

And so from every point of view, whether of pleasure, honor, or advantage, the approver of justice is right and speaks the truth, and the disapprover is wrong and false and ignorant?

c

Yes, from every point of view.

Come, now, and let us gently reason with the unjust, who is not intentionally in error.20 “Sweet sir,” we will say to him, “what think you of things esteemed noble and ignoble? Is not the noble that which subjects the beast to the man, or rather to the god in man? and the ignoble that which subjects the man to the beast?” He can hardly avoid saying, Yes—can he, now?

d

Not it he has any regard for my opinion.

But, if he agree so far, we may ask him to answer another question : “Then how would a man profit if he received gold and silver on the condition that he was to enslave the noblest part of him to the worst? Who can imagine that a man who sold his son or daughter into slavery for money, especially if he sold them into the hands of fierce and evil men, would be the gainer, however large might be the sum which he received?21 And will anyone say that he is not a miserable caitiff who remorselessly sells his own divine being to that which is most godless and detestable? Eriphyle took the necklace as the price of her husband’s life,hv but he is taking a bribe in order to compass a worse ruin.”

e
590

Yes, said Glaucon, far worse—I will answer for him.

Has not the intemperate been censured of old, because in him the huge multiform monster is allowed to be too much at large?

Clearly.

And men are blamed for pride and bad temper when the lion and serpent element in them disproportionately grows and gains strength?

b

Yes.

And luxury and softness are blamed, because they relax and weaken this same creature, and make a coward of him?

Very true.

And is not a man reproached for flattery and meanness who subordinates the spirited animal to the unruly monster, and, for the sake of money, of which he can never have enough, habituates him in the days of his youth to be trampled in the mire, and from being a lion to become a monkey?

True, he said.

c

And why are mean employments and manual arts a reproach?22 Only because they imply a natural weakness of the higher principle ; the individual is unable to control the creatures within him, but has to court them, and his great study is how to flatter them.

Such appears to be the reason.

And therefore, being desirous of placing him under a rule like that of the best, we say that he ought to be the servant of the best, in whom the Divine rules; not, as Thrasymachus supposed, to the injury of the servant, but because everyone had better be ruled by divine wisdom dwelling within him; or, if this be impossible, then by an external authority, in order that we may be all, as far as possible, under the same government, friends and equals.

d

True, he said.

And this is clearly seen to be the intention of the law, which is the ally of the whole city; and is seen also in the authority which we exercise over children, and the refusal to let them be free until we have established in them a principle analogous to the constitution of a State, and by cultivation of this higher element have set up in their hearts a guardian and ruler like our own, and when this is done they may go their ways.

e
591

Yes, he said, the purpose of the law is manifest.

From what point of view, then, and on what ground can we say that a man is profited by injustice or intemperance or other baseness, which will make him a worse man, even though he acquire money or power by his wickedness?

From no point of view at all.

What shall he profit, if his injustice be undetected and unpunished? He who is undetected only gets worse, 23 whereas he who is detected and punished has the brutal part of his nature silenced and humanized; the gentler element in him is liberated, and his whole soul is perfected and ennobled by the acquirement of justice and temperance and wisdom, more than the body ever is by receiving gifts of beauty, strength, and health, in proportion as the soul is more honorable than the body.

b

Certainly, he said.

To this nobler purpose the man of understanding will devote the energies of his life. And in the first place, he will honor studies which impress these qualities on his soul, and will disregard others?

c

Clearly, he said.

In the next place, he will regulate his bodily habit and training, and so far will he be from yielding to brutal and irrational pleasures, that he will regard even health as quite a secondary matter; his first object will be not that he may be fair or strong or well, unless he is likely thereby to gain temperance, but he will always desire so to attemper the body as to preserve the harmony of the soul?

d

Certainly he will, if he has true music in him.

And in the acquisition of wealth there is a principle of order and harmony which he will also observe; he will not allow himself to be dazzled by the foolish applause of the world, and heap up riches to his own infinite harm?

Certainly not, he said.

He will look at the city which is within him, and take heed that no disorder occur in it, such as might arise either from superfluity or from want; and upon this principle he will regulate his property and gain or spend according to his means.

e

Very true.

And, for the same reason, he will gladly accept and enjoy such honors as he deems likely to make him a better man; but those, whether private or public, which are likely to disorder his life, he will avoid?

592

Then, if that is his motive, he will not be a statesman.

By the dog of Egypt,hw he will! in the city which is his own he certainly will, though in the land of his birth perhaps not, unless he have a divine call.

I understand; you mean that he will be a ruler in the city of which we are the founders, and which exists in idea only; for I do not believe that there is such a one anywhere on earth?

b

In heaven, I replied, there is laid up a pattern of it, methinks, which he who desires may behold, and beholding, may set his own house in order. But whether such a one exists, or ever will exist in fact, is no matter;hx for he will live after the manner of that city, having nothing to do with any other.

I think so, he said.

BOOK 10

OF THE MANY EXCELLENCES which I perceive in the order of our State, there is none which upon reflection pleases me better than the rule about poetry.

595

To what do you refer?

To the rejection of imitative poetry, which certainly ought not to be received; as I see far more clearly now that the parts of the soul have been distinguished.1

b

What do you mean?

Speaking in confidence, for I should not like to have my words repeated to the tragedians and the rest of the imitative tribe—but I do not mind saying to you, that all poetical imitations are ruinous to the understanding of the hearers, and that the knowledge of their true nature is the only antidote to them.

Explain the purport of your remark.

Well, I will tell you, although I have always from my earliest youth had an awe and love of Homer, which even now makes the words falter on my lips, for he is the great captain and teacher of the whole of that charming tragic company;2 but a man is not to be reverenced more than the truth, and therefore I will speak out.

c

Very good, he said.

Listen to me, then, or, rather, answer me.

Put your question.

Can you tell me what imitation is? for I really do not know. 3 A likely thing, then, that I should know.

Why not? for the duller eye may often see a thing sooner than the keener.

596

Very true, he said; but in your presence, even if I had any faint notion, I could not muster courage to utter it. Will you inquire yourself?

Well, then, shall we begin the inquiry in our usual manner: Whenever a number of individuals have a common name, we assume them to have also a corresponding idea or form; do you understand me?

I do.

Let us take any common instance; there are beds and tables in the world—plenty of them, are there not?

b

Yes.

But there are only two ideas or forms of them—one the idea of a bed, the other of a table.4

True.

And the maker of either of them makes a bed or he makes a table for our use, in accordance with the idea—that is our way of speaking in this and similar instances—but no artificer makes the ideas themselves: how could he?

Impossible.

And there is another artist—I should like to know what you would say of him.

Who is he?

c

One who is the maker of all the works of all other workmen.

What an extraordinary man!

Wait a little, and there will be more reason for your saying so. For this is he who is able to make not only vessels of every kind, but plants and animals, himself and all other things—the earth and heaven, and the things which are in heaven or under the earth; he makes the gods also.

He must be a wizard and no mistake.

d

Oh! you are incredulous, are you? Do you mean that there is no such maker or creator, or that in one sense there might be a maker of all these things, but in another not? Do you see that there is a way in which you could make them all yourself?

What way?

An easy way enough; or rather, there are many ways in which the feat might be quickly and easily accomplished, none quicker than that of turning a mirror round and round—you would soon enough make the sun and the heavens, and the earth and yourself, and other animals and plants, and all the other things of which we were just now speaking, in the mirror.

e

Yes, he said; but they would be appearances only.

Very good, I said, you are coming to the point now. And the painter, too, is, as I conceive, just such another—a creator of appearances, is he not?

Of course.

But then I suppose you will say that what he creates is untrue. And yet there is a sense in which the painter also creates a bed?

Yes, he said, but not a real bed.

And what of the maker of the bed? were you not saying that he too makes, not the idea which, according to our view, is the essence of the bed, but only a particular bed?

597

Yes, I did.

Then if he does not make that which exists he cannot make true existence, but only some semblance of existence; and if anyone were to say that the work of the maker of the bed, or of any other workman, has real existence, he could hardly be supposed to be speaking the truth.

At any rate, he replied, philosophers would say that he was not speaking the truth.5

No wonder, then, that his work, too, is an indistinct expression of truth.

No wonder.

Suppose now that by the light of the examples just offered we inquire who this imitator is?

b

If you please.

Well, then, here are three beds: one existing in nature, which is made by God,hy as I think that we may say—for no one else can be the maker?

No.

There is another which is the work of the carpenter?

Yes.

And the work of the painter is a third?

Yes.

Beds, then, are of three kinds, and there are three artists who superintend them: God, the maker of the bed, and the painter?

Yes, there are three of them.

God, whether from choice or from necessity, made one bed in nature and one only; two or more such ideal beds neither ever have been nor ever will be made by God.

c

Why is that?

Because even if He had made but two, a third would still appear behind them which both of them would have for their idea, and that would be the ideal bed and not the two others.

Very true, he said.

God knew this, and he desired to be the real maker of a real bed, not a particular maker of a particular bed, and therefore he created a bed which is essentially and by nature one only.

d

So we believe.

Shall we, then, speak of him as the natural author or maker of the bed?

Yes, he replied; inasmuch as by the natural process of creation he is the author of this and of all other things.

And what shall we say of the carpenter—is not he also the maker of the bed?

Yes.

But would you call the painter a creator and maker?

Certainly not.

Yet if he is not the maker, what is he in relation to the bed?

I think, he said, that we may fairly designate him as the imitator of that which the others make.

e

Good, I said; then you call him who is third in the descent from nature an imitator?

Certainly, he said.

And the tragic poet is an imitator, and, therefore, like all other imitators, he is thrice removed from the king and from the truth?6

That appears to be so.

Then about the imitator we are agreed. And what about the painter? I would like to know whether he may be thought to imitate that which originally exists in nature, or only the creations of artists?

598

The latter.

As they are or as they appear? you have still to determine this.

What do you mean?

I mean, that you may look at a bed from different points of view, obliquely or directly or from any other point of view, and the bed will appear different, but there is no difference in reality. And the same of all things.

Yes, he said, the difference is only apparent.

Now let me ask you another question: Which is the art of painting designed to be—an imitation of things as they are, or as they appear—of appearance or of reality?

b

Of appearance.

Then the imitator, I said, is a long way off the truth, and can do all things because he lightly touches on a small part of them, and that part an image. For example: A painter will paint a cobbler, carpenter, or any other artist, though he knows nothing of their arts; and, if he is a good artist, he may deceive children or simple persons, when he shows them his picture of a carpenter from a distance, and they will fancy that they are looking at a real carpenter.

c

Certainly.

And whenever anyone informs us that he has found a man who knows all the arts, and all things else that anybody knows, and every single thing with a higher degree of accuracy than any other man—whoever tells us this, I think that we can only imagine him to be a simple creature who is likely to have been deceived by some wizard or actor whom he met, and whom he thought all-knowing, because he himself was unable to analyze the nature of knowledge and ignorance and imitation.

d

Most true.

And so, when we hear persons saying that the tragedians, and Homer, who is at their head, know all the arts and all things human, virtue as well as vice, and divine things too, for that the good poet cannot compose well unless he knows his subject, and that he who has not this knowledge can never be a poet, we ought to consider whether here also there may not be a similar illusion.7 Perhaps they may have come across imitators and been deceived by them; they may not have remembered when they saw their works that these were but imitations thrice removed from the truth, and could easily be made without any knowledge of the truth, because they are appearances only and not realities? Or, after all, they may be in the right, and poets do really know the things about which thev seem to the many to speak so well?

e
599

The question, he said, should by all means be considered.

Now do you suppose that if a person were able to make the original as well as the image, he would seriously devote himself to the image-making branch? Would he allow imitation to be the ruling principle of his life, as if he had nothing higher in him?

b

I should say not.

The real artist, who knew what he was imitating, would be interested in realities and not in imitations; and would desire to leave as memorials of himself works many and fair; and, instead of being the author of encomiums, he would prefer to be the theme of them.

Yes, he said, that would be to him a source of much greater honor and profit.

Then, I said, we must put a question to Homer;8 not about medicine, or any of the arts to which his poems only incidentally refer: we are not going to ask him, or any other poet, whether he has cured patients like Asclepius,hz or left behind him a school of medicine such as the Asclepiads were, or whether he only talks about medicine and other arts at second-hand; but we have a right to know respecting military tactics, politics, education, which are the chiefest and noblest subjects of his poems, and we may fairly ask him about them. “Friend Homer,” then we say to him, “if you are only in the second remove from truth in what you say of virtue, and not in the third—not an image maker or imitator—and if you are able to discern what pursuits make men better or worse in private or public life, tell us what State was ever better governed by your help? The good order of Lacedæmon is due to Lycurgus,ia and many other cities, great and small, have been similarly benefited by others; but who says that you have been a good legislator to them and have done them any good? Italy and Sicily boast of Charondas,ib and there is Solon who is renowned among us; but what city has anything to say about you?” Is there any city which he might name?

C
d
e

I think not, said Glaucon; not even the Homeridsic themselves pretend that he was a legislator.

Well, but is there any war on record which was carried on successfully by him, or aided by his counsels, when he was alive?

600

There is not.

Or is there any invention of his applicable to the arts or to human life, such as Thales the Milesianid or Anacharsis the Scythian,ie and other ingenious men have conceived, which is attributed to him?

There is absolutely nothing of the kind.

But, if Homer never did any public service, was he privately a guide or teacher of any?9 Had he in his lifetime friends who loved to associate with him, and who handed down to posterity a Homeric way of life, such as was established by Pythagoras,if who was so greatly beloved for his wisdom, and whose followers are to this day quite celebrated for the order which was named after him?

b

Nothing of the kind is recorded of him. For, surely, Socrates, Creophylus, the companion of Homer,10 that child of flesh, whose name always makes us laugh, might be more justly ridiculed for his stupidity, if, as is said, Homer was greatly neglected by him and others in his own day when he was alive?

c

Yes, I replied, that is the tradition. But can you imagine, Glaucon, that if Homer had really been able to educate and improve mankind—if he had possessed knowledge, and not been a mere imitator—can you imagine, I say, that he would not have had many followers, and been honored and loved by them?11 Protagoras of Abdera and Prodicus of Ceos12 and a host of others have only to whisper to their contemporaries: “You will never be able to manage either your own house or your own State until you appoint us to be your ministers of education”—and this ingenious device of theirs has such an effect in making men love them that their companions all but carry them about on their shoulders. And is it conceivable that the contemporaries of Homer, or again of Hesiod, would have allowed either of them to go about as rhapsodists, ig if they had really been able to make mankind virtuous? Would they not have been as unwilling to part with them as with gold, and have compelled them to stay at home with them? Or, if the master would not stay, then the disciples would have followed him about everywhere, until they had got education enough?

d
e

Yes, Socrates, that, I think, is quite true.

Then must we not infer that all these poetical individuals, beginning with Homer, are only imitators; they copy images of virtue and the like, but the truth they never reach? The poet is like a painter who, as we have already observed, will make a likeness of a cobbler though he understands nothing of cobbling; and his picture is good enough for those who know no more than he does, and judge only by colors and figures.

601

Quite so.

In like manner the poet with his words and phrases may be said to lay on the colors of the several arts, himself understanding their nature only enough to imitate them; and other people, who are as ignorant as he is, and judge only from his words, imagine that if he speaks of cobbling, or of military tactics, or of anything else, in metre and harmony and rhythm, he speaks very well—such is the sweet influence which melody and rhythm by nature have. And I think that you must have observed again and again what a poor appearance the tales of poets make when stripped of the colors which music puts upon them, and recited in simple prose.

b

Yes, he said.

They are like faces which were never really beautiful, but only blooming; and now the bloom of youth has passed away from them?

Exactly.

Here is another point: The imitator or maker of the image knows nothing of true existence; he knows appearances only. Am I not right?

c

Yes.

Then let us have a clear understanding, and not be satisfied with half an explanation.

Proceed.

Of the painter we say that he will paint reins, and he will paint a bit?

Yes.

And the worker in leather and brass will make them?

Certainly.

But does the painter know the right form of the bit and reins? Nay, hardly even the workers in brass and leather who make them; only the horseman who knows how to use them—he knows their right form.13

Most true.

And may we not say the same of all things?

What?

That there are three arts which are concerned with all things: one which uses, another which makes, a third which imitates them?

d

Yes.

And the excellence or beauty or truth of every structure, animate or inanimate, and of every action of man, is relative to the use for which nature or the artist has intended them.

True.

Then the user of them must have the greatest experience of them, and he must indicate to the maker the good or bad qualities which develop themselves in use; for example, the flute-player will tell the flute-maker which of his flutes is satisfactory to the performer; he will tell him how he ought to make them, and the other will attend to his instructions?

e

Of course.

The one knows and therefore speaks with authority about the goodness and badness of flutes, while the other, confiding in him, will do what he is told by him?

True.

The instrument is the same, but about the excellence or badness of it the maker will only attain to a correct belief; and this he will gain from him who knows, by talking to him and being compelled to hear what he has to say, whereas the user will have knowledge?

602

True.

But will the imitator have either? Will he know from use whether or no his drawing is correct or beautiful? or will he have right opinion from being compelled to associate with another who knows and gives him instructions about what he should draw?

Neither.

Then he will no more have true opinion than he will have knowledge about the goodness or badness of his imitations?

I suppose not.

The imitative artist will be in a brilliant state of intelligence about his own creations?

Nay, very much the reverse.

And still he will go on imitating without knowing what makes a thing good or bad, and may be expected therefore to imitate only that which appears to be good to the ignorant multitude?

b

Just so.

Thus far, then, we are pretty well agreed that the imitator has no knowledge worth mentioning of what he imitates. Imitation is only a kind of play or sport,14 and the tragic poets, whether they write in iambic or in heroic verse, are imitators in the highest degree?

Very true.

And now tell me, I conjure you, has not imitation been shown by us to be concerned with that which is thrice removed from the truth?

c

Certainly.

And what is the faculty in man to which imitation is addressed?

What do you mean?

I will explain: The body which is large when seen near, appears small when seen at a distance?

True.

And the same objects appear straight when looked at out of the water, and crooked when in the water; and the concave becomes convex, owing to the illusion about colors to which the sight is liable. Thus every sort of confusion is revealed within us; and this is that weakness of the human mind on which the art of conjuring and of deceiving by light and shadow and other ingenious devices imposes, having an effect upon us like magic.

d

True.

And the arts of measuring and numbering and weighing come to the rescue of the human understanding—there is the beauty of them—and the apparent greater or less, or more or heavier, no longer have the mastery over us, but give way before calculation and measure and weight?15

Most true.

And this, surely, must be the work of the calculating and rational principle in the soul?

e

To be sure.

And when this principle measures and certifies that some things are equal, or that some are greater or less than others, there occurs an apparent contradiction?

True.

But were we not saying that such a contradiction is impossible—the same faculty cannot have contrary opinions at the same time about the same thing?

Very true.

Then that part of the soul which has an opinion contrary to measure is not the same with that which has an opinion in accordance with measure?

603

True.

And the better part of the soul is likely to be that which trusts to measure and calculation?

Certainly.

And that which is opposed to them is one of the inferior principles of the soul?

No doubt.

This was the conclusion at which I was seeking to arrive when I said that painting or drawing, and imitation in general, when doing their own proper work, are far removed from truth, and the companions and friends and associates of a principle within us which is equally removed from reason, and that they have no true or healthy aim.

b

Exactly.

The imitative art is an inferior who marries an inferior, and has inferior offspring.

Very true.

And is this confined to the sight only, or does it extend to the hearing also, relating in fact to what we term poetry?

Probably the same would be true of poetry.

Do not rely, I said, on a probability derived from the analogy of painting; but let us examine further and see whether the faculty with which poetical imitation is concerned is good or bad.

c

By all means.

We may state the question thus: Imitation imitates the actions of men, whether voluntary or involuntary, on which, as they imagine, a good or bad result has ensued, and they rejoice or sorrow accordingly. Is there anything more?

No, there is nothing else.

But in all this variety of circumstances is the man at unity with himself—or, rather, as in the instance of sight there were confusion and opposition in his opinions about the same things, so here also are there not strife and inconsistency in his life? though I need hardly raise the question again, for I remember that all this has been already admitted; and the soul has been acknowledged by us to be full of these and ten thousand similar oppositions occurring at the same moment?“ih

d

And we were right, he said.

Yes, I said, thus far we were right; but there was an omission which must now be supplied.

e

What was the omission?

Were we not saying that a good man, who has the misfortune to lose his son or anything else which is most dear to him, will bear the loss with more equanimity than another?ii

Yes.

But will he have no sorrow, or shall we say that although he cannot help sorrowing, he will moderate his sorrow?

The latter, he said, is the truer statement.

Tell me: will he be more likely to struggle and hold out against his sorrow when he is seen by his equals, or when he is alone?

604

It will make a great difference whether he is seen or not. When he is by himself he will not mind saying or doing many things which he would be ashamed of anyone hearing or seeing him do?

True.

There is a principle of law and reason in him which bids him resist, as well as a feeling of his misfortune which is forcing him to indulge his sorrow?

b

True.

But when a man is drawn in two opposite directions, to and from the same object, this, as we affirm, necessarily implies two distinct principles in him?

Certainly.

One of them is ready to follow the guidance of the law? How do you mean?

The law would say that to be patient under suffering is best, and that we should not give way to impatience, as there is no knowing whether such things are good or evil; and nothing is gained by impatience; also, because no human thing is of serious importance, and grief stands in the way of that which at the moment is most required.

c

What is most required? he asked.

That we should take counsel about what has happened, and when the dice have been thrown order our affairs in the way which reason deems best; not, like childrenij who have had a fall, keeping hold of the part struck and wasting time in setting up a howl, but always accustoming the soul forthwith to apply a remedy, raising up that which is sickly and fallen, banishing the cry of sorrow by the healing art.

d

Yes, he said, that is the true way of meeting the attacks of fortune.

Yes, I said; and the higher principle is ready to follow this suggestion of reason?

Clearly.

And the other principle, which inclines us to recollection of our troubles and to lamentation, and can never have enough of them, we may call irrational, useless, and cowardly?

Indeed, we may.

And does not the latter—I mean the rebellious principle—furnish a great variety of materials for imitation? Whereas the wise and calm temperament, being always nearly equable, is not easy to imitate or to appreciate when imitated, especially at a public festival when a promiscuous crowd is assembled in a theatre. For the feeling represented is one to which they are strangers.16

e

Certainly.

605

Then the imitative poet who aims at being popular is not by nature made, nor is his art intended, to please or to affect the rational principle in the soul; but he will prefer the passionate and fitful temper, which is easily imitated?

Clearly.

And now we may fairly take him and place him by the side of the painter, for he is like him in two ways: first, inasmuch as his creations have an inferior degree of truth—in this, I say, he is like him; and he is also like him in being concerned with an inferior part of the soul; and therefore we shall be right in refusing to admit him into a well-ordered State, because he awakens and nourishes and strengthens the feelings and impairs the reason. As in a city when the evil are permitted to have authority and the good are put out of the way, so in the soul of man, as we maintain, the imitative poet implants an evil constitution, for he indulges the irrational nature which has no discernment of greater and less, but thinks the same thing at one time great and at another small—he is a manufacturer of images and is very far removed from the truth.

b
c

Exactly.

But we have not yet brought forward the heaviest count in our accusation: the power which poetry has of harming even the good (and there are very few who are not harmed), is surely an awful thing?

Yes, certainly, if the effect is what you say.

Hear and judge: The best of us, as I conceive, when we listen to a passage of Homer or one of the tragedians, in which he represents some pitiful hero who is drawling out his sorrows in a long oration, or weeping, and smiting his breast—the best of us, you know, delight in giving way to sympathy, and are in raptures at the excellence of the poet who stirs our feelings most.17

Yes, of course, I know.

d

But when any sorrow of our own happens to us, then you may observe that we pride ourselves on the opposite quality—we would fain be quiet and patient; this is the manly part, and the other which delighted us in the recitation is now deemed to be the part of a woman.

e

Very true, he said.

Now can we be right in praising and admiring another who is doing that which any one of us would abominate and be ashamed of in his own person?

No, he said, that is certainly not reasonable.

Nay, I said, quite reasonable from one point of view.

606

What point of view?

If you consider, I said, that when in misfortune we feel a natural hunger and desire to relieve our sorrow by weeping and lamentation, and that this feeling which is kept under control in our own calamities is satisfied and delighted by the poets; the better nature in each of us, not having been sufficiently trained by reason or habit, allows the sympathetic element to break loose because the sorrow is another’s; and the spectator fancies that there can be no disgrace to himself in praising and pitying anyone who comes telling him what a good man he is, and making a fuss about his troubles; he thinks that the pleasure is a gain, and why should he be supercilious and lose this and the poem too? Few persons ever reflect, as I should imagine, that from the evil of other men something of evil is communicated to themselves. And so the feeling of sorrow which has gathered strength at the sight of the misfortunes of others is with difficulty repressed in our own.

b

How very true!

c

And does not the same hold also of the ridiculous? There are jests which you would be ashamed to make yourself, and yet on the comic stage, or indeed in private, when you hear them, you are greatly amused by them, and are not at all disgusted at their unseemliness; the case of pity is repeated; there is a principle in human nature which is disposed to raise a laugh, and this which you once restrained by reason, because you were afraid of being thought a buffoon, is now let out again; and having stimulated the risible faculty at the theatre, you are betrayed unconsciously to yourself into playing the comic poet at home.

Quite true, he said.

And the same may be said of lust and anger and all the other affections, of desire, and pain, and pleasure, which are held to be inseparable from every action—in all of them poetry feeds and waters the passions instead of drying them up; she lets them rule, although they ought to be controlled, if mankind are ever to increase in happiness and virtue.

d

I cannot deny it.

Therefore, Glaucon, I said, whenever you meet with any of the eulogists of Homer declaring that he has been the educator of Hellas, and that he is profitable for education and for the ordering of human things, and that you should take him up again and again and get to know him and regulate your whole life according to him, we may love and honor those who say these things—they are excellent people, as far as their lights extend; and we are ready to acknowledge that Homer is the greatest of poets and first of tragedy writers; but we must remain firm in our conviction that hymns to the gods and praises of famous men are the only poetry which ought to be admitted into our State. For if you go beyond this and allow the honeyed muse to enter, either in epic or lyric verse, pleasure and pain will be kings in your state, and not law and the rational principle that is always judged best for the common interest.18

e
607

That is most true, he said.

And now since we have reverted to the subject of poetry, let this our defence serve to show the reasonableness of our former judgment in sending away out of our State an art having the tendencies which we have described; for reason constrained us. But that sheik may not impute to us any harshness or want of polite-ness, let us tell her that there is an ancient quarrel between philosophy and poetry; of which there are many proofs,19 such as the saying of “the yelping hound howling at her lord,” or of one “mighty in the vain talk of fools,” and “the mob of sages circumventing Zeus,” and the “subtle thinkers who are beggars after all”;il and there are innumerable other signs of ancient enmity between them. Notwithstanding this, let us assure our sweet friend and the sister art of imitation, that if she will only prove her title to exist in a well-ordered State we shall be delighted to receive her—we are very conscious of her charms; but we may not on that account betray the truth. I dare say, Glaucon, that you are as much charmed by her as I am, especially when she appears in Homer?

b
c
d

Yes, indeed, I am greatly charmed.

Shall I propose, then, that she be allowed to return from exile, but upon this condition only—that she make a defence of herself in lyrical or some other metre?

Certainly.

And we may further grant to those of her defenders who are lovers of poetry and yet not poets the permission to speak in prose on her behalf: let them show not only that she is pleasant, but also useful to States and to human life, and we will listen in a kindly spirit; for if this can be proved we shall surely be the gainers—I mean, if there is a use in poetry as well as a delight?

e

Certainly, he said, we shall be the gainers.

If her defence fails, then, my dear friend, like other persons who are enamoured of something, but put a restraint upon themselves when they think their desires are opposed to their interests, so, too, must we after the manner of lovers give her up, though not without a struggle. We, too, are inspired by that love of poetry which the education of noble States has implanted in us, and therefore we would have her appear at her best and truest; but so long as she is unable to make good her defence, this argument of ours shall be a charm to us, which we will repeat to ourselves while we listen to her strains; that we may not fall away into the childish love of her which captivates the many. At all events we are well aware that poetry being such as we have described is not to be regarded seriously as attaining to the truth; and he who listens to her, fearing for the safety of the city which is within him, should be on his guard against her seductions and make our words his law.

608
b

Yes, he said, I quite agree with you.

Yes, I said, my dear Glaucon, for great is the issue at stake, greater than appears, whether a man is to be good or bad.20 And what will anyone be profited if under the influence of honor or money or power, aye, or under the excitement of poetry, he neglect justice and virtue?

Yes, he said; I have been convinced by the argument, as I believe that anyone else would have been.

And yet no mention has been made of the greatest prizes and rewards which await virtue.21

c

What, are there any greater still? If there are, they must be of an inconceivable greatness.

Why, I said, what was ever great in a short time? The whole period of threescore years and tenim is surely but a little thing in comparison with eternity?

Say rather ‘nothing,’ he replied.

And should an immortal being seriously think of this little space rather than of the whole?

d

Of the whole, certainly. But why do you ask?

Are you not aware, I said, that the soul of man is immortal and imperishable?22

He looked at me in astonishment, and said: No, by heaven: And are you really prepared to maintain this?23

Yes, I said, I ought to be, and you too—there is no difficulty in proving it.

I see a great difficulty; but I should like to hear you state this argument of which you make so light.

Listen, then.

I am attending.

There is a thing which you call good and another which you call evil?

Yes, he replied.

Would you agree with me in thinking that the corrupting and destroying element is the evil, and the saving and improving element the good?

e

Yes.

And you admit that everything has a good and also an evil; as ophthalmiain is the evil of the eyes and disease of the whole body; as mildew is of corn, and rot of timber, or rust of copper and iron: in everything, or in almost everything, there is an inherent evil and disease?

609

Yes, he said.

And anything which is infected by any of these evils is made evil, and at last wholly dissolves and dies?

True.

The vice and evil which are inherent in each are the destruction of each; and if these do not destroy them there is nothing else that will; for good certainly will not destroy them, nor, again, that which is neither good nor evil.

b

Certainly not.

If, then, we find any nature which having this inherent corruption cannot be dissolved or destroyed, we may be certain that of such a nature there is no destruction?

That may be assumed.

Well, I said, and is there no evil which corrupts the soul?

Yes, he said, there are all the evils which we were just now passing in review: unrighteousness, intemperance, cowardice, ignorance.

c

But does any of these dissolve or destroy her?—and here do not let us fall into the error of supposing that the unjust and foolish man, when he is detected, perishes through his own injustice, which is an evil of the soul. Take the analogy of the body: The evil of the body is a disease which wastes and reduces and annihilates the body; and all the things of which we were just now speaking come to annihilation through their own corruption attaching to them and inhering in them and so destroying them. Is not this true?

d

Yes.

Consider the soul in like manner. Does the injustice or other evil which exists in the soul waste and consume her? Do they by attaching to the soul and inhering in her at last bring her to death, and so separate her from the body?

Certainly not.

And yet, I said, it is unreasonable to suppose that anything can perish from without through affection of external evil which could not be destroyed from within by a corruption of its own?

It is, he replied.

Consider, I said, Glaucon, that even the badness of food, whether staleness, decomposition, or any other bad quality, when confined to the actual food, is not supposed to destroy the body; although, if the badness of food communicates corruption to the body, then we should say that the body has been destroyed by a corruption of itself, which is disease, brought on by this; but that the body, being one thing, can be destroyed by the badness of the food, which is another, and which does not engender any natural infection—this we shall absolutely deny?

e
610

Very true.

And, on the same principle, unless some bodily evil can produce an evil of the soul, we must not suppose that the soul, which is one thing, can be dissolved by any merely external evil which belongs to another?

Yes, he said, there is reason in that.

Either, then, let us refute this conclusion, or, while it remains unrefuted, let us never say that fever, or any other disease, or the knife put to the throat, or even the cutting up of the whole body into the minutest pieces, can destroy the soul, until she herself is proved to become more unholy or unrighteous in consequence of these things being done to the body; but that the soul, or anything else if not destroyed by an internal evil, can be destroyed by an external one, is not to be affirmed by any man.

b
c

And surely, he replied, no one will ever prove that the souls of men become more unjust in consequence of death.

But if someone who would rather not admit the immortality of the soul boldly denies this, and says that the dying do really become more evil and unrighteous, then, if the speaker is right, I suppose that injustice, like disease, must be assumed to be fatal to the unjust, and that those who take this disorder die by the natural inherent power of destruction which evil has, and which kills them sooner or later, but in quite another way from that in which, at present, the wicked receive death at the hands of others as the penalty of their deeds?

d

Nay, he said, in that case injustice, if fatal to the unjust, will not be so very terrible to him, for he will be delivered from evil. But I rather suspect the opposite to be the truth, and that injustice which, if it have the power, will murder others, keeps the murderer alive—aye, and well awake, too; so far removed is her dwelling-place from being a house of death.

e

True, I said; if the inherent natural vice or evil of the soul is unable to kill or destroy her, hardly will that which is appointed to be the destruction of some other body, destroy a soul or anything else except that of which it was appointed to be the destruction.

Yes, that can hardly be.

But the soul which cannot be destroyed by an evil, whether inherent or external, must exist forever, and, if existing forever, must be immortal?

611

Certainly.

That is the conclusion, I said; and, if a true conclusion, then the souls must always be the same, for if none be destroyed they will not diminish in number. Neither will they increase, for the increase of the immortal natures must come from something mortal, and all things would thus end in immortality.

Very true.

But this we cannot believe—reason will not allow us—any more than we can believe the soul, in her truest nature, to be full of variety and difference and dissimilarity.24

b

What do you mean? he said.

It is not easy, I said, for something to be immortal that is compounded out of many elements and not compounded in the finest way, as now seemed to us to be the case with the soul.

Certainly not.

Her immortality is demonstrated by the previous argument, and there are many other proofs; but to see her as she really is, not as we now behold her, marred by communion with the body and other miseries, you must contemplate her with the eye of reason, in her original purity; and then her beauty will be revealed, and justice and injustice and all the things which we have described will be manifested more clearly. Thus far, we have spoken the truth concerning her as she appears at present, but we must remember also that we have seen her only in a condition which may be compared to that of the sea-god Glaucus,io whose original image can hardly be discerned because his natural members are broken off and crushed and damaged by the waves in all sorts of ways, and incrustations have grown over them of sea-weed and shells and stones, so that he is more like some monster than he is to his own natural form. And the soul which we behold is in a similar condition, disfigured by ten thousand ills. But not there, Glaucon, not there must we look.

c
d

Where, then?

At her love of wisdom. ip Let us see whom she affects, and what society and converse she seeks in virtue of her near kindred with the immortal and eternal and divine; also how different she would become if, wholly following this superior principle, and borne by a divine impulse out of the ocean in which she now is, and disengaged from the stones and shells and things of earth and rock which in wild variety spring up around her because she feeds upon earth, and is overgrown by the good things in this life as they are termed:iq then you would see her as she is, and know whether she have one shape only or many, or what her nature is. Of her affections and of the forms which she takes in this present life I think that we have now said enough.

True, he replied.

e
612

And thus, I said, we have fulfilled the conditions of the argument ; we have not introduced the rewards and glories of justice, which, as you were saying, are to be found in Homer and Hesiod; but justice in her own nature has been shown to be the best for the soul in her own nature. Let a man do what is just, whether he have the ring of Gyges or not, and even if in addition to the ring of Gyges he put on the helmet of Hades.ir

b

Very true.

And now, Glaucon, there will be no harm in further enumerating how many and how great are the rewards which justice and the other virtues procure to the soul from gods and men, both in life and after death.

c

Certainly not, he said.

Will you repay me, then, what you borrowed in the argument? 25

What did I borrow?

The assumption that the just man should appear unjust and the unjust just: for you were of opinion that even if the true state of the case could not possibly escape the eyes of gods and men, still this admission ought to be made for the sake of the argument, in order that pure justice might be weighed against pure injustice. Do you remember?

d

I should be much to blame it I had torgotten.

Then, as the cause is decided, I demand on behalf of justice that the estimation in which she is held by gods and men and which we acknowledge to be her due should now be restored to her by us; since she has been shown to confer reality, and not to deceive those who truly possess her, let what has been taken from her be given back, that so she may win that palm of appearance which is hers also, and which she gives to her own.is

The demand, he said, is just.

e

In the first place, I said—and this is the first thing which you will have to give back—the nature both of the just and unjust is truly known to the gods.

Granted.

And if they are both known to them, one must be the friend and the other the enemy of the gods, as we admitted from the beginning?it

True.

And the friend of the gods may be supposed to receive from them all things at their best, excepting only such evil as is the necessary consequence of former sins?

613

Certainly.

Then this must be our notion of the just man, that even when he is in poverty or sickness, or any other seeming misfortune, all things will in the end work together for good to him in life and death: for the gods have a care of anyone whose desire is to become just and to be like God, as far as man can attain the divine likeness, by the pursuit of virtue?

b

Yes, he said; if he is like God he will surely not be neglected by him.

And of the unjust may not the opposite be supposed?

Certainly.

Such, then, are the palms of victory which the gods give the just?

That is my conviction.

And what do they receive of men? Look at things as they really are, and you will see that the clever unjust are in the case of runners, who run well from the starting-place to the goal, but not back again from the goal: iu they go off at a great pace, but in the end only look foolish, slinking away with their ears draggling on their shoulders, and without a crown; but the true runner comes to the finish and receives the prize and is crowned. And this is the way with the just; he who endures to the end of every action and occasion of his entire life has a good report and carries off the prize which men have to bestow.

c

True.

And now you must allow me to repeat of the just the blessings which you were attributing to the fortunate unjust.26 I shall say of them, what you were saying of the others, that as they grow older, they become rulers in their own city if they care to be; they marry whom they like and give in marriage to whom they will; all that you said of the others I now say of these. And, on the other hand, of the unjust I say that the greater number, even though they escape in their youth, are found out at last and look foolish at the end of their course, and when they come to be old and miserable are flouted alike by stranger and citizen; they are beaten, and then come those things unfit for ears polite, as you truly term them; they will be racked and have their eyes burned out, as you were saying. And you may suppose that I have repeated the remainder of your tale of horrors. But will you let me assume, without reciting them, that these things are true?

d
e

Certainly, he said, what you say is true.

These, then, are the prizes and rewards and gifts which are bestowed upon the just by gods and men in this present life, in addition to the other good things which justice of herself provides.

614

Yes, he said; and they are fair and lasting.

And yet, I said, all these are as nothing either in number or greatness in comparison with those other recompenses which await both just and unjust after death.iv And you ought to hear them, and then both just and unjust will have received from us a full payment of the debt which the argument owes to them.

Speak, he said; there are few things which I would more gladly hear.

b

Well, I said, I will tell you a tale;27 not one of the tales which Odysseus tells to the hero Alcinoüs, yet this, too, is a tale of a hero, Er the son of Armenius, a Pamphylian by birth.28 He was slain in battle, and ten days afterward, when the bodies of the dead were taken up already in a state of corruption, his body was found unaffected by decay, and carried away home to be buried. And on the twelfth day, as he was lying on the funeral pyre, he returned to life and told them what he had seen in the other world. He said that when his soul left the body he went on a journey with a great company, and that they came to a mysterious place at which there were two openings in the earth; they were near together, and over against them were two other openings in the heaven above. In the intermediate space there were judges seated, who commanded the just, after they had given judgment on them and had bound their sentences in front of them, to ascend by the heavenly way on the right hand; and in like manner the unjust were bidden by them to descend by the lower way on the left hand; these also bore the symbols of their deeds, but fastened on their backs. He drew near, and they told him that he was to be the messenger who would carry the report of the other world to them, and they bade him hear and see all that was to be heard and seen in that place. Then he beheld and saw on one side the souls departing at either opening of heaven and earth when sentence had been given on them; and at the two other openings other souls, some ascending out of the earth dusty and worn with travel, some descending out of heaven clean and bright. And arriving ever and anon they seemed to have come from a long journey, and they went forth with gladness into the meadow, where they encamped as at a festival; and those who knew one another embraced and conversed, the souls which came from earth curiously inquiring about the things above, and the souls which came from heaven about the things beneath. And they told one another of what had happened by the way, those from below weeping and sorrowing at the remembrance of the things which they had endured and seen in their journey beneath the earth (now the journey lasted a thousand years),iw while those from above were describing heavenly delights and visions of inconceivable beauty. The story, Glaucon, would take too long to tell; but the sum was this: He said that for every wrong which they had done to anyone they suffered tenfold; or once in a hundred years—such being reckoned to be the length of man’s life, and the penalty being thus paid ten times in a thousand years. If, for example, there were any who had been the cause of many deaths, or had betrayed or enslaved cities or armies, or been guilty of any other evil behavior, for each and all of their offences they received punishment ten times over, and the rewards of beneficence and justice and holiness were in the same proportion. I need hardly repeat what he said concerning young children dying almost as soon as they were born. Of piety and impiety to gods and parents, and of murderers, there were retributions other and greater far which he described. He mentioned that he was present when one of the spirits asked another, “Where is Ardiaeus the Great?”ix (Now this Ardiaeus lived a thousand years before the time of Er: he had been the tyrant of some city of Pamphylia, and had murdered his aged father and his elder brother, and was said to have committed many other abominable crimes.) The answer of the other spirit was: “He comes not hither, and will never come.”iy And this, said he, was one of the dreadful sights which we ourselves witnessed. We were at the mouth of the cavern, and, having completed all our experiences, were about to reascend, when of a sudden Ardiaeus appeared and several others, most of whom were tyrants; and there were also, besides the tyrants, private individuals who had been great criminals: they were just, as they fancied, about to return into the upper world, but the mouth, instead of admitting them, gave a roar, whenever any of these incurable sinners or someone who had not been sufficiently punished tried to ascend; and then wild men of fiery aspect, who were standing by and heard the sound, seized and carried them off; and Ardiaeus and others they bound head and foot and hand, and threw them down and flayed them with scourges, and dragged them along the road at the side, carding them on thorns like wool, and declaring to the passers-by what were their crimes and that they were being taken away to be cast into hell.iz And of all the many terrors which they had endured, he said that there was none like the terror which each of them felt at that moment, lest they should hear the voice; and when there was silence, one by one they ascended with exceeding joy. These, said Er, were the penalties and retributions, and there were blessings as great.

c
d
e
615
b
c
d
e
616
b

Now when the spirits which were in the meadow had tarried seven days, on the eighth they were obliged to proceed on their journey, and, on the fourth day after, he said that they came to a place where they could see from above a line of light, straight as a column, extending right through the whole heaven and through the earth, in color resembling the rainbow, only brighter and purer; another day’s journey brought them to the place, and there, in the midst of the light, they saw the ends of the chains of heaven let down from above:29 for this light is the belt of heaven, and holds together the circle of the universe,30 like the under-girders of a trireme.ja From these ends is extended the spindle of Necessity, jb on which all the revolutions turn. The shaft and hook of this spindle are made of steel, and the whorljc is made partly of steel and also partly of other materials.31 Now the whorl is in form like the whorl used on earth; and the description of it implied that there is one large hollow whorl which is quite scooped out, and into this is fitted another lesser one, and another, and another, and four others, making eight in all, like vessels which fit into one another; the whorls show their edges on the upper side, and on their lower side all together form one continuous whorl. This is pierced by the spindle, which is driven home through the centre of the eighth. The first and outermost whorl has the rim broadest, and the seven inner whorls are narrower, in the following proportions—the sixth is next to the first in size, the fourth next to the sixth; then comes the eighth; the seventh is fifth, the fifth is sixth, the third is seventh, last and eighth comes the second. The largest (or fixed stars) is spangled, and the seventh (or sun) is brightest; the eighth (or moon) colored by the reflected light of the seventh; the second and fifth (Saturn and Mercury) are in color like one another, and yellower than the preceding; the third (Venus) has the whitest light; the fourth (Mars) is reddish; the sixth (Jupiter) is in whiteness second. Now the whole spindle has the same motion; but, as the whole revolves in one direction, the seven inner circles move slowly in the other, and of these the swiftest is the eighth; next in swiftness are the seventh, sixth, and fifth, which move together; third in swiftness appeared to move according to the law of this reversed motion, the fourth; the third appeared fourth, and the second fifth. The spindle turns on the knees of Necessity; and on the upper surface of each circle is a siren,jd who goes round with them, hymning a single tone or note.32 The eight together form one harmony,33 and round about, at equal intervals, there is another band, three in number, each sitting upon her throne: these are the Fates,je daughters of Necessity, who are clothed in white robes and have chaplets upon their heads, Lachesis and Clotho and Atropos, who accompany with their voices the harmony of the sirens—Lachesis singing of the past, Clotho of the present, Atropos of the future; Clotho from time to time assisting with a touch of her right hand the revolution of the outer circle of the whorl or spindle, and Atropos with her left hand touching and guiding the inner ones, and Lachesis laying hold of either in turn, first with one hand and then with the other.

c
d
e
617
b
c
d

When Er and the spirits arrived, their duty was to go at once to Lachesis; but first of all there came a prophet who arranged them in order; then he took from the knees of Lachesis lots and samples of lives, and having mounted a high pulpit, spoke as follows: “Hear the word of Lachesis, the daughter of Necessity. Mortal souls, behold a new cycle of life and mortality. Your geniusjf will not be allotted to you, but you will choose your genius; and let him who draws the first lot have the first choice, and the life which he chooses shall be his destiny. Virtue is free, and as a man honors or dishonors her he will have more or less of her; the responsibility is with the chooser—God is justified.“34 When the Interpreter had thus spoken he scattered lots indifferently among them all, and each of them took up the lot which fell near him, all but Er himself (he was not allowed), and each as he took his lot perceived the number which he had obtained. Then the Interpreter placed on the ground before them the samples of lives; and there were many more lives than the souls present, and they were of all sorts. There were lives of every animal and of man in every condition. And there were tyrannies among them, some lasting out the tyrant’s life, others which broke off in the middle and came to an end in poverty and exile and beggary; and there were lives of famous men, some who were famous for their form and beauty as well as for their strength and success in games, or, again, for their birth and the qualities of their ancestors; and some who were the reverse of famous for the opposite qualities. And of women likewise; there was not, however, any definite character in them, because the soul, when choosing a new life, must of necessity become different. But there was every other quality, and they all mingled with one another, and also with elements of wealth and poverty, and disease and health; and there were mean states also. And here, my dear Glaucon, is the supreme peril of our human state; and therefore the utmost care should be taken. Let each one of us leave every other kind of knowledge and seek and follow one thing only, if peradventure he may be able to learn and may find someone who will make him able to learn and discern between good and evil, and so to choose always and everywhere the better life as he has opportunity. He should consider the bearing of all these things which have been mentioned severally and collectively upon virtue; he should know what the effect of beauty is when combined with poverty or wealth in a particular soul, and what are the good and evil consequences of noble and humble birth, of private and public station, of strength and weakness, of cleverness and dulness, and of all the natural and acquired gifts of the soul, and the operation of them when conjoined; he will then look at the nature of the soul, and from the consideration of all these qualities he will be able to determine which is the better and which is the worse; and so he will choose, giving the name of evil to the life which will make his soul more unjust, and good to the life which will make his soul more just; all else he will disregard. For we have seen and know that this is the best choice both in life and after death. A man must take with him into the world below an adamantine faith in truth and right, that there too he may be undazzled by the desire of wealth or the other allurements of evil, lest, coming upon tyrannies and similar villainies, he do irremediable wrongs to others and suffer yet worse himself; but let him know how to choose the mean and avoid the extremes on either side, as far as possible, not only in this life but in all that which is to come. For this is the way of happiness.

e
e
619
b
618
b
c
d

And according to the report of the messenger from the other world this was what the prophet said at the time: “Even for the last comer, if he chooses wisely and will live diligently, there is appointed a happy and not undesirable existence. Let not him who chooses first be careless, and let not the last despair.” And when he had spoken, he who had the first choice came forward and in a moment chose the greatest tyranny; his mind having been darkened by folly and sensuality, he had not thought out the whole matter before he chose, and did not at first sight perceive that he was fated, among other evils, to devour his own children. But when he had time to reflect, and saw what was in the lot, he began to beat his breast and lament over his choice, forgetting the proclamation of the prophet; for, instead of throwing the blame of his misfortune on himself, he accused chance and the gods, and everything rather than himself. Now he was one of those who came from heaven, and in a former life had dwelt in a well-ordered State, but his virtue was a matter of habit only, and he had no philosophy. And it was true of others who were similarly overtaken, that the greater number of them came from heaven and therefore they had never been schooled by trial, whereas the pilgrims who came from earth, having themselves suffered and seen others suffer, were not in a hurry to choose. And owing to this inexperience of theirs, and also because the lot was a chance, many of the souls exchanged a good destiny for an evil or an evil for a good. For if a man had always on his arrival in this world dedicated himself from the first to sound philosophy, and had been moderately fortunate in the number of the lot, he might, as the messenger reported, be

c
d
e

happy here, and also his journey to another life and return to this, instead of being rough and underground, would be smooth and heavenly. Most curious, he said, was the spectacle—sad and laughable and strange; for the choice of the souls was in most cases based on their experience of a previous life. There he saw the soul which had once been Orpheus choosing the life of a swan out of enmity to the race of women, hating to be born of a woman because they had been his murderers;jg he beheld also the soul of Thamyras choosing the life of a nightingale;jh birds, on the other hand, like the swans and other musicians, wanting to be men. The soul which obtained the twentieth lot chose the life of a lion, and this was the soul of Ajax the son of Telamon,ji who would not be a man, remembering the injustice which was done him in the judgment about the arms. The next was Agamemnon, who took the life of an eagle, because, like Ajax, he hated human nature by reason of his sufferings. About the middle came the lot of Atalanta;jj she, seeing the great fame of an athlete, was unable to resist the temptation: and after her there followed the soul of Epeus the son of Panopeus passing into the nature of a woman cunning in the arts; and far away among the last who chose, the soul of the jester Thersitesjk was putting on the form of a monkey. There came also the soul of Odysseus having yet to make a choice, and his lot happened to be the last of them all. Now the recollection of former toils had disenchanted him of ambition, and he went about for a considerable time in search of the life of a private man who had no cares; he had some difficulty in finding this, which was lying about and had been neglected by everybody else; and when he saw it, he said that he would have done the same had his lot been first instead of last, and that he was delighted to have it. And not only did men pass into animals, but I must also mention that there were animals tame and wild who changed into one another and into corresponding human natures—the good into the gentle and the evil into the savage, in all sorts of combinations.

620
b
c
d

All the souls had now chosen their lives, and they went in the order of their choice to Lachesis, who sent with them the genius whom they had severally chosen, to be the guardian of their lives and the fulfiller of the choice: this genius led the souls first to Clotho, and drew them within the revolution of the spindle impelled by her hand, thus ratifying the destiny of each; and then, when they were fastened to this, carried them to Atropos, who spun the threads and made them irreversible, whence without turning round they passed beneath the throne of Necessity; and when they had all passed, they marched on in a scorching heat to the plain of Forgetfulness,jl which was a barren waste destitute of trees and verdure; and then toward evening they encamped by the river of Unmindfulness, whose water no vessel can hold; of this they were all obliged to drink a certain quantity, and those who were not saved by wisdom drank more than was necessary; and each one as he drank forgot all things. Now after they had gone to rest, about the middle of the night there were a thunderstorm and earthquake, and then in an instant they were driven upward in all manner of ways to their birth, like stars shooting. He himself was hindered from drinking the water. But in what manner or by what means he returned to the body he could not say; only, in the morning, awaking suddenly, he found himself lying on the pyre.

e
621
b

And thus, Glaucon, the tale has been saved and has not perished, and will save us if we are obedient to the word spoken; and we shall pass safely over the river of Forgetfulness, and our soul will not be defiled. Wherefore my counsel is that we hold fast ever to the heavenly way and follow after justice and virtue always, considering that the soul is immortal and able to endure every sort of good and every sort of evil. Thus shall we live dear to one another and to the gods, both while remaining here and when, like conquerors in the games who go round to gather gifts, we receive our reward. And it shall be well with us both in this life and in the pilgrimage of a thousand years which we have been describing.35

c
d

ENDNOTES

Book 1

1 (1.331d) if Simonides is to be believed: Like his father, Cephalus, who quotes Pindar to support his views (1.331), Polemarchus cites a saying of Simonides as justification for his understanding of justice. Both poets are quoted again in book 2 along with several others (namely Homer, Hesiod, Aeschylus), as Glaucon and Adeimantus detail how poetry helps perpetuate the commonly accepted view of justice as an unprofitable inconvenience (see especially 2.363a-366a). These early indications of poetry’s influence on basic ethical attitudes and beliefs prepare for Socrates’ focus, in books 2 and beyond, on poetic “imitation” (mimesis) and on poetry’s role in education and acculturation.

2 (1.332b) And are enemies also to receive what we owe to them?: The notion that it is proper to help friends and harm enemies is asserted in a variety of poetic texts from the archaic and classical periods. The poem composed by the Athenian statesman Solon (late seventh to early sixth centuries B.C.E.), which begins with an invocation to the Muses, is exemplary; in its first few verses, the author prays, “Grant me prosperity from the blessed gods and let me have respect from all men; may I be sweet to my friends and bitter to my enemies.”

3 (1.332b) an enemy ... owes to an enemy that which is due or proper to himthat is to say, evil: In Crito and other dialogues, Plato represents Socrates vigorously contesting the notion that it is acceptable (and just) to harm one’s enemies and retaliate against those who have caused injury.

4 ( 1.332c) if we asked him what due or proper thing is given by medicine, and to whom, what answer do you think that he would make to us?: Analogies comparing justice—whether in everyday moral choices made by individuals, as here, or in the authority exercised by political leaders, as at 1.340d ft.—to various arts and skills (technai in Greek—for example, of the doctor, helmsman, and musician) are central to Republic’s analysis of justice. The implications of these analogies are considerable, as are the effects. One important effect is to suggest a link between “justice” and knowledge, or expertise, which enables one to distinguish between appearance (seeming) and reality (being), as at 1.334c-335b and 1.339d-341a. These suggestions set the stage for Socrates’ subsequent arguments that “justice” in the individual results from the rule of the soul’s rational (that is, knowledgeable) principle over “spirit” and “appetites” (book 4), and that justice in the state can be realized only when the rulers are “philosophers” (books 5-7).

5 (1.334a) a lesson which I suspect you must have learnt out of Homer: Several epic poems composed in dactylic hexameter, including Iliad and Odyssey, were attributed to “Homer” in antiquity. Iliad is set at and around Troy (a non-Greek city in Asia Minor) in the tenth year of the legendary war between the Greeks and the Trojans; Odyssey relates the homecoming of Odysseus to the island of Ithaca in the tenth year after the Greek victory at Troy. Unlike Plato’s interlocutors, modern scholars (with a few exceptions) tend to view Iliad and Odyssey as products of centuries of oral story-telling and poetic improvisation, rather than creations of a single individual (that is, “Homer”). Iliad and Odyssey, in more or less the forms that they now have, became widely known throughout Greece during the latter half (650-500 B.C.E.) of the archaic period, and Athenians in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E. revered them as key cultural landmarks. Several Platonic dialogues, including Republic and lon, attest to the contemporary popularity of the Homeric epics, which were widely performed by “rhapsodes” and subjected to analysis and interpretation by professional critics. It is worth noting how Plato has his interlocutors speak of Homer (and other poets) in the present tense, as if they were still alive.

6 (1.335b) in the good qualities of horses, not of dogs?: The Greek literally reads “in regard to the excellence (aretê) of dogs, or of horses....” Aretê, from which the adjective aristos (“best”) is derived, is the condition or quality that makes a given thing or individual “good.” When used in general terms of human beings, it commonly refers to moral excellence as well as other qualities or factors (such as intelligence, courage in battle, self-restraint, piety, physical attractiveness, birth, wealth) that would make a man stand out among—and be “better” than—his fellow citizens. Aretê, then, is sometimes translated as “virtue” (see below at 1.348c), but in typical usage its range of meaning is generally broader than that of the English word “virtue.”

7 (1.336a) Periander or Perdiccas or Xerxes or Ismenias the Theban: Periander was tyrant of Corinth (c.625-585 B.C.E.). The Macedonian king named Perdiccas to whom Socrates refers here is probably Perdiccas II (c.450-413 B.C.E.). Xerxes was the king of Persia (d.465 B.C.E.) who led the invasion of Greece in the late 480s B.C.E. Ismenias the Theban is possibly the Ismenias who, in 395 B.C.E., took gold from the Persians in exchange for his help in fomenting war between the Thebans and the Spartans. Since the “dramatic date” of Republic is necessarily earlier than 395, Socrates’ reference to this Ismenias constitutes a (presumably deliberate) anachronism.

8 (1.338c)justice is nothing else than the interest of the stronger: Thrasymachus’ definition relies on a term (that is, to sumpheron—“interest” or “advantage”) that he expressly precluded Socrates from using at 1.336c-d. Nonetheless, that justice is advantageous to the just person is a concept that Socrates, along with Glaucon and Adeimantus, will develop, although along lines wholly different from those in Thrasymachus’ mind.

9 (1.338d) have you never heard that forms of government differthere are tyrannies, and there are democracies, and there are aristocracies?: As he draws attention to the ways in which the ruling authority of a community is responsible for determining what constitutes acceptable (that is, “just”) behavior on the part of its inhabitants, Thrasymachus shifts the focus of the conversation from the “just” behavior of ordinary individuals to the “just” exercise of political power. From this point on, the investigation moves back and forth between the two points of focus. It can be argued that these two kinds of “justice” are fundamentally different. Yet Socrates will eventually define justice as a condition of the soul that is responsible for all kinds of “just” behavior, whether in private dealings or in the exercise of political power (4.442d-443e), and the conflation that begins here anticipates his formulation.

10 (1.341d) every art has an interest?: The way in which Socrates, here and elsewhere, conflates the practitioner of a given skill or craft (for example, a doctor) with the technê itself (for example, medicine) is noteworthy.

11 (1.343b) and you further imagine that the rulers of States, if they are true rulers, never think of their subjects as sheep, and that they are not studying their own advantage day and night: Thrasymachus’ contemptuous dismissal of Socrates’ view of leadership looks ahead to the metaphor developed in books 2-5 that likens the guardians of the ideal city-state, as leaders and protectors, to shepherds and their dogs—see, for example, 5.451c.

12 (1.343d) the unjust man has always more and the just less: The phrase pleon echein—in Greek, literally “to have more”—recurs throughout the first two books of Republic to describe (1) the self-aggrandizing behavior of the unjust man, who feels no scruple about competing with others (and harming them, if need be) in order to get all that he wants, and (2) the advantages that such aggressively self-seeking behavior is thought to bring. Compare 1.349b: “Does the just man try to gain any advantage [pleon echein] over the just?,” 2.359c: “then we shall discover... the just and unjust man to be proceeding along the same road, following their interest [dia pleonexian],” and 2.362b: “and at every contest, whether in public or private, [the unjust man] gets the better [pleonektein] of his antagonists.” Thrasymachus’ glamorization of the pursuit of personal advantage and power (pleonexia) has much in common with Callicles’ argument concerning the “law of nature” in Gorgias 482c-486d as well as with the argument of Antiphon’s “On Truth.” Although Thrasymachus’ praise of injustice is surely meant to seem at first blush outrageous and “sophistic” in character, Plato’s interlocutors invite us to believe that his ideas, for all the arresting frankness of their expression, are really in accordance with mainstream values. See Glaucon at 2.358c: “I hear the voices of Thrasymachus and myriads of others dinning in my ears,” Adeimantus at 2.367: “I dare say that Thrasymachus and others . . . ,” and, more generally, Socrates at 6.493a: “all those mercenary individuals, whom the many call Sophists... do, in fact, teach nothing but the opinion of the many.” Compare Gorgias 492d.

13 (1.344a) the happiest of men: Compare “happy and blessed” at the end of 1.344b just below. “Happy” and “blessed” are both translations for the adjective eudaimon; “happiness” and “blessedness” are interchangeably used to translate the noun eudaimonia, which literally refers to the state of having a favorable guardian spirit (daimon) presiding over one’s life. The “happiness” that is Republic’s focus is thus not mere temporary joy or delight; it is, rather, long-term (that is, lifelong) fulfillment and contentment.

14 (1.344e) Is the attempt to determine the way of man’s life so small a matter in your eyesto determine how life may be passed by each one of us to the greatest advantage?: This is the first of several passages in Republic in which Socrates or another speaker accentuates the profound significance of the issues under discussion. Compare, for example, 1.347e, 2.367c-d, 5.450b, and 10.608b.

15 (1.345a) even if uncontrolled and allowed to have free play: The Greek literally reads “even if one lets it [that is, injustice] go and does not prevent it from doing what it wants.” This sentence marks the beginning of Socrates’ effort, which he sustains throughout Republic, to disassociate “happiness” and personal “profit” from the satisfaction of appetites and desires—that is, “doing what one wants.”

16 (1.347a) no one is willing to govern ... without remuneration: This important idea is developed in book 7, especially at 7.519c-521b and 7.540b.

17 (1.348c-d) And would you call justice vice? No, I would rather say sublime simplicity. Then would you call injustice malignity?: For the broad range of meaning of aretê (translated in the text surrounding this passage as “virtue”), see note 6 on 1.335b. The word translated here as “vice,” kakia, has a similarly broad range of meaning and refers to the condition or quality that makes a given thing or individual “base” (kakos), including (for human beings) ugliness, poverty, and lowliness in social station, as well as moral defect. When Thrasymachus identifies injustice with aretê in the exchange that immediately follows, he asserts in essence that the self-aggrandizement he has associated with injustice makes one stand out and be “better.” The assertion is bold, since justice is typically conceived of as one of the chief “virtues” (aretai), but hardly nonsensical, given Thrasymachus’ view of the material advantages of injustice.

18 (1.352a) And is not injustice equallyfatal when existing in a single person... making him an enemy to himself and the just?: This statement and the discussion leading up to it look ahead to the analysis in books 4, 8, and 9 of injustice and its effects on the individual’s soul.

19 (1.352d) Would you not say that a horse has some end?: The word ergon in Greek, rendered here as “end,” is perhaps better translated as “function.” This question and the analysis it introduces reinforce a concept already introduced at 1.346a-b, that every thing (or person) has a single function (ergon). Both passages anticipate the crucial organizational principle of the ideal city-state-that is, the mandate that every citizen should have one and only one occupation (2.370a-b)—which becomes the foundation for the conceptions of justice in the individual as well as the community that are advanced in books 4, 8, and 9.

20 (1.353b) And has not the eye an excellence?: Once again, “excellence” is aretê in Greek; see note 6 on 1.335b.

21 (1.353d) and has not the soul an end which nothing else can fulfil?: The notions that the human soul (psyche in Greek) has a function—that is, to live—and that it fulfills that function well, producing a “good” and “happy” life by virtue of its excellence (aretê), are fundamental to Republic. Although we are not meant to be satisfied with the case Socrates makes in this passage for justice as the “excellence” that enables the soul to fulfill its function (see 1.354a-c, below), the formulations he develops in this passage preview the argument he will make at length, especially in books 4, 8, and 9.

22 (1.354b) Nevertheless, I have not been well entertained; but that was my own fault and not yours: Socrates’ observation about the unsatisfactory nature of the discussion so far (his ironic comment at 2.368b notwithstanding) directs attention to the problem of definition. The advantages of and happiness brought by justice (or injustice) cannot be properly assessed before justice and injustice are defined. Compare the end of Protagoras (361c).

Book 2

1 (2.357a-b) do you wish really to persuade us, or only to seem to have persuaded us, that to be just is always better than to be unjust?: The differences between seeming and being, appearance and reality, are central to Republic (especially books 6 and 7), and Plato does not miss an opportunity to draw attention to them. Compare Glaucon’s question here with 1.334c-335b and 1.339d-341a.

2 (2.358e) They say that to do injustice is, by nature, good; to suffer injustice, evil; but that the evil is greater than the good: Glaucon’s summary of the (purportedly) common understanding of justice and injustice, especially the sentiment that suffering injustice is far worse than doing injustice, parallels in several aspects the views that Plato attributes to Polus and Callicles in Gorgias. Although Glaucon and later Adeimantus raise many important points concerning the ambiguities of popular moral values, their representations of “what most people think”—and of the moral messages of poetic works—are tendentious, and they provide the basis for Socrates’ claim in book 6 that it is “the many” who are in fact responsible for the corruption of young people. See 6.492d-494a and 1.344c.

3 (2.360c) a man is just, not willingly or because he thinks that justice is any good to him individually, but of necessity, for wherever anyone thinks that he can safely be unjust, there he is unjust: Glaucon here inverts the maxim commonly attributed to Socrates that “no one does wrong willingly.” Compare Socrates at 3.413a and also Adeimantus at 2.366c-d, who adds that even someone who appreciates that justice is best will not be “angry with the unjust... because he also knows that men are not just of their own free will.”

4 (2.362c) and out of his gains he can benefit his friends, and harm his enemies: By identifying the gain over antagonists (that is, pleonexia) as the phenomenon that enables one to “help friends and hurt enemies,” Glaucon makes an explicit connection between Thrasymachus’ boldly expressed defense of injustice (as pleonexia) and the traditional conception of justice as “helping friends and hurting enemies” that Polemarchus articulates at the beginning of book 1. See note 12 on 1.343d.

5 (2.365d) secret brotherhoods and political clubs: Brotherhoods (literally, “conspiracies”) and political clubs flourished in Athens in the late fifth century B.C.E.; their members typically included men from aristocratic families who were disenchanted with the institutions and practices of democracy.

6 (2.365d) professors of rhetoric: Several dialogues by Plato, notably Gorgias, Phaedrus, and Protagoras, are concerned with the teaching of rhetoric by professional (and at times highly paid) instructors. Plato sometimes distinguishes such “professors of rhetoric” from “sophists”; sometimes he does not (for example, in Protagoras).

7 (2.366c) men are not just of their own free will: See note 3 on 2.360c.

8 (2.367a) but everyone would have been his own watchman: The word for “watchman” in Greek is phylax, also translated as “guardian.” Adeimantus’ use of the word here anticipates the attention that will be given in books 2-7 to the “guardians” in the ideal state. Compare the equally pointed use of phylax at 8.549b and 3.413e.

9 (2.367e) I had always admired the natural ability of Glaucon and Adeimantus: The Greek word physis, when used in reference to human beings, describes their natural and innate abilities, dispositions, and talents. Throughout the rest of Republic, Socrates will repeatedly emphasize the importance of physis, which, he asserts, varies considerably from individual to individual. (See, for example, 2.370b, where he and Adeimantus agree that “we are not all alike; there are diversities of natures among us which are adapted to different occupations.”) This view of physis, which has its roots in traditional aristocratic ideology and its assumptions about the innate superiority of the “well-born,” has enormous implications for the political philosophy advanced in Republic.

10 (2.369a) I propose... that we inquire into the nature of justice and injustice, first as they appear in the State, and secondly in the individual, proceeding from the greater to the lesser and comparing them: The assumptions that the same conditions give rise to “justice” in the community and in the individual and that, as a consequence, the “justice” of an individual is completely comparable to that of a city-state, are crucial to Socrates’ argument, and they are never challenged by his interlocutors. Compare 4.442d for another reassertion that “justice” in community is identical to that in the individual, and also 4.435d-e and 8.544d for the assumption that the traits of a given community or people are determined by the characters of its individual members.

11 (2.369b) Can any other origin of a State be imagined?: Theories about the origins of human society abounded in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E.; compare, for example, Protagoras 320c-323a.

12 (2.370b) we are not all alike; there are diversities of natures among us which are adapted to different occupations: This is a crucial assumption and formulation in Republic; see note 9 on 2.367e.

13 (2.370c) when one man does one thing which is natural to him and does it at the right time, and leaves other things: This is another crucial formulation, which is anticipated by the argument at 1.353b—d concerning the unique functions of eyes, ears, etc.

14 (2.371c) In well-ordered States [salesmen] are commonly those who are the weakest in bodily strength, and therefore of little use for any other purpose: Plato has Socrates reflect typical Athenian prejudices about the inferior character and abilities of merchants and laborers. Compare 6.495d-e and 9.590c.

15 (2.372a) Probably in the dealings of these citizens with one another: Adeimantus’ inference about where to “locate” justice in the ideal community is borne out in the discussion at 4.432d-434a.

16 (2.372e) But if you wish also to see a State at fever-heat, I have no objection: Despite Socrates’ reservations concerning the “fevered” and “unhealthy” condition of a city that provides for more than its citizens’ most basic needs, the refinements Glaucon asks for are in fact crucial to Socrates’ conceptual izations of the ideal city-state and thus of justice itself, since they enable him to posit the need in the “fevered” city for a force of specialized warriors—that is, the guardians (2.374d), whose education and way of life become a principal focus of Republic.

17 (2.374c) But is war an art so easily acquired that a man may be a warrior who is also a husbandman [that is, a farmer], or shoemaker, or other artisan [?]: Greek city-states, including Athens, did not have professional standing armies during the archaic and classical periods. Rather, citizens were called up for service at times of need, and even the elite warriors of Sparta had interests aside from their military duties, insofar as they were landown ers and therefore “farmers.” Although the Peloponnesian War brought about a marked increase in the number of mercenary soldiers and began a trend toward military professionalism, relatively few men in Plato’s day were full-time professional soldiers. The army of “guardians” that Socrates envisions would have been unprecedented.

18 (2.375c) how shall we find a gentle nature which has also a great spirit, for the one is the contradiction of the other?: This is one of several places in which Socrates acknowledges that the combination of natural qualities required for guardians (and later for the “true” philosophers who are to govern the ideal state) is rare and difficult to nurture properly. See note 9 on 2.367e, and compare also 6.485a—486e and 6.503b—c. There is surely some humor in Socrates’ ensuing comparison of the ideal state’s guardians to dogs and in his assertions concerning the dog’s “philosophical nature” (2.375a-376c). Nonetheless, the comparison pointedly looks back at the discussion in book 1, during which leadership in human communities is likened to the supervision of flocks by shepherds and their dogs (see note 11 on 1.343b). Moreover, the dog’s “philosophical” gift for distinguishing “familiars” from “strangers” harks back to the problem of recognition faced by those who define justice as “helping friends and hurting enemies” (1.334c—335b).

19 (2.376c) Then we have found the desired natures; and now that we have found them, how are they to be reared and educated?: Socrates asserts throughout Republic that the best “natures,” rare as they are, will amount to nothing (or, worse yet, become corrupted) unless they are carefully nurtured and trained from early childhood. Compare this long section on the early education and training of the ideal city-state’s future warriors, which continues through most of book 3 (to 3.412b), with the equally long section describing the education of future philosopher-rulers (6.502c-7.540c). Compare also passages at 4.423e and 4.429e—430b, 6.494a-495b, 8.546d, and 8.549b, where Socrates emphasizes the importance of education (paideia), nurture (trophê), and “music” (mousikê—see the next note).

20 (2.376e) [education] has two divisions: gymnastics for the body, and music for the soul: The word translated as “music” is mousikê in Greek, derived from Mousai, the generic name of the patron goddesses of music, poetry, dance, etc. Mousikê has a far broader range of meaning than its English derivative “music.” It refers to education in poetry, drama, and literature, and thus to general cultural cultivation; hence Socrates’ description of mousikê as “education for the soul.” Yet, since most of Greek poetry (including drama) was sung and performed with the accompaniment of instruments such as pipes (auloi) and various types of lyres, it was inherently musical in our modem sense of the word. See 3.401d—402a and 8.549b for the importance of mousikê.

21 (2.377c) You may find a model of the lesser in the greater ... : This statement launches a critique of the content and form of poetic (that is, “mimetic”) texts that extends well into book 3. Socrates’ comparison of Homer’s and Hesiod’s works to children’s stories, though somewhat dismissive, reflects the important fact that memorization of passages from Iliad, Odyssey, Theogony, Works and Days, and other well-known texts, was a basic component in the education of young boys throughout the classical period and beyond. Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’ detailed descriptions of the popular view of justice, with its many quotations from “the poets,” are plainly designed to leave the impression that these texts exert considerable (and dangerous) moral influence on adults as well as children, as they convey problematic views of justice and its rewards. See, for example, 2.365e: “If the poets speak truly, why, then, we had better be unjust ...”; see also note 1 on 1.331d.

Socrates’ critique begins with the content of poetic works: their representations of the gods (2.379e—383c) and their presentations of heroic figures such as Achilles in Iliad (3.386a—391e). Discussion of depictions of mortal men (3.392a-c) is deemed premature, since Socrates and his companions have yet to determine what land of behavior—that is, “just” or “unjust”—merits imitation. The style and manner of representation are next considered, with special attention to the psychological dangers of direct imitation (mimesis), as opposed to simple narrative in which performers never assume characters’ identities (3.392d-398c). Further formal considerations involve the modes (harmonies) used in musical accompaniment as well as the choice of instruments (3.398d-399e) and rhythms (3.399e-400e). Socrates’ basic complaints against poetic texts such as Iliad are that (1) they set forth inappropriate conceptions of the essence and activities of the gods, and (2) they provide unwholesome models of conduct to young, uncritical, and easily influenced minds. As emerges at 3.410b-412b, the overall goal of the “musical” and gymnastic curricula proposed for young guardians is to cultivate, in an appropriate balance, the qualities of courage (ferocity) and temperance (gentleness); see note 18 on 2.375c.

Socrates’ criticisms of the harmful moral messages conveyed by poetic texts may justifiably strike some readers as simplistic, insofar as they overlook the complexity and sophistication of the perspectives offered in works such as Iliad and Odyssey on the workings of society and the social responsibilities of individuals. Yet texts such as Frogs, a comedy by Aristophanes that was first performed in 405 B.C.E., suggest that the concerns raised in this section of Republic about the form and content of poetic texts were influenced by a broader cultural debate. Although he takes his censorship (especially of the content of poems) to an extreme, Plato’s Socrates is by no means alone in voicing anxieties about the psychological and ethical effects of poetry and music. Indeed, musical innovations first in narrative poetry (that is, dithyrambs) and then in the lyric portions of tragedy caused a stir in the late fifth century, and they seem to have been what fomented a concern about poetic propriety that preoccupied certain segments of Athenian society into the fourth century. It is worth noting how adamantly Socrates insists in Republic that innovations in music and poetry cannot be tolerated; such proscriptions are reminiscent of the views attributed to the archly conservative “Aeschylus” in Frogs.

22 (2.378b) the young man should not be told that in committing the worst of crimes he is far from doing anything outrageous: In Clouds (produced 423 B.C.E.), Aristophanes has a young man, who has been educated in Socrates’ “Think-Factory” (phrontisterion), justify his abuse of his own father with a reference to Zeus’ mistreatment of Cronus. Clouds represents Socrates as an unscrupulous sophist, and in Apology, Plato has Socrates blame the comedy for fomenting harmful misconceptions about him. This passage of Republic, in which Socrates vehemently condemns the myths about Uranus, Cronus, and Zeus and the “lessons” they convey, is perhaps meant to counter further Aristophanes’ unflattering representation of Socrates.

23 (2.378d) these tales must not be admitted into our State, whether they are supposed to have an allegorical meaning or not. For a young person cannot judge what is allegorical and what is literal: Several individuals during the fifth and fourth centuries proposed allegorical readings of passages in Iliad and Odyssey that, for example, identified the gods with various elements (fire, air, water, earth) and interpreted stories such as the one about Hephaestus’ efforts to protect Hera in the light of theories about the interactions of elements. At 10.605c-608a, Socrates expresses deep reservations about the discriminatory abilities of (most) adults as well as children.

24 (2.379a) God is always to be represented as he truly is: Although Socrates does refer here to “god” (theos in Greek) in the singular, Jowett’s use of the capital G is misleading. The god of whom Socrates speaks here and elsewhere should not be identified with the God of today’s monotheistic religions, even though many of the qualities he attributes to god (perfection, immutability, beneficence, truthfulness) are in accordance with the conceptions of monotheistic systems of belief. Overall, Socrates’ conceptions of divinity (as Plato represents them) seem very flexible, at least in terms of number. At times he is content to speak of the traditional pantheon of gods (Zeus, Hera, Apollo, et al.), and at times he speaks of “god” in the singular. This is not unprecedented, however, and Greeks regularly spoke of god in the singular if they did not have a particular deity in mind, or if they wanted to refer to divine power in some general way. Socrates, it is true, was charged in 399 B.C.E. with “impiety” because of his failure to recognize the gods recognized by the Athenian polis, but the verb “to recognize” (nomizein) in this context can refer to ritual practice as well as “belief.” It is not clear that a flirtation with monotheism, of the sort that Plato represents here, would have supplied Socrates’ opponents with sufficient grounds for leveling the charge of impiety.

25 (2.380a) neither will we allow our young men to hear the words of Aeschylus: It is difficult to imagine that Plato (or Socrates) seriously believed that excision of objectionable material from Iliad, Odyssey, and other major poetic works was a practical undertaking. Rather, Socrates’ method of citing passage after passage that “we will not allow our young men to hear” seems intended to point out the pervasive problems in the contents and “messages” of even the most revered works.

26 (2.380a) the house of Pelops: Pelops was the son of Tantalus and the father of Atreus and Thyestes, and thus the grandfather (via Atreus) of Agamemnon and Menelaus. The troubles of the many generations in Pelops’ family were popular subjects of tragic drama (for example, the extant Oresteia trilogy by Aeschylus). The southern region of Greece in which Sparta and Epi daurus are situated is called the Peloponnese (literally, Pelops’ island) after Pelops.

27 (2.382c) Whereas the lie in words is in certain cases useful and not hateful: These reflections on the usefulness of lies in certain limited circumstances anticipates the provision made at 3.414b-415d for “needful falsehoods” in the ideal city-state. Compare 3.387c and 3.389b, and also 1.331c.

Book 3

1 (3.389d) he will punish him for introducing a practice which is equally subversive and destructive of ship or State: The metaphorical comparison of the polis to a ship at sea is common in classical literature. “Justice” has already been compared to the piloting of ships at 1.332e, and the affinities of political communities to ships will be underscored again, in a powerful and suggestive image, at 6.488a-489a.

2 (3.391a) Loving Homer as I do, I hardly like to say: The Greek literally reads, “I hesitate, indeed, on account of Homer, to say....”: Here and again at 10.595b and 10.607a-608a (compare 2.383a), Plato has Socrates acknowledge the powerful charm and appeal of the poems attributed to Homer and of poetry in general. This does not mean, however, that these works are beneficial to their listeners, or useful to communities; their great charm, according to Socrates, is what renders them dangerous insofar as it makes them so appealing. The seductive power of pleasant things, which makes most people incapable of distinguishing what is truly good from what is immediately pleasurable and gratifying, is a recurrent concern in Republic and several other Platonic dialogues, notably Philebus.

3 (3.392c) we cannot determine until we have discovered what justice is, and how naturally advantageous to the possessor, whether he seem to be just or not: Socrates provides some indirect indications at 10.603e-605c as to how mortal men and women are to be represented.

4 (3.392d) And narration may be either simple narration or imitation, or a union of the two?: Socrates’ division of poetry into three formal categories—(1) simple narration, in which performers never assume the identities of characters, (2) simple imitation, in which performers always assume the identities of characters, as in dramatic performances, and (3) a mixed, or “double,” form—collapses the established distinctions between genres, such as epic poetry (a “mixed” form) and tragic drama (pure imitation), thus paving the way for his characterizations of Homer as “first of the tragedians” ( 10.595b and 10.607a). It also provides him with additional means for criticizing poetic works such as Iliad on the grounds that their imitative element violates the ideal state’s foundational “one person, one job” rule (3.394d—396b; compare 2.370b).

5 (3.397d) but the mixed style is also very charming: and indeed the pantomimic ... is the most popular style with children and their attendants, and with the world in general: See note 2 on 3.391a.

6 (3.398e) The harmonies which you mean are the mixed or tenor Lydian, and the full-toned or bass Lydian, and such like: Harmoniai, translated by the terms “modes” and also “harmonies,” differ in their arrangements of intervals between notes and also in pitch. Socrates’ judgments about the ethos and ethical effects of different harmoniai, especially his high regard for the popular Dorian mode, largely accords with assessments in other sources, except for the fact that he chooses to ignore the Phrygian mode’s secondary association with orgiastic frenzy (compare Aristotle, Politics 8.1342a32-b12).

7 (3.399c-d) we shall not want multiplicity of notes or a panharmonic scale? ... Then we shall not maintain the artificers of lyres with three comers and complex scales, or the makers of any other many-stringed, curiously harmonized instruments?: Musical innovators in late-fifth-century Athens transformed traditional modes by changing the tunings on and adding extra strings to instruments such as lyres. Another contemporary innovation was the more frequent use of instruments such as the triangular harp (trigonos), which Jowett misleadingly translates by the phrase “lyre with three corners.” The high-pitched trigonos had many strings, and, like the pipe (aulos), it was associated with intense emotion, sensuality, and licentiousness.

Music was generally thought in antiquity to have strong ethical effects. Conservative segments of Athenian society accordingly took a dim view of the sorts of innovations described above (as well as experiments with rhythm, described below), on the grounds that they had undesirable effects on conduct and were conducive to “loose behavior” as well as general disregard for traditional norms and standards of decorum. On the topic of music’s ethical influence and the dangers of innovation, Socrates in Republic heartily concurs with the traditionalists; “musical training,” he states at 3.401d-402a, “is a more potent instrument than any other, because rhythm and harmony find their way into the inward places of the soul, on which they mightily fasten....” His repeated insistence that, to preserve the ideal state, rulers must guard “above all” against innovations in music and poetry (4.424b-e; compare 8.546d), is hardly surprising.

8 (3.399e) The preferring of Apollo and his instruments to Marsyas and his instruments is not at all strange, I said: Apollo’s instruments are the cithara and other lyres; the instruments of the satyr Marsyas, who lost a musical contest with Apollo and was flayed for his impudence in challenging the god, are pipes (auloi). The music of the aulos was generally linked to ecstasy, frenzy, and sensuality, whereas the music of stringed instruments was considered more restrained and dignified. In endorsing the Phrygian mode (3.399a-c), Socrates ignores its association with auloi; see note 6 above on 3.398e.

9 (3.399e) complex systems of metre, or metres of every kind: The rhythms of Greek poetry were quantitative, based on combinations of long and short syllables (in metra or longer cola) according to fixed patterns that permitted some limited variations. (Long syllables were generally “held” for twice as long as short syllables.) Experiments with rhythmic variation (and hence complexity) comprised another set of innovations in the late fifth century that met with disapproval from conservative critics.

10 (3.400a) there are some three principles of rhythm out of which metrical systems are framed: Theorists classified the basic rhythms (that is, iambic, trochaic, anapestic, dactylic, paeonic, cretic) into three groups, depending on the proportion of long and short syllables in their metra. Iambic and trochaic, which alternate short and long syllables, were grouped together; anapestic and dactylic, which alternate a long syllable with two short syllables, were likewise grouped together. The paeonic, which featured a long syllable followed by three short syllables, was grouped with its variant, “cretic.”

11 (3.400a) four notes out of which all the harmonies are composed: This is perhaps a reference to the systems of four notes (that is, tetrachords) that were the bases of scales and therefore of harmoniai, or modes.

12 (3.400d) our principle is that rhythm and harmony are regulated by the words, and not the words by them: Greek music traditionally featured no vocal flourishes such as coloratura, although in the late fifth century singers experimented with stretching out a single syllable over more than one note. This practice (epektasis) was yet another innovation that met with disapproval from those with conservative tastes.

13 (3.400d-e) The beauty of style and harmony and grace and good rhythm depend on simplicity: Eschewing complexity and variety in favor of simplicity (in the positive sense of the word) is the unifying principle of Socrates’ educational program for future guardians; see Socrates’ assertion at 3.404e that complexity engenders “license” in the soul and “disease” in the body, whereas simplicity guards against both, and also 3.398a-b, 3.399c-e, 3.404b, and 3.410a. For the negative association of “simplicity” with foolishness, see Thrasymachus’ ironic comment on “sublime simplicity” at 1.348c.

14 (3.401c) then will our youth dwell in a land of health: Socrates’ description of the young guardians’ healthy spiritual condition anticipates his definition of justice (in the individual) as the healthy, balanced, and harmonious state of the soul at 4.444c-d.

15 (3.402c) neither we nor our guardians ... can ever become musical until we and they know the essential forms of temperance, courage, liberality, magnificence, and their kindred, as well as the contrary forms, ... and can recognize them and their images wherever they are found.... : Scholars vigorously debate whether readers are meant to assume that Socrates is referring at this point to the metaphysical “ideas” (that is, of good-in-itself, beauty-in-itself, etc.) that are identified in books 6 and 7 as the ultimate objects of philosophical inquiry. Although the term used here (ta eidê) is the one used later in Republic and in other Platonic dialogues to designate the ideas, it is perhaps wise to assume that, since the ideas have not yet come up in Republic’s conversation, Socrates is currently using the term in a less specialized sense, simply to indicate that all who aim to be properly educated should be exposed, via mousikê, to examples of temperance, courage, and other worthy qualities (compare 3.396d-e).

16 (3.402e) But let me ask you another question: Has excess of pleasure any affinity to temperance?: This question, which leads to a brief discussion of how intense homoerotic attachments must be banned in the ideal state, constitutes a striking transition between the discussions of the young guardians’ training in mousikê and gymnastikê. Later in Republic (5.474d) Glaucon graciously accepts being characterized, for the sake of the argument, as a “man of pleasure” (literally, an “erotic man”—that is, someone who falls in love with handsome youths), and the verses quoted by Socrates at 2.368a reveal that, until recently, Glaucon has also been the object of an older man’s attentions. Moreover, in Symposium, Phaedrus, and elsewhere, Plato has Socrates playfully confess his erotic attraction to handsome young men, such as Alcibiades and Agathon. It is always made plain, however, that Socratic eros is wholly spiritual. The point in this passage is that, although love of beauty is ennobling and worth cultivating, it does not legitimize intemperate lust for handsome young men or boys.

17 (3.404b) My meaning may be learned from Homer: Socrates’ reliance upon “Homer” as an authority on diet, exercise, and medicine may come as a bit of a surprise after his extensive critical analysis of various elements in Iliad and Odyssey. It is perhaps best to take with some grains of salt Plato’s references to the expertise of Homer and other poets on various practical matters.

18 (3.405b) pride himself on his litigiousness: Fifth- and fourth-century critics of democracy frequently alleged that the Athenians were overly fond of going to court, both as prosecutors and as jurors. The analogy developed in this passage between medicine, which cures the ailments of the body, and corrective justice, which seeks to “cure” the ills of the soul, is paralleled in some regards in Gorgias.

19 (3.407e) Then, he said, you regard Asclepius as a statesman: The parallels between rulers who care for their subjects and doctors who care for their patients have already been suggested in book 1 (for example, at 1.341c), and they figure prominently in other Platonic dialogues concerned with political leadership and management. Statesman 293c-d advances the notion that the good ruler, like a doctor, will be obliged to make difficult decisions (such as the life-and-death choices that Socrates attributes to Asclepius) and do painful, unpleasant things.

20 (3.408c-d) Ought there not to be good physicians in a State, and are not the best those who have treated the greatest number of constitutions, good and bad, and are not the best judges in like manner those who are acquainted with all sorts of moral natures?: Among Plato’s dialogues, Gorgias is noteworthy for its extensive comparison of corrective justice, which metes out (often painful) punishments in order to ameliorate defects of the soul, and the art of medicine, which implements (often painful) treatments in order to cure disease in the body. In this passage, however, Socrates (perhaps with some irony) adduces an important difference between the expertise of doctors and that of people who sit in judgment of crimes—doctors benefit from the experience of physical illness, but jurors/judges (dikastai in Greek) are not profited by exposure to crime and moral defect.

21 (3.410e) And in our opinion the guardians ought to have both these qualities?: The cultivation of courage (3.386a-389d) and temperance (3.389d-391e) has been a preoccupation of Socrates’ description of the guardians‘early education and thus of his discussion of poetry’s content and its musical accompaniment. For more on the importance of fostering these two qualities in the citizenry, see Plato, Statesman 306a-311c and Laws 1.626d-636c.

22 (3.412b) Very good, I said; then what is the next question?: In the short section that follows this question (through 3.417b), Socrates introduces several important provisions about the organization of the ideal city-state and, more particularly, about the guardians’ way of life. These provisions include: the testing of the guardians so that they may be divided into two groups, rulers (who are “guardians” in the limited sense of the word) and their helpers (“auxiliaries”); the devising of a “royal lie” designed to make citizens accept their division into “classes” of gold (rulers), silver (auxiliaries) and bronze and iron (craftsmen, farmers, et al.); the promotion and demotion of children born into each class according to their natural abilities (physis); and the requirement that the guardians (both rulers and auxiliaries) have no private property and “live together like soldiers in a camp” (3.416e). This last requirement, along with the provision that rulers and auxiliaries “possess” their women and children in common (4.423e), receives fuller treatment in book 5.

23 (3.413c) we must inquire who are the best guardians of their own conviction that what they think the interest of the State is to be the rule of their lives: Described here is the battery of tests and trials (of memory, physical endurance, and mental stability) that young guardians must undergo; those who are to be rulers will need to undergo, beginning at age twenty, yet another series of tests that measure their intellectual sophistication (7.537a-540c).

24 (3.413e) good guardians of themselves and of the music which they have learned: See note 8 on 2.367a.

25 (3.414c) only an old Phoenician tale: Cadmus, the legendary founder of Thebes in Boeotia, came to Greece from Phoenicia (on the eastern edge of the Mediterranean Sea). The tale is that Cadmus killed the dragon that dwelled at the site of his newly founded city and threw its teeth in the ground; from these teeth sprang fully armed men, called Spartoi (that is, “Sown Men”). This is one of several myths that describe how individuals, or an entire people, came to be born from the earth.

26 (3.415a) Some of you have the power of command, and in the composition of these he has mingled gold ... : As Socrates indicates at 8.546e, the conception of people characterized by gold, silver, bronze, and iron is borrowed from Hesiod, Works and Days 109-201, which describes how the earth was successively peopled by a golden “race” (genos), a silver race, a bronze race, a race of “heroes,” and the current race of “iron.”

27 (3.415d) Not in the present generation: At 7.540e-541b Socrates acknowledges that it would be generally impossible to persuade adults to accept the beliefs and ideals necessary for the institution of the ideal state; compare 6.501a.

28 (3.416e-417a) for that commoner metal has been the source of many unholy deeds, but their own is undefiled: Socrates’ assertion concerning the (inevitably) corrupting influence of wealth counters the original assumption of Cephalus, who claimed at 1.331a-b that his wealth is what has enabled him to be “just” throughout his life. Property-holding in the guardian classes violates the ideal state’s foundational one-person-one-job rule, insofar as it would consequently lead rulers and auxiliaries to become “good housekeepers and husbandmen instead of guardians ...” (3.417a). Compare Socrates’ more general indication at 4.421d-422a that excessive wealth among the bronze/ iron class (who are allowed to possess private property) would be “the parent of luxury and indolence.”

Book 4

1 (4.423a-b) Hellenes or barbarians: Greeks (that is, Hellenes) saw themselves as ethnically and culturally distinct from other people, such as the local peoples of Asia Minor (for example, Lydians and Phrygians), as well as Egyptians, Persians, and Scythians. See also 4.435e-4.436a and 5.470c.

2 (4.424a) the general principle that friends have all things in common: Socrates casually mentions here another strikingly unusual aspect of the guardians’ way of life: the absence of individual families and the common “possession” of women and children. Although Adeimantus does not question Socrates’ provision about the guardians’ wives and children at this point, it is examined in detail beginning at 5.449c.

3 (4.424c) when modes of music change, the fundamental laws of the State always change with them: The word translated here as “modes” is not harmoniai (see note 6 on 3.398e), but the more general term tropoi (“styles,” “manners”). Damon’s theory concerning the relationship between musical innovation and change in fundamental political laws naturally follows on what Socrates has set forth in book 3 concerning the ethical influence of music (compare Laws 2.673a). The underlying logic is that, if the character of people changes (because of their exposure to new types of music), this ethical transformation will inevitably lead to changes in basic customs and laws (compare Laws 3.700a-701d). Hence Socrates’ insistence that the guardians must, above all, guard against innovation in music and education; compare 8.546e.

4 (4.424d) in the form of amusement; and at first sight it appears harmless: On the importance of children’s games and play to the overall welfare and stability of the state, see also Laws 7.793d-794a and 7.797a-798e, which present more detailed arguments against permitting innovations in children’s games.

5 (4.426b-c) do not these States resemble the persons whom I was describing?: The allusion is to 3.405a-410a. As in the earlier passage, this description of the “ill-ordered state” that forbids constitutional change but continually experiments with legislative tinkering plainly alludes to contemporary Athens. See note 18 on 3.405b.

6 (4.428a) And is not a similar method to be pursued about the virtues, which are also four in number?: Traditional conceptions of the virtues (aretai) admitted some variation. Here, the virtues are wisdom (sophia), courage (andreia ), temperance or moderation (sophrosynê), and justice (dikaiosynê); in Protagoras, Plato has Socrates and Protagoras add piety (hosiotês) to these four. The process of elimination by which Socrates proposes to discover “justice” in the ideal state may, with good reason, strike some readers as simplistic and unconvincing, and it is perhaps wisest to assume that his argument in the following passage is meant to be merely suggestive. See 4.435c-d for the first of several passages in which Socrates and his interlocutors acknowledge the provisional and inadequate nature of their discussion.

7 (4.432d) Why, my good sir, at the beginning of our inquiry, ages ago, there was Justice tumbling out at our feet, and we never saw her; nothing could be more ridiculous: See 2.372a and also 2.370b. The definition of justice that emerges in this passage—that is, of doing one’s own business—looks back to the formulation of justice introduced by Polemarchus at 1.332b as “giving what is due or proper,” insofar as the role of leadership is “due” and “proper” to the guardians in the ideal state, as it also is to the “rational principle” in the individual human being (4.441e).

8 (4.433a) Justice was doing one’s own business, and not being a busybody: The verb “to be a busybody” (polypragmonein) and the related noun (polypragmosynê, “meddlesomeness”) and adjective (polypragmon) were ideo logically charged terms in fifth- and fourth-century Athens. They were typically used by critics of Athenian democracy to disparage its empower ment of average citizens who, as members of the Assembly and as jurors in courts, could “meddle” in affairs of state as well as in the lives of important men. The same terms were also used to critique the “meddling” of Athens in the affairs of the city-states that were its nominal allies in the Delian League. The association of injustice in the state with polypragmosynê, which is described at 4.434a-c as the “meddling” of the bronze/iron class in the business of rulers and auxiliaries, is an obvious criticism of the current institutions and practices of Athenian democracy. The earlier comparison at 3.389c of average individuals to the patients of a doctor or the crew on a ship anticipates this passage’s emphasis on the dysfunction that occurs when such people attempt to give orders instead of taking them.

It is worth noting how Socrates and his interlocutors, here in book 4 and in the more detailed analysis of the four “degenerate” political constitutions in books 8 and 9, assume that the division of the ideal city-state’s citizens into three groups (rulers, auxiliaries, all others) reflects the actual and natural categorization of people in all types of political communities. This assumption follows upon their agreement that in the ideal state people are grouped according to their natural abilities, and it furnishes them the grounds for assessing the defects of any political arrangement that fails to observe the ideal state’s distinctions and prohibitions against “meddling.”

9 (4.435b-c) we may assume that he has the same three principles in his own soul which are found in the State; and he may be rightly described in the same terms, because he is affected in the same manner?: This assumption, which Socrates strives to justify in the following pages, is a corollary of the major assumption that “justice” in the state is qualitatively identical to “justice” in the individual (2.368c-e; compare below at 4.442d). The understanding of human psychology that Socrates advances in this passage capitalizes on commonplace conceptions (for example, the opposition between “reason” and “appetites”) but is nonetheless distinctive. In particular, his conception of the third and intermediate part of the soul (“spirit” or “passion” [thumos ]), which he posits as reason’s “ally” (4.440a-441c), requires special explanation. In Phaedrus, Plato has Socrates develop a similar (though not identical) image of the soul, which is likened to a chariot with a team of two horses. The charioteer (that is, “reason”) drives; of the two horses, the one on the right side is fair and disciplined, corresponding to the “spirited” part (thumos) of the soul in Republic, whereas his dark and unruly counterpart on the left corresponds to Republic’s appetitive part.

10 (4.435d) I do not think that the method which we are employing is at all adequate to the accurate solution of this question: This is the first of several important passages in Republic in which Socrates, Glaucon, and/or Adeimantus acknowledge the methodological inadequacies of their discussion and call attention to the fact that, in the current circumstances, they are not able to explore their concerns properly. Compare 5.450e-451a and 5.472b-c; 6.484a, 6.504b, 6.506c-d, and 6.509c; 7.517b, 7.532d-e, 7.536b-c; and 10.595c. The cumulative effect of these passages is to highlight the provisional and suggestive nature of the conversation dramatized in Republic.

11 (4.435e) the Thracians, Scythians, and in general the Northern nations: Thrace was located on the northern edge of the Aegean Sea; the Scythians were a nomadic people based, during the classical period, in the area north of the Black Sea. Phoenicia, mentioned below, was located on the eastern edge of the Mediterranean Sea. Socrates’ statement reflects the standard cultural and ethnic prejudices that Greeks of his time entertained, and also the thinking of medical theorists such as Hippocrates, who argued that climate influenced the character of individuals and whole peoples. On Phoenician and Egyptian “character” and the importance of climate, compare Laws 5.747c-e.

12 (4.437d) is not thirst the desire which the soul has of drink, and of drink only; not of drink qualified by anything else.. ?: That is, if one is thirsty for a cold drink, one is actually subject to two separate conditions: thirst (which makes one desire a drink) and heat (which makes one desire coldness). Appetite for good food is accordingly an appetite for food that is modified by some other force or factor.

13 (4.439e) And what of passion, or spirit? Is it a third, or akin to one of the preceding?: The Greek word translated here as “passion” and “spirit” is thumos, which the ensuing discussion identifies as the source of anger and indignation. This understanding basically accords with traditional conceptions of thumos as the wellspring of courage and daring, and also competitiveness (compare Euripides, Medea 1079-1080 and Aristophanes, Acharnians 480). Given the pains Socrates takes in the ensuing exchange to distinguish “spirit” from the appetitive part of the soul, it seems that Plato could not assume that his readers would automatically see thumos as something other than (an) appetite.

14 (4.442a) the concupiscent, which in each of us is the largest part of the soul and by nature most insatiable of gain: So, too, the bronze/iron group is the largest in the state—far larger than the classes of (gold) rulers and (silver) auxiliaries. In statements such as this, we can see the complete interdependence of the psychological theory that Socrates develops in Republic and the political philosophy that arises from his conception of the ideal state.

15 (4.443c-d) But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned, however, not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man: Socrates’ striking conclusion, that the “justice” of an individual is not the product of his or her deeds and dealings with others but is rather the well-ordered “psychological” state that naturally gives rise to “just” actions, departs radically from traditional conceptions of “justice” and has far-reaching implications. Most notably, Socrates’ formulation deemphasizes the political and social interactions that are the focal points of most considerations of “justice,” since these are merely the results of the rule of reason in the soul over spirit and appetites. On the logic advanced in Republic, an individual can be “just” even if he or she has no social contact with other human beings.

16 (4.444b) Must not injustice be a strife which arises among the three principles-a meddlesomeness, and interference ... ?: Stasis (“strife”) typically refers to civil strife and factionalism within a polis. Many Greek city-states, including Athens, had considerable experience with stasis in the classical period; during the Peloponnesian War, factional strife within Athens brought about two oligarchic coups (411-410 and 404-403 B.C.E.). “Meddlesomeness” is Jowett’s translation for the noun polypragmosynê, which is derived from the verb polypragmonein, translated above as “to be a busybody” (4.433a). “Interference” is his translation for allotriopragmosynê, a variation of polypragmosynê. For the political and ideological thrust of these last two terms, see note 8 on 4.433a.

Socrates’ leading question strikes yet another blow at Athenian democracy. By linking polypragmosynê (“meddlesomeness”) to civil strife and factionalism (stasis), Socrates insinuates that there is inherent dysfunction in a political system (such as Athens‘) that encourages its citizens to become politically active. This formulation harks back to Socrates’ identification of injustice as the source of “divisions and hatreds and fighting” at 1.351d.

17 (4.444c) they are like disease and health; being in the soul just what disease and health are in the body: The comparison of justice and injustice in the soul to bodily health and disease previews the arguments that Socrates will develop in books 8 and 9 about the psychological dysfunction brought about by “injustice” as it has just been defined in book 4.

Book 5

1 (5.449b) when Polemarchus, who was sitting just a little way off, just beyond Adeimantus, began to whisper to him: The personal interactions in this passage are noteworthy. Polemarchus, who was at the beginning of the dialogue an uncritical proponent of the commonplace view of justice, seems caught up in the spirit of the discussion among Socrates and the two brothers, and ventures to seek clarification (via Adeimantus) about two key proposals concerning the guardians’ way of life. Even Thrasymachus, who was openly hostile to Socrates in book 1, appears won over (5.450a-b); it is he who now emphasizes the importance of the conversation (compare Socrates at 1.344e) and urges Socrates to cooperate with the group’s request for more details about the “community” of wives and children.

The lengthy digression that Polemarchus’ request initiates postpones further consideration of the dialogue’s main questions—that is, whether justice leads to “happiness” and is “profitable”—until book 8. At first Socrates and his interlocutors are concerned with considering the role to be undertaken by women of the guardian classes and the “community” of wives and children; Glaucon, however, insists that Socrates address the more general questions of whether the ideal city-state could ever be brought into being, and under what conditions it might be founded (5.471c—e; compare 5.466c). This prompts Socrates to make his famous claim that the ideal state will come into being only when “philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy” (5.473d—e). Socrates’ assertion leads in turn to efforts to (1) define “philosophy” and “philosophers” (5.474b-6.487a), (2) explain the unfavorable reputation of philosophers in contemporary Athens (6.487a—497a), (3) identify the ultimate goal of the philosopher’s education (6.502c-7.521b), and (4) elucidate how future philosophers might be prepared to achieve that goal (7.521c-540c).

Though technically parts of a digression, these topics are clearly of central importance to Republic. The philosopher-ruler is the key figure upon whom the ideal (that is, just) state depends for its (hypothetical) existence, and he (or she) is also implicitly the exemplar of justice in the individual, since he (or she) is “orderly and divine, as far as the nature of man allows” (6.500c-d). It should be noted that Plato strives to create strong impressions in his readers’ imaginations throughout this long section, in which he has Socrates convey some of his most vivid and memorable images—including the simile of the sun at 6.507a-509b and the allegory of the cave at 7.514a-518b; see also the metaphor of the ship of state at 6.488a-489a, and the image of philosophy as a bride abandoned by her true grooms and forced to “wed” unworthy suitors at 6.495b-496a.

2 (5.449d) the right or wrong management of [domestic] matters will have a great and paramount influence on the State for good or for evil: The notion that proper “household management” was intimately connected to the effective management of political affairs became widely accepted in Athens during the classical period; in Protagoras 318e-319a, for example, Plato has Protagoras claim to teach his students how they “might best arrange their household business and become most successful with respect to the affairs of the city.” Socrates’ outline in books 2 and 3 of the guardians’ early education argues for a yet more intense connection between “domestic affairs” (that is, the education and training of children) and the successful management of the polis.

3 (5.451a) the danger is not that I shall be laughed at ... but that I shall miss the truth ... and drag my friends after me in my fall: Socrates was formally accused and convicted in 399 B.C.E. on charges of impiety and “corrupting the youth.” It is in the light of the latter charge, perhaps, that Plato has Socrates express caution about speaking his mind and (potentially) misleading his young companions. Glaucon’s reassurance that Socrates “shall not be held to be a deceiver” may be equally pointed.

4 (5.452a) several of our proposals ... being unusual, may appear ridiculous: Socrates repeatedly draws attention to the possibility that his proposals concerning guardian women may strike many as “ridiculous”; compare 5.452c and 5.457a-b, and also 5.473d-e, where he introduces the concept of the philosopher-ruler. Utopian social models that empowered women (and also featured “communism” in wives and children) were satirized by comic playwrights, such as Aristophanes in The Women at the Assembly (Ecclesiazusae), which was produced in 392 B.C.E. Socrates’ comments seem aimed at acknowledging—and discrediting—this kind of comic satire.

5 (5.452c-d) when first the Cretans, and then the Lacedaemonians, introduced the custom: “Lacedaemonian” and “Laconian” refer to the territory around the polis of Sparta and its inhabitants. Greek men in the classical period regularly stripped when they exercised and competed in athletic contests; in his History of the Peloponnesian War 1.6, Thucydides concurs that this practice was an innovation that the Spartans (that is, Lacedaemonians) introduced to Greece at some point in the distant past.

6 (5.454a) glorious is the power of the art of contradiction!: The “art of contradiction” is antilogike technê (literally, the “skill of antilogic”), a technique of argumentation whereby speakers cause their listeners to think of an object (or person or action) as first possessing one quality (or predicate) and then its opposite. “Antilogic” represents one of several techniques that someone seeking success in verbal debates could deploy and is therefore associated with the practice of “eristic.” Socrates opposes eristic argumentation (aiming at persuasion and victory, no matter what the cost) to dialectic (aiming at the truth, no matter what the cost) just below at 5.454a, where he contrasts the “spirit of contention” with that “of fair discussion,” and again at 7.539c. See also Meno 75c and Philebus 17a.

7 (5.454d) a physician and one who is in mind a physician may be said to have the same nature: The Greek text is difficult. Some editors prefer a reading that translates as “a male physician and a female physician may be said to have the same nature”; others prefer the reading “one physician and another may be said....”

8 (5.454d—e) but if the difference consists only in women bearing and men begetting children, this does not amount to a proof that a woman differs from a man in respect of the sort of education she should receive: Socrates’ assertion of the potential equality between men and women (which is perhaps at odds with the remark at 5.455d about “the general inferiority of the female sex”), and his judgment that the current practice of not training women for war is “in reality a violation of nature” (5.456c) are striking. Women in Athens during the classical period had no political franchise and were generally not educated outside the home. Although several dramas dating to the fifth century (for example, Aeschylus’ Oresteia trilogy [458 B.C.E.] and Aristophanes’ Lysistrata [411 B.C.E.]) feature characters who debate the fairness and propriety of this kind of marginalization, there seems to have been little doubt in the minds of Athenian men that their wives, daughters, and sisters were meant to stay in the home. Mythical women warriors, such as Amazons, were universally represented as dangerous aberrations.

Modem scholars differ in their assessments of Plato’s “feminism.” On the one hand, he has Socrates assert that women as well as men are capable of becoming philosopher-rulers (7.540c); on the other, perhaps reflecting the cultural realities of his day, he never represents respectable Athenian women (that is, the relatives of citizen men) participating in philosophical conversations, and female figures in his dialogues (the probably fictional Diotima in Symposium, Pericles’ mistress Aspasia in Menexenus) are few and far between.

9 (5.457c) Yes, that was a mighty wave which you have escaped: Waves were thought to come in groups of three, with the third as the largest (and potentially most dangerous). See below at 5.472a. The three “waves” are the challenges Socrates faces in (1) explaining how female guardians are to be trained and educated (5.451c-457c), (2) justifying the “community” of wives and children among the guardians (5.457c-471c), and (3) explaining how the ideal city-state might come into being. Socrates’ effort to respond to this final challenge occupies the rest of book 5 and all of books 6 and 7.

10 (5.458d) necessity, not geometrical, but another sort of necessity which lovers know, and which is far more convincing and constraining to the mass of mankind: Socrates refers here to the “necessity” of sexual passion, which most people cannot resist, and which differs completely from the logical necessity of mathematical reasoning.

11 (5.458e) the next thing will be to make matrimony sacred in the highest degree: To Athenian ears, the phrase hieros gamos (“sacred marriage”) would have signified, first and foremost, the marriage of Zeus and Hera, which was regularly celebrated at a special festival. The phrase underscores the solemnity of the “marriages” among guardians.

12 (5.459c-d) our rulers will find a considerable dose of falsehood and deceit necessary for the good of their subjects: ... the use of all these things regarded as medicines might be of advantage: See note 27 on 2.382c, and also 3.414b-415d for “needful falsehoods” in the ideal city-state.

13 (5.460c) but the offspring of the inferior, or of the better when they chance to be deformed, will be put away in some mysterious, unknown place, as they should be: Sickly, deformed, or unwanted infants were regularly exposed and left to die outside the city limits in Athens and elsewhere in Greece; the decision to expose an infant typically was made by the father or male head of household. Socrates’ provision for the “putting away” of sickly and deformed children is wholly in keeping with this practice; the only difference is that the decision in the ideal city-state would be made by the polis’ officials, not the father.

14 (5.460e) A woman ... at twenty years of age may begin to bear children to the State, and continue to bear them until forty: In Athens, girls were generally married at puberty and began bearing children immediately; men did not marry until much later in life (that is, at approximately age thirty). Socrates’ provision for the female guardians’ late start in childbearing is noteworthy.

15 (5.462c) And is not that the best-ordered State in which the greatest number of persons apply the terms “mine” and “not mine” in the same way to the same thing?: Like the prohibition against private property (3.416e-417b), the creation of what is in essence a common family among the guardians is aimed at keeping them from developing private interests at odds with those of the community as a whole (5.463c-464b).

16 (5.465d) The Olympic victor ... is deemed happy in receiving a part only of the blessedness which is secured to our citizens, who have won a more glorious victory and have a more complete maintenance at the public cost: Victors in the games at Olympia and other pan-Hellenic sites were rewarded in Athens with public honors and privileges, including meals (paid for out of the polis’ treasury) in the Prytaneum. (Compare Apology 36d.) Socrates’ pronouncement concerning the “victory” of the guardians and the rewards they receive answers the complaint Adeimantus lodges on behalf of the guardians at 4.419a.

17 (5.466d) The inquiry ... has yet to be made, whether such a community will be found possible ... and if possible, in what way possible: See note 9 on 5.457c and note 21 on 5.471c.

18 (5.469b) Do you think it right that Hellenes should enslave Hellenic States, or allow others to enslave them, if they can help?: See note 1 on 4.423a, and also 5.470c. Although Greeks rarely served as slaves in other Greek city-states, Greek armies could sell their Hellenic captives to non-Greek foreigners. What is said in these paragraphs raises the question: Do Socrates and his interlocutors assume that there will be slaves in the ideal city-state, although their role in the community is never discussed? Scholars disagree about the implications of this sentence and the following remarks. Slaves were universally present in all Greek communities, and although the ideal state differs radically in several regards from existing states (see, for example, 6.497a-c), it is perhaps reasonable to infer from this passage that it was not meant to differ as far as the practice of slavery was concerned.

19 (5.469d) And is there not illiberality and avarice in robbing a corpse ... ?: Victorious armies regularly stripped weapons from corpses of the enemy dead; the armor subsequently would be dedicated to the gods and displayed in temples. Destroying crops and livestock and burning buildings (5.470a) were also standard practices in war.

20 (5.470c) we shall say that Hellas is then in a state of disorder and discord: Socrates’ distinction between stasis (“civil strife”) and polemos (“war”) reflects standard usage; his redefinition of the term stasis to cover conflicts between city-states is, however, unusual.

21 (5.471c) Is such an order of things possible, and how, if at all?: See note 9 on 5.457c and note 17 on 5.466d. Socrates’ reference to “the first and second waves” in the following paragraphs looks back to 5.457b-c.

22 (5.472e) And is our theory a worse theory because we are unable to prove the possibility of a city being ordered in the manner described?: Although Socrates eventually argues that the ideal state is in fact possible and is not “a mere dream” (7.540d), his assertion concerning the utility and importance of ideal models, even when they are unrealizable, is noteworthy.

23 (5.473c-d) “Until philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy ... cities will never have rest from their evils ... and then only will this our State have a possibility of life and behold the light of day”: This striking statement, which (as Glaucon imagines just below) most people would strenuously reject, dominates the discussion in books 5-7 and sets the stage for Republic’s analysis of justice’s “profitability” in books 8-10, as well as its reconsideration of poetic mimesis in book 10. The immediate problem it raises is how the “philosopher” (literally, “lover of wisdom”) is to be distinguished from other people who seem to be curious about the world around them and lovers of learning (5.474b-476c).

24 (5.476d) But take the case of the other, who recognizes the existence of absolute beauty and is able to distinguish the idea from the objects which participate in the idea ... is he a dreamer, or is he awake?: Socrates’ effort to separate philosophers, who are keen to perceive absolute beauty (as well as absolute justice, absolute good, and so forth), from mere lovers of sights (philotheamones), who perceive beautiful things but “have no sense of absolute beauty” (5.476c), introduces concepts, terminology, and analogies that are central to the theory of knowledge developed in Republic as well as its metaphysics (that is, the theory of the “ideas”).

The notion that there is, for example, a single “idea” (idea, or eidos) of beauty, which is perfect, unalterable, and eternal and is also the source of the beauty in all “beautiful” phenomenal objects (including people, ideas, institutions, etc.) is familiar from other Platonic dialogues, notably Symposium, Phaedo, and Phaedrus. Phenomenal objects that are “beautiful” are said to “participate” temporarily and partially in the idea of beauty (also termed “absolute beauty,” “beauty-in-itself”); the temporary and partial nature of their participation accounts for the facts (1) that phenomenal objects do not seem equally beautiful to all observers (5.479a-e), and (2) that the beauty—of a rose, for instance—is impermanent. Phenomenal objects capable of being apprehended by the senses are themselves impermanent; in the language of Republic, they belong to the class of objects that are “becoming” (that is, between absolute “being” and absolute “nonbeing”). The only objects in the realm of absolute being (and thus the only objects that are truly “real”) are the ideas and mathematical objects, such as the circle, triangle, etc., that are wholly independent of anything that is physically and phenomenally manifest.

This theory of “ideas” is in part indebted to the formulations concerning “being” or “that which is” (to on) of Parmenides of Elea (late sixth-early fifth century B.C.E.), who similarly asserts that “being” can be apprehended only through reason (logos) and not via the senses, which are misleading. Complementing his conception of the metaphysical “ideas” and their relationship to phenomenal objects, Socrates begins to elaborate in this passage a theory of knowledge, to be refined at 6.509d-511e, that is in fact a theory about the different faculties of cognition (dynameis) that people exercise as they contemplate different types of objects (5.476d-480a). The ideas, which are not apprehensible by means of the senses, are perceived through the exercise of what Socrates in this passage alternatively calls gnosis or epistemê (translated as “knowledge” by Jowett); in contrast, everything in the realm of “becoming” is apprehensible by the separate faculty of doxa (“opinion”), which is intermediate between true knowledge and pure ignorance. Only the ideas, then, can be “known” in the absolute sense; about any phenomenal object, one can only “opine” (5.477a-b; compare 5.479e).

People who have “a sense of beautiful things” but “no sense of absolute beauty” are likened to dreamers who mistake their dreams for waking reality (5.476c); they will later be compared to the blind (6.484c-d; compare 6.506c) and, in the allegory of the cave, to prisoners in a cavern who erroneously believe that a parade of shadow-images is real (7.514a-518b). Only those few who are able and willing to contemplate “the very truth of each thing” (literally, “each thing that is”; 6.484d) are “awake” and truly sighted and “free”; these people are the genuine “philosophers” who ought to be entrusted with political governance (see 6.504d-506e). Through these potent images, Plato has Socrates stake out a rather limited definition of what, properly speaking, constitutes “philosophy,” as well as a bold claim for philosophy’s supreme relevance to the proper conduct of human affairs (for example, at 6.500c-501b and 6.506b). One particularly important assertion is that the philosopher’s awareness of the relative meanness and insignificance of all things in the phenomenal realm will ineluctably lead him or her to despise wealth, honor, and other “material” goods (for example, 7.540d-e).

25 (5.476d) But suppose that the latter should quarrel with us and dispute our statement: Some scholars suggest that this is an allusion to Antisthenes (450-c.360 B.C.E.), a member of Socrates’ circle, who became a rival of Plato in the fourth century and, it seems, was skeptical of the theory of ideas that Plato has Socrates advance in this passage. On the other hand, “the latter” (literally, “this man”) could refer generically to any hypothetical “lover” of sounds and sights “who opines only.”

26 (5.476e) Something that is or is not?: The verb “to be” (einai in Greek) has a broad semantic range; it can refer to existence, essence or quality, or truthfulness. Socrates’ question is therefore open to interpretation.

27 (5.477a) for how can that which is not ever be known?: Parmenides similarly asserts that “that which is not” cannot be “spoken or thought.” In his “On Nature” (or “On What Is Not”), a treatise apparently aimed at challenging Parmenides’ conception of “being,” Gorgias argued (1) that nothing “is,” (2) that, even if something “is,” it cannot be comprehended, and (3) that, even if something could be comprehended by an individual, this comprehension could not be communicated to another. Socrates’ insistence in this passage that there is something “that is” which is absolutely knowable seems aimed at valorizing Parmenides’ conception of knowledge in the face of challenges such as Gorgias‘.

28 (5.478d) Then you would infer that opinion [doxa] is intermediate?: Compare 6.506c, where Socrates claims “all mere opinions are bad, and the best of them blind.”

29 (5.479c) or the children’s puzzle about the eunuch aiming at the bat: According to an ancient commentator, the riddle is: “How did a man who isn’t a man aim at (ballei) but not hit (ou ballei) a bird that isn’t a bird, which he saw (that is, thought he saw) but didn’t see (that is, didn’t actually see) sitting on a tree that wasn’t a tree, with a stone that wasn’t a stone?” The eunuch is the man who isn’t a man, and the bat is the bird that isn’t a bird; the verb ballein means both “to aim at” and “to strike”; the word for “tree” (xulon) can also mean “reed” or “rafter,” and a pumice stone both is and isn’t a “stone.”

Book 6

1 (6.484a) if there were not many other questions awaiting us: Socrates’ reminder is yet another acknowledgment of the incomplete nature of Republic ’s discussion of justice and its advantages; see note 9 on 4.435c.

2 (6.484c-d) are not such persons, I ask, simply blind?: Analogies comparing knowledge and wisdom to sight, and ignorance to blindness, are common in Greek poetry; for example, they figure prominently—and paradoxically—in Sophocles’ Oedipus the King (produced c.430 B.C.E.). In Republic, Socrates uses the faculty of sight and the experience of seeing visible objects with the eyes as a metaphor for the faculty of “knowledge” (epistemê) and the experience of apprehending intelligible objects (that is, the ideas) with the mind (6.507b-509c); see also the allegory of the cave, 7.514a-518b). But he also contrasts intellectual apprehension of the ideas with the apprehension of visible and other phenomenal objects with the eyes and other senses, most notably in his description of the divided line (6.509d-511e).

3 (6.485a) In the first place ... the nature of the philosopher has to be ascertained: See note 18 on 2.375c.

4 (6.486a) There should be no secret corner of illiberality: Aneleutheria (“illiberality”) refers first and foremost to stinginess with property and resources; megaloprepeia (“high-mindedness,” “magnanimity”) denotes generosity with material goods. Socrates uses the terms more broadly to contrast general narrow-mindedness with breadth of spirit and “vision.”

5 (6.487b) They fancy that they are led astray a little at each step in the argument ... all their former notions appear to be turned upside down: Adeimantus’ frank remarks about Socrates’ method echo, in a friendly way, the complaints of interlocutors in other dialogues, such as Callicles in Gorgias 497a. By having Socrates take pains to satisfy Adeimantus’ questions about the differences between the common estimations of philosophers (as being either useless or corrupt) and the claims that have just been made about their fitness for political rule, Plato further discredits the allegations that Socrates carelessly and unscrupulously “corrupted the youth” (see also note 12 on 6.494c and note 3 on 5.451a.)

6 (6.488a-b) Imagine then a fleet or a ship in which there is a captain who is taller and stronger than any of the crew, but he is a little deaf and has a similar infirmity in sight, and his knowledge of navigation is not much better: The image of the ship of state provides an unflattering image of contemporary Athenian politics. The captain/ship-owner, who is tall and strong but short-sighted and hard of hearing, represents the Athenian people; the unruly and ignorant sailors who compete to steer the ship stand in for politicians who vie for control of the government. The true pilot, who is dismissed as a useless stargazer because no one respects his expertise and abilities, is the philosopher.

7 (6.491d) we know that all germs or seeds ... when they fail to meet with proper nutriment, or climate, or soil ... are all the more sensitive to the want of a suitable environment, for evil is a greater enemy to what is good than to what is not: Compare Socrates’ emphases throughout book 3 on the strict education of future guardians in the ideal state.

8 (6.492a) he is like a plant which, ... if sown and planted in an alien soil, becomes the most noxious of all weeds, unless he be preserved by some divine power: Compare 6.493a, 6.496a-c, and 8.558b. It seems likely that Plato intends his readers to see Socrates as one such divinely protected individual.

9 (6.492a) Are not the public who say these things the greatest of all Sophists?: Compare 6.493a on how the sophists, whom the many “deem to be their adversaries, do, in fact, teach nothing but the opinion of the many”; see also note 12 on 1.343d.

10 (6.493d) the so-called necessity of Diomede: This is a proverbial expression (of uncertain origin) for unavoidable necessity. It perhaps refers to an incident (not related in Iliad or Odyssey) that occurred when Odysseus tried to kill Diomedes; on the way back to the Greek camp he in turn bound Odysseus and beat him with the flat of his sword blade.

11 (6.494a) Then the world cannot possibly be a philosopher?: Literally, the Greek reads “Then the many [or the majority] cannot be philosophic.” This brief but crucial statement provides a succinct connection between the metaphysical and epistemological and political concerns of Republic and echoes Parmenides’ disparagement of the “confusion in the breasts” of most mortals, who “know nothing.”

12 (6.494c) And what will a man such as he is be likely to do under such circumstances, especially if he be a citizen of a great city, rich and noble, and a tall, proper youth?: Plato undoubtedly means his readers to think of the Athenian general and statesman Alcibiades (450-404 B.C.E.). Alcibiades, the ward of the famous statesman Pericles, was aristocratic, handsome, charismatic, successful, and also undisciplined and capricious. He is memorably represented in Symposium as being completely in love with Socrates. Suspicion that Socrates had unduly influenced Alcibiades, who defected to the Spartans during the Peloponnesian War, may have lent weight to the charge of “corrupting the youth” that was leveled against Socrates in 399 B.C.E. In this passage and elsewhere (for example, Symposium 215e-216b), Plato seems keen to clear Socrates of responsibility for Alcibiades’ misdeeds. He may have had other young men in mind, as well, such as Dionysius II of Syracuse. As a young man, Dionysius was encouraged by his uncle Dion to study philosophy with Plato, but upon succeeding his father as tyrant of Syracuse, Dionysius fell out with both his uncle and his tutor.

13 (6.496d) he holds his peace, and goes his own way: Socrates’ defense of the man who, in a dysfunctional political community, keeps to himself (that is, practices apragmosynê, or “lack of involvement”) is in keeping with his criticism of “meddlesomeness” (polypragmosynê) that impairs city-states such as Athens; see note 8 on 4.433a.

14 (6.497c-d) you may remember my saying before, that some living authority would always be required in the State having the same idea of the constitution which guided you when ... you were laying down the laws: Compare 3.412a-c. Statesman 293c-297e offers a different perspective on the supreme importance of the “living authority” of the statesman.

15 (6.497e) I declare that States should pursue philosophy, not as they do now, but in a different spirit: In particular, Socrates objects to permitting young men to study philosophy; he elaborates his reasons at 7.537b-540c.

16 (6.498d) against the day when they live again, and hold the like discourse in another state of existence: The reference to reincarnation anticipates the myth of the afterlife that Socrates relates at 10.617b-621b.

17 (6.499b) whether they will or not: Compare 1.345e and book 7 in general, especially 7.519c-521b and 7.540b.

18 (6.499d) There is no impossibility in all this; that there is a difficulty, we acknowledge ourselves: Compare Adeimantus’ query at 5.471e, and also 7.540d.

19 (6.499e) do not attack the multitude: they will change their minds: It is to be assumed that the people in the ideal state’s bronze/iron class, though unable to be philosophoi themselves, would harbor no hostility to philosophy, since its practitioners would be their rulers and caretakers. If the ideal state is a possibility, however remote, so too is the widespread acceptance of philosophy that Socrates optimistically envisions in this passage.

20 (6.500d) will he, think you, be an unskilful artificer of justice, temperance, and every civil virtue?: Compare 7.540c, where Glaucon proclaims that Socrates is a “sculptor” who has “made statues of our governors faultless in beauty”

21 (6.501a) They will begin by taking the State and the manners of men, from which, as from a tablet, they will rub out the picture, and leave a clean surface: Compare 7.540e-541a. The assumption in both of these passages—that it is practically impossible to rehabilitate the attitudes and beliefs of adults (and even teenagers) who have been acculturated to a dysfunctional system of values—underlies the emphases in book 2 and 3 on the early education of the guardians. Plato arguably demonstrates the impossibility of such rehabilitation in his many “aporetic” dialogues (for example, Protagoras, Gorgias, Laches, Ion, Euthyphro, etc.), which feature Socrates in conversation with men who, though ultimately incapable of accounting for their beliefs and values, are nonetheless unable and unwilling to give up them up.

22 (6.502a) Will anyone deny the other point, that there may be sons of kings or princes who are by nature philosophers?: Some scholars see in this question a reference to Dionysius II of Syracuse. See note 12 on 6.494c.

23 (6.503b) Yes, my friend, I said, and I then shrank from hazarding ... that the perfect guardian must be a philosopher: Socrates assimilates the reluctance experienced by the personified discussion, or logos, to the “fear and hesitation” he claimed to feel at 5.472a. From this point through the end of book 7, Socrates makes several disclaimers about the inexact and provisional nature of the concepts he advances; see note 10 on the remarks at 4.435d, about which Socrates reminds Adeimantus at 6.504b.

24 (6.503b) And do not suppose that there will be many of them: Compare 6.485a-486e and 2.375c.

25 (6.504b) We were saying ... that he who wanted to see them in their perfect beauty must take a longer and more circuitous way, at the end of which they would appear: Compare 4.435c-d. In his or her investigations of justice, temperance, courage, etc., the philosopher who is a guardian in the ideal state would be able to take none of the “shortcuts” that Socrates and his companions have taken in Republic. Socrates’ comments are perhaps intended to remind readers that they should not confuse the conversation represented in this dialogue with true “dialectic” practiced by philosophers (compare 7.531d-534e).

26 (6.505a) for you have often been told that the idea of good is the highest knowledge, and that all other things become useful and advantageous only by their use of this: According to the theory of the ideas, all “good” objects in the phenomenal realm are “good” by virtue of their participation in the form/idea of the good; therefore, the only sure way of knowing the “relative” goodness of something is to evaluate it in light of the form of the good. Since what is “good” is the ultimate object of every human pursuit (6.505d-e), knowledge of the idea of the good is supremely important. As he has Socrates tentatively express his ideas about what the form of the good is, Plato invites readers to imagine that Socrates, Adeimantus, and presumably Glaucon have often discussed it, and that Socrates’ insistence that the idea of the good is the supreme object of learning is nothing new.

27 (6.505b) You are further aware that most people affirm pleasure to be the good: For Plato’s recurrent concern that most people identify what is pleasing with what is good, see note 2 on 3.391a.

28 (6.507c) But have you remarked that sight is by far the most costly and complex piece of workmanship which the artificer of the senses ever contrived?: See Phaedrus 250d for another assertion concerning the qualities that distinguish sight from the other senses. The “artificer (demiourgos) of the senses” is presumably “god,” but this is not made explicit.

29 (6.508b) And the power which the eye possesses is a sort of effluence which is dispensed from the sun?: There was considerable theoretical speculation in the classical period about the mechanics of sight and vision, to which Plato alludes in several passages—for example, Phaedrus 251c, Timaeus 45b—c, and Meno 76c-d.

30 (6.508b-c) And this is he whom I call the child of the good, whom the good begat in his own likeness, to be in the visible world ... what the good is in the intellectual world in relation to mind and the things of mind: The cosmology Socrates proposes, that the sun is the offspring of the good (“begat in his likeness”) is idiosyncratic. Nonetheless, his description of the sun as the offspring of the good builds on established associations between knowledge and physical sight (compare 6.484c); it also capitalizes on the keen awareness of the sun’s importance that would have been natural (and inevitable) in the pre-industrial society of classical Athens (compare 6.509b). On the logic of the analogy, just as the sun is responsible for the existence of all objects in the phenomenal realm, the idea of the good brings into being all objects in the intelligible realm. Moreover, just as the sun is the source of light in the phenomenal realm, which enables the eye to see physical objects (including the sun itself), the good is likewise the source of truth in the intelligible realm, which makes the soul (or mind) capable of apprehending intelligible objects (including the good itself). The power to exercise the faculty of sight, vis-à-vis objects in the phenomenal realm, is thus comparable to the power to exercise the faculty of reason, or knowledge, vis-à-vis objects in the intelligible realm.

“The offspring of the good, which the good engendered as an analogue to itself” is a more literal translation of the words that Jowett translates as “the child of the good, whom the good begat in his own likeness.” Jowett’s translation is plainly inspired by—and it arguably intends to evoke—passages in the King James version of the Bible, particularly Genesis 1:26-27 and Matthew 1:1-16.

31 (6.509c) Glaucon said, with a ludicrous earnestness: By the light of heaven, how amazing!: The phrase translated by Jowett as “with a ludicrous earnestness” is in Greek the adverb geloiôs (“humorously” or “facetiously”). Compare 6.506d, where Socrates, though urged on by Glaucon, claims to be anxious about attempting to describe the idea of the good, fearing that his “indiscreet zeal will bring ridicule [gelota]” upon him. The “light” tone adopted by Socrates and Glaucon is yet another reminder that the ideas advanced here about the idea of the good, though suggestive and important, are not meant to stand as definitive “last words.”

32 (6.509d-e) Now take a line which has been cut into two unequal parts, and divide each of them again in the same proportion ... and you will find that the first section in the sphere of the visible consists of images: The figure of the divided line supplies key refinements to the theory of knowledge (that is, the theory about distinct cognitive faculties that are used to apprehend different types of objects) that is first advanced at 5.476d-480a.

Socrates’ focus is initially on the objects of perception. In addition to the now familiar distinction between intelligible objects and objects in the phenomenal realm (here represented by “visible objects”), two new distinctions are introduced. Reflections, shadows, imitations, and the like are grouped together and differentiated from other objects in the phenomenal realm; within the intelligible realm, objects that the soul apprehends on the basis of untested hypotheses (that is, mathematical objects) are differentiated from those that are apprehended through dialectic, which tests hypotheses and “ascends to a first principle” (that is, the ideas).

Reflecting the fact that intelligible objects, which neither come into being nor can be destroyed, are more “real” than objects in the phenomenal realm, the line is unequally divided, with the larger portion given to the intelligible. The two main segments are also unequally divided in the same proportion as the whole line, and again the divisions reflect the relative “reality” of the different types of objects within, respectively, the intelligible and phenomenal realms. Thus the segment of the line representing reflections, shadows, and imitations is smallest of all. If each of the line’s four segments is designated by a letter (for example, A for the segment representing the ideas, B for the other intelligible objects, C for phenomenal objects generally, and D for reflections, etc.), then the line’s proportions can be expressed in the following terms: AB: CD :: A : B :: C: D.

33 (6.510b) There are two subdivisions, in the lower of which the soul uses the figures given by the former division as images; the inquiry can only be hypothetical ... ; in the higher of the two, the soul passes out of hypotheses ... proceeding only in and through the ideas themselves: Despite Socrates’ initial emphasis on the differences among the objects represented by the divided line, his concern—beginning with this sentence—shifts to distinguishing the cognitive processes and faculties whereby mathematical objects and the ideas are apprehended. Mathematicians, as Socrates and Glaucon agree at 7.531e-532a, are not required “to give and take a reason” for the objects they study; they hypothesize, for example, a circle, and study its properties, but never question whether the circle they study actually exists or not. They rely, moreover, on visible images (for example, circles that are physically drawn) for their investigations. In contrast, dialecticians—that is, those who study the ideas—depend on no such physical models and, most importantly, test their hypotheses; they do not take for granted the existence of the ideas they investigate. Mathematical “objects” per se, then, do not differ substantively from the ideas, and they are capable of being apprehended by the faculty of “reason” (noesis) as well as that of “understanding” (dianoia); see 6.511d. It is, rather, the exercise of noesis that differs radically from the exercise of dianoia. The distinction here between noesis and dianoia looks ahead to the description of the philosopher’s education at 7.521c-540a, in which training in mathematical subjects—that is, “number science” (arithmetikê), plane and solid geometry, astronomy, and harmonics—constitutes a mere “prelude” that prepares the future philosopher for his or her study of dialectic (7.531d).

34 (6.511b) that other sort of knowledge which reason itself attains by the power of dialectic: Dialectic and its use are described in more detailed, albeit still tentative, terms at 7.531d-539d.

35 (6.511d-e) let there be four faculties in the soul ... and let us suppose that the several faculties have clearness in the same degree that their objects have truth: The terms Socrates now uses for the four cognitive faculties, which are rendered differently by different translators, are noesis (“reason”), dianoia (“understanding”), pistis (“faith” or “conviction”), and eikasia (“perception of shadows” in Jowett, but often translated elsewhere as “imagination”). Noesis and dianoia fall under the rubric of epistemê (gnosis, gnome), the terms used in book 5 to describe the general cognitive faculty that enables one to apprehend objects in the “higher” intelligible realm, whereas pistis and eikasia are different species of doxa, the general faculty by which phenomenal objects are perceived. See note 33 on 6.510b and note 24 on 5.476d.

Book 7

1 (7.514a) Behold! human beings living in an underground den: Socrates’ allegory of the cave builds on the image of the divided line as well as the analogy established in the simile of the sun comparing the eye’s ability to apprehend the objects in the physical realm to the mind’s ability to apprehend intelligible objects. Likening the prisoners to “ourselves” (7.515a) and the world of daily experience to mere shadows and echoes, it vividly reinforces Socrates’ contention that most people are mistaken in their belief that the phenomenal world is real and knowable (see 7.517a-c). In contrast to the simile, the allegory accentuates the difficulties of apprehending the idea of the good, which is once again represented by the sun, and consequently of developing the cognitive faculty that enables this apprehension. It emphasizes the emotional as well as physical distress of the prisoner (that is, future philosopher) who, upon being released from his bonds, is disabused of his assumptions about “reality” as he makes the arduous upward journey out of the cave into the bright light of day (7.515c-d). The released prisoner, once accustomed to looking at the sunlit world and the sun itself, will also have difficulties when he is forced to reenter the dark and shadowy cave; the description of his tense dealings with his former fellow-prisoners at 7.517a-e harks back to Socrates’ explanation of the philosopher’s apparent uselessness in 6.488a-489a, and it resonates as well with what is suggested in Republic and other dialogues (for example, Phaedo, Gorgias) about the philosopher’s disdain for material goods and “prizes.”

Not all the details in the allegory stand up to logical analysis. For example, the identity of the individuals responsible for the parade of shadow-casting objects and for the releasing of the prisoner (7.514c-515d) is not accounted for, nor is it clear how the released prisoner could be “compelled to fight in courts of law... about the images or the shadows of images of justice” once he returns to the cave (7.517d). Moreover, whereas the divided line’s differentiation of cognitive faculties is clearly important to the allegory’s distinctions among stages of cognitive development, it does not seem necessary to insist on precise correspondence between the stages of the released prisoner’s upward progress and the line’s four segments. The allegory’s purpose, however, is to be powerfully suggestive, and logic is not its primary concern. Its point is simply, as Socrates intimates in 7.516e-519a, that the situation of the prisoners in the cave represents the lot of most people. Just as the prisoners (except for the fortunate few who are released) are unable to conceive of a world outside the dim cave, so most people are incapable of apprehending anything other than the phenomenal world (the world of “becoming”—see 518c, and also note 24 on 5.476d). Moreover, just as only a few prisoners are released, only a few people are permitted (by a lucky and rare combination of circumstances) to develop the higher cognitive faculties of dianoia and noesis and thus the ability to apprehend the intellectual world (the world of “being”).

2 (7.515e) And suppose once more, that he is reluctantly dragged up a steep and rugged ascent: Socrates’ description of the released prisoner’s upward journey evokes the mythological motif of anabasis—that is, an upward journey out of the underworld. Compare 7.521c.

3 (7.517b) and you will not misapprehend me if you interpret the journey upward to be the ascent of the soul into the intellectual world, in my view, at least, which, at your desire, I have expressed—whether rightly or wrongly, God knows: Compare Socrates’ reluctance to describe the idea of the good at 6.504b and 6.509c.

4 (7.518b) certain professors of education: Some sophists and professional teachers of rhetoric claimed to be able to instill knowledge (epistemê) in their students. According to Socrates’ argument, however, the faculty of epistemê is already in the soul; as the discussion of books 6 and 7 makes plain, cultivating this faculty is a challenging and difficult process that few are capable of undertaking since, as he states in the immediately following paragraph, it involves the reorientation of the whole soul away from “becoming” and toward “being.”

5 (7.520c) Wherefore each of you, when his turn comes, must go down to the general underground abode, and get the habit of seeing in the dark: The verb “go down” (or “descend”) in Greek is katabainein. Katabasis (the opposite of anabasis; see note 2 on 7.515e) typically refers to a journey to the underworld undertaken by a heroic figure such as Heracles, Theseus, or Orpheus.

6 (7.521c) as some are said to have ascended from the world below to the gods?: The reference may be to individuals like Asclepius, who was apothe osized after being killed by Zeus, and Semele, the Theban princess who was pregnant with Dionysus when she was killed by Zeus’ thunderbolt.

7 (7.521c) the turning over of an oyster-shell: Ostrakon in Greek actually means “potsherd” (pottery fragment), not “oyster-shell.” For the purposes of the game to which Socrates alludes, a potsherd was painted black on one side and white on the other; when it was flipped in the air, the players called “night” or “day,” just as people today call “heads” and “tails” when coins are flipped. Socrates’ meaning is that education is a serious affair that cannot be left to chance.

8 (7.521d) Usefulness in war: Arithmetic, plane and solid geometry, and astronomy, which constitute four of the five preparatory disciplines that future philosophers should study as they train their souls to move from “becoming to being,” all had obvious military applications. Nonetheless, when discussing geometry and astronomy, Socrates insists that utility in war is not the most important determinant of these disciplines’ value to guardians in training (7.526a and 7.528d-529a). Rather, they are useful primarily because they “make more easy the vision of the idea of good” (7.526d-e).

9 (7.522c) The little matter of distinguishing one, two, and three—in a word, number and calculation: do not all arts and sciences necessarily partake of them?: “Number” (arthmos) and “calculation” (logismos) lead “the soul toward being” (7.523a) because they help people make sense of confusing appearances and thus lead them to look beyond mere appearances (7.523b). All of the mathematical disciplines that Socrates goes on to describe, beginning with arithmetikê (the “science of number”), are essential to the philosopher’s training since it helps him (or her) “rise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being” (7.525b).

10 (7.523a) It appears to me to be a study of the kind which we are seeking, and which leads naturally to reflection, but never to have been rightly used; for the true use of it is simply to draw the soul toward being: Compare 7.527a-b and 7.529a-531c for critiques of the methods and emphases of those who currently study geometry, astronomy, and harmonics.

11 (7.524d) And to which class do unity and number belong?: That is, do “unity and number” belong to the class of impressions that are not innately confusing and require no “calculation” or to the class that requires abstract reasoning to be properly understood? The phrase “unity and number” reflects the fact that Plato did not consider “one” a number.

12 (7.524e) “What is absolute unity?”: Any single object in the phenomenal world (that is, a visible “one”) is actually both “one” and “many”; for example, one flower has many petals, one piece of fruit has many seeds. The realization that every visible “one” is in fact both “one” and “many” accordingly leads one to wonder about the “absolute unity” that is not also “many,” and to realize eventually that this “absolute unity” is not to be found in the phenomenal world.

13 (7.525d-e) absolute unity: That is, the unit that is adopted for the purpose of a given calculation and which is, for the purpose of that calculation, indivisible. Such a unit is, strictly speaking, hypothetical.

14 (7.527a-b) They have in view practice only, and are always speaking ... of squaring and extending and applying and the likethey confuse the necessities of geometry with those of daily life; whereas knowledge is the real object of the whole science: In the fifth century B.C.E., some geometers tried their hand at town planning; for example, Hippodamus of Miletus designed the grid-iron layouts of streets in Piraeus and the Athenian colony of Thurii (in Italy). Such undertakings seem to have struck many people as “ridiculous”; in Aristophanes’ Birds (produced in 414 B.C.E.), the geometer Meton is comically represented as a pompous would-be town planner.

15 (7.527d) I am amused, I said, at your fear of the world, which makes you guard against the appearance of insisting upon useless studies: Socrates’ gentle admonition resonates with what has been established about the “un-philosophic” nature of the many and their current prejudice against philosophy; see, for example, 6.488e-489a and 6.494a.

16 (7.528a) Then take a step backward, for we have gone wrong in the order of the sciences: Solid geometry, which Socrates proposes as the logical follow-up for the study of plane geometry, is less complex and abstract than astronomy, which is the study of “solid objects in revolution [that is, motion].” The subjects of the entire preparatory curriculum (that is, arithmetikê, plane geometry, solid geometry or stereometry, astronomy, harmonics) are increasingly complex and abstract, and they are organized so as to make future philosophers ready for the supremely difficult and wholly abstract operations of dialectic.

17 (7.528b) but so little seems to be known as yet about these subjects: Problems of solid geometry had concerned several theoreticians (for example, Anaxagoras, Democritus, some in the Pythagorean school) in the fifth century. What Glaucon apparently means here is that solutions to complex stereometrical problems (that is, beyond simple problems such as the doubling of a cube) had not yet been discovered.

18 (7.529b) whether a man gapes at the heavens or blinks on the ground, seeking to learn some particular of sense, I would deny that he can learn, for nothing of that sort is matter of science: As in the case of geometry (7.527a), Socrates argues that astronomy ought not be pursued for the sake of understanding physical phenomena (that is, the movements of heavenly bodies), but rather as abstract geometry in four dimensions that is concerned with “true motions of absolute slowness and absolute swiftness.” So too “harmonics,” which is concerned with the motion of sounds (7.530d), is to be studied for the sake of understanding abstract “harmonies” of number as opposed to those that can be physically heard (7.531c).

Plato perhaps has Socrates specifically disavow interest in problems dealing with “some particular of sense” in order to distance him further from the figure of “Socrates” in Aristophanes’ Clouds, whose “Think-Factory” sponsors ridiculous research in “astronomy” and other fields. See note 22 on 2.378b and note 10 on 7.523a.

19 (7.530d) There is a second, I said, which is the counterpart of the one already named: Astronomy, which has been “already named,” is the study of the motion of solid bodies in space; its “sister science” is harmonics, the study of the motion of sound. For the comparison of the functions of the ear and eye, see 6.507c-d.

20 (7.530d) as the Pythagoreans say: The reference is to the followers of Pythagoras, the religious thinker and theorist who settled in Croton in southern Italy during the sixth century B.C.E. Pythagoreans were known in the classical period for their ascetic way of life, their belief in the reincarnation of the soul, and their mathematically based study of music and harmonics.

21 (7.531a) The teachers of harmony compare the sounds and consonances which are heard only, and their labor, like that of the astronomers, is in vain: This is most likely a reference to the Pythagoreans.

22 (7.531a) condensed notes, as they call them: Pyknomata in Greek is a technical term that apparently refers to combinations of two quarter-tone (or semi-tone) intervals.

23 (7.531b) one set of them declaring that they distinguish an intermediate note and have found the least interval which should be the unit of measurement: For example, the quarter-tone. Other theorists (perhaps including Plato himself) posited the semi-tone as “the least interval,” with a view not only to simplifying the analysis of music, but also encouraging simplicity in musical composition.

24 (7.531b) plectrum: The plectrum was the pick by which the strings of an instrument were plucked. The metaphor developed in the first sentence of this paragraph plainly alludes to the torturing and beating of slaves.

25 (7.531d) the prelude, or what?: Prooimion in Greek refers broadly to the introductory section of a song (or poem or speech). The musical metaphor is continued in the following paragraphs, where Socrates refers to the nomos, or “song,” that dialectic performs.

26 (7.531d-e) For you surely would not regard the skilled mathematician as a dialectician?: Compare 6.510b-511d. Unlike the mathematician who, for example, assumes the existence of “absolute unity” (7.525d-526a,) the dialectician’s study of “the idea of one” would not be complete until he had “ascended to first principles” (6.511a-b) and showed by argument that such a concept is essential to the rational understanding of both the intelligible and phenomenal worlds.

27 (7.532d) This, however, is not a theme to be treated of in passing only.... And so, whether our conclusion be true or false, let us assume all this, and proceed at once from the prelude or preamble to the chief strain, and describe that in like manner: Socrates’ reticence in describing dialectic mirrors the reserve he displays when discussing the idea of the good, which is the ultimate object of dialectic. Compare 7.517b. The word translated here as “chief strain” is nomos, which also means “law” and/or “custom.”

28 (7.533d) Custom terms them sciences: That is, epistemai (the plural of epistemê). Whereas the term epistemai is “customarily” used to refer to disciplines, or fields of study, Socrates has earlier used epistemê to designate the cognitive faculty by which objects in the intelligible world are apprehended.

29 (7.534d) you would not allow the future rulers to be like posts, having no reason in them, and yet to be set in authority over the highest matters?: Jowett’s interpretation, that grammai in this context refers to the lines at the start of racecourses (hence his translation “posts”), is disputable. The reference is more likely to alogoi grammai—that is, “irrational quantities” such as the square root of negative one. If so, there would be a witty play on the adjective alogos (“irrational,” “having no reason”) since those who are unable to approach the idea of the good through dialectic are unable to give an account (logon dounai) of it. Compare 7.531e, where Socrates and Glaucon agree that mathematicians are incapable of reasoning (literally, unable to logon dounai).

30 (7.536c) Certainly not, I said; and yet perhaps, in thus turning jest into earnest I am equally ridiculous.... I had forgotten ... that we were not serious, and spoke with too much excitement. For when I saw philosophy so undeseruedly trampled under foot of men. . . . : Socrates painted a vivid (and somewhat playful) picture of philosophy bereft of legitimate “suitors” and forced to “marry ... a bald little tinker” at 6.495c-496a. His statement that he and his interlocutors “are not serious” may come as a surprise, given the stress repeatedly laid on the importance of the issues raised in Republic; see note 14 on 1.344e. Nonetheless, it is in keeping with the many advertisements concerning the provisional nature of the conversation, and it perhaps should stand as a reminder that Plato did not hope to accomplish anything truly “serious” in this or any other dialogue. For the fundamentally “playful” nature of writing, see Phaedrus 274c-278e.

31 (7.537e) Do you not remark, I said, how great is the evil which dialectic has introduced?: Socrates’ acknowledgment that dialectic is potently destabilizing, since it inevitably causes one to devalue that which one prized in the past (and which others may still prize) and to develop “a questioning spirit” that “asks what is fair and honorable” (7.538d), paves the way for his distinction between dialectic, as practiced for socially constructive ends by the true philosopher, and “antilogic” and “eristic,” as pursued by those who carelessly engage in arguments simply for the sake of winning (7.539b-d; see note 6 on 5.454a). It also reinforces his point that philosophy (that is, dialectic) is not suitable for young, restless people, no matter how gifted (7.539a-b; compare 6.498b-c).

Book 8

1 (8.544c) the four governments of which I spoke ... are first, those of Crete and Sparta, which are generally applauded: In contrast to Athens’ democracy, the governments of Crete and Sparta strictly limited political franchise. Critics of Athenian democracy praised the Spartan constitution in particular, and Plato is careful to have Socrates associate it with “timarchy,” which is characterized by “love of honor” (see 545b), and not with the more degenerate “oligarchy,” in which wealth alone determines qualification for political franchise and leadership.

2 (8.545d) Clearly, all political changes originate in divisions of the actual governing power; a government which is united, however small, cannot be moved: Compare the concern for stasis (factionalism and civil strife) at 4.444b.

3 (8.545e) Shall we imagine them in solemn mockery, to play and jest with us as if we were children, and to address us in a lofty tragic vein, making believe to be in earnest?: As above at 7.536b-c, Plato has Socrates call attention to the fundamentally “playful” nature of the discussion, and he seems to invite his readers not to take what is claimed in 8.546a-c too literally.

4 (8.546a) In plants that grow in the earth, as well as in animals that move on the earth’s surface, fertility and sterility of soul and body occur when the circumferences of the circles of each are completed, which in short-lived existences pass over a short space, and in long-lived ones over a long space: Socrates envisions the “cycle” of fertility for each species of living thing as represented by a circle; for a short-lived species, the representative circle is small and so is its circumference, whereas the circle is larger for the longer-lived. The notion advanced here—that the cycles of fertility and sterility in individual species are mathematically comprehensible—anticipates what is suggested in 8.546b—c about the existence of a rational, mathematically comprehensible order governing the cosmos as a whole.

5 (8.546b) but the period of human birth is comprehended in a number ... : Adopting the voice of the Muses, Socrates presents a calculation for the number that comprehends, or governs, human births. The number ( 12,960,000) is in fact a “master number” that comprehends the area of two great figures, one of which is a square with sides of 3600 units, and the other a rectangle with sides of 4800 and 2700 units.

The “number of Plato” is a notoriously difficult passage that has garnered a great deal of scholarly attention. Critics have offered a number of interpretations of its significance. It is possible that the number and its calculation are indebted to Pythagorean mathematical theories, and it is also possible that the two figures comprehended in the master number 12,960,000 represent two periods in the “lifetime” of the cosmos with which human births, if they are to be “goodly and fortunate” (8.546c), must somehow be in accord. All such interpretations are speculative, however. As suggested in note 3 on 8.545e, the fact that Socrates ascribes the calculation of the number to the Muses (who, he imagines, “play and jest with us as if we were children”) should make us cautious about attempting to interpret the number and its calculation in an overly precise manner. Nonetheless, it seems reasonable to suppose that the passage in 8.546a-c is intended to convey, in general and suggestive terms, two facts: (1) that there is a rational order governing the cosmos, which can be expressed in mathematical terms, and (2) that this order is extremely difficult to comprehend. However its philosophical significance is interpreted, the passage puts Plato’s mathematical sophistication on full display.

6 (8.546c) Now this number represents a geometrical figure which has control over the good and evil of births: More literally, “this entire geometric number has authority over this sort of thing, [that is] better and inferior births.” Jowett’s translation is somewhat misleading, since the entire “geometric number” comprehends the two geometric figures described in the immediately preceding passage. The apparent meaning of this sentence is that, to be appropriate and “good,” human births must somehow be in accordance with the cosmic order that the figures suggest; precisely how this accordance is to be accomplished is left unspecified.

7 (8.547b-c) There was a battle between them, and at last they agreed to distribute their land and houses among individual owners; and they enslaved their friends and maintainers ... and they themselves were engaged in war and in keeping a watch against them: Compare 3.416d-417b and 5.462b-464d, where Socrates links private property to the development of private interests that differ from those of the community as a whole and are thus detrimental, as is reasserted at 8.550d. Socrates’ assumption seems to be that the possession of private property goes hand in hand with the establishment of individual families and households; see, for example, the reference to “wives” at 8.548a-b.

8 (8.547d) In the honor given to rulers, in the abstinence of the warrior-class from agriculture, handicrafts, and trade in general, in the institution of common meals, and in the attention paid to gymnastics and military trainingin all these respects this State will resemble the former: Plato surely intends Socrates’ description of the practices of the ruling class in the timarchic state to remind his readers of the Spartans. See note 1 on 8.544c.

9 (8.549b) having lost his best guardian: The language used in this passage, which identifies logos (“reason,” which Jowett translates as “philosophy”) mixed with mousikê (“music”) as the best guardian (aristos phylax) and savior of virtue, is pointed; compare 2.367a.

10 (8.549c) His origin is as follows.... : The vivid vignette describing the origin of the timarchic man, who is seduced into straying from the ways of his virtuous father by the nagging of his malcontent mother and household slaves, seems designed to reinforce the argument that individual families—and the private interests and loyalties they inevitably cause to develop—are detrimental to the development of “virtue” in both individuals and communities. Dysfunction in the family similarly accounts for the development of other “degenerate” personalities; compare 8.553a-d, 8.558c-560e, and 9.572d-575a.

11 (8.550e) And so they grow richer and richer, and the more they think of making a fortune the less they think of virtue; for when riches and virtue are placed together in the scales of the balance the one always rises as the other falls: This directly counters Cephalus’ assertion at 1.331b that wealth facilitates virtue; compare 3.416d-417b.

12 (8.551a-b) They next proceed to make a law which fixes a sum of money as the qualification for citizenship: The ownership of property (often land), as well as birth from citizen parents, were the typical qualifications for citizenship in Greek city-states.

13 (8.551d) The inevitable division: such a State is not one, but two States, the one of poor, the other of rich men; and they are living on the same spot and always conspiring against one another: Compare 4.422e; see also 4.422a on the corrosive social effects of wealth and poverty, and 8.555c on the incompatibility of wealth and self-restraint.

14 (8.552a) nor horseman, nor hoplite: Hoplites were heavily armed infantrymen. Since Greek men typically supplied their own armor (and their own horses, if in the cavalry), and since the hoplite’s armor was expensive (as was the upkeep of horses), only men from wealthier classes served as hoplites and cavalrymen.

15 (8.552c) May we not say that this is the drone in the house who is like the drone in the honeycomb, and that the one is the plague of the city as the other is of the hive?: The images of the beehive and its drones (both “stingless” and “with stingers”) remain central throughout the rest of book 8 and in book 9’s discussion of the “tyrannical” personality. Within the individual soul, “drones” are desires and appetites that interfere with reason’s rule. In the state, “drones” are the criminals (who have “stings”) and paupers (who are “stingless”) created by extremes of wealth and poverty; it is the “drones with stingers” who, in Socrates’ account, exercise increasingly greater power in the increasingly degenerate constitutions.

16 (8.554d-e) The man, then, will be at war with himself; he will be two men, and not one: The oligarchic city is similarly described as being two cities “conspiring against one another” at 8.551d.

17 (8.556a) The evil blazes up like a fire; and they will not extinguish it either by restricting a man’s use of his own property, or by another remedy: This critique of what had become, by Plato’s day, common money-lending practices reflects the prejudices of upper-class Athenians against traders and bankers (many of whom were non-Athenian), as well as more general anxieties about the monetarized economy that had been rapidly developing from the mid-fifth century B.C.E. in Athens and other Greek city-states.

18 (8.557a) And then democracy comes into being after the poor have conquered their opponents, slaughtering some and banishing some: Socrates’ account of democracy’s development from oligarchy, while incorporating elements that reflect how democratic governments arose in some Greek city-states (including Athens) during the fifth century, is nonetheless not aimed first and foremost at historical accuracy. His subsequent account of democracy’s degeneration into tyranny (8.562a-569c) likewise incorporates reflections of actual events and phenomena into an essentially fictional framework. Nonetheless, many magistrates in classical Athens were elected by lot, and the following description of the democratic city, with its love of “freedom and frankness,” is plainly designed to evoke the political institutions and social arrangements of Athens.

19 (8.557b) In the first place, are they not free[?]: The emphasis on democracy’s love of freedom (compare 8.562b-c) recalls the popular identification of happiness with the freedom “to do what one wants,” which Socrates challenges at the beginning of the dialogue (1.345a).

20 (8.558a) And is not their humanity to the condemned in some cases quite charming?: The wording in Greek is ambiguous and variously interpreted. It may refer to the relaxed behavior of people who have been condemned for crimes, or conversely to the insouciant attitudes of those who have sat in judgment.

21 (8.558c) These and other kindred characteristics are proper to democracy, which is a charming form, of government ... dispensing a sort of equality to equals and unequals alike: Socrates’ acknowledgment that democracy is “charming” (literally, hedeia, or “pleasant”), insofar as it affords the greatest number of people the greatest amount of freedom, should be interpreted in the light of Republic’s sustained interest in disassociating what is pleasant from what is good and beneficial. See 8.561c, as well as note 2 on 3.391a. The “equality” of Athens and democracy in general is opposed to the ideal state’s recognition of inequality; compare 2.370a.

22 (8.560a) and he goes to war with himself: That is, he falls into stasis (civil war) with himself; compare 4.444b.

23 (8.560c) the aforesaid vain conceits shut the gate of the King’s fastness: The language continues the image of the rational part of the soul (which is the soul’s king) as being seated—and besieged—in an acropolis, or citadel; compare 8.561b.

24 (8.560d) modesty, which they call silliness, is ignominiously thrust into exile by them, and temperance, which they nick-name unmanliness, is trampled in the mire and cast forth; ... they drive them beyond the border: Compare Thrasymachus’ attempt to redefine virtue (aretê) and baseness (kakia) at 1.348c-d. In his account of the stasis on Corcyra in 427 B.C.E. (History of the Peloponnesian War 3.82-84), Thucydides describes a convolution of basic moral terminology very much like the one outlined in these paragraphs.

25 (8.561b) any true word of advice: That is, logos. Socrates describes logos (that is, “reason,” “rational accounting”) as the guardian (phylax) and “saviour” of virtue at 8.549b.

26 (8.562a) And does not tyranny spring from democracy in the same manner as democracy from oligarchy—I mean, after a sort?: That is, each degenerate constitution is destroyed by what it erroneously values in the place of true virtue (aretê). Just as democracy, in Socrates’ logic, is destroyed by its desire for freedom (8.562b-d), so timocracy and oligarchy are brought to ruin because of the premiums they place, either covertly or overtly, on wealth.

27 (8.562e) By degrees the anarchy finds a way into private houses, and ends by getting among the animals and infecting them: A similar point is made in a treatise dating to approximately 430 B.C.E., titled “The Constitution of the Athenians” (alternatively, “The Old Oligarch”), which was erroneously attributed in antiquity to Plato’s contemporary (and fellow Socratic) Xenophon.

28 (8.565b-c) And the end is that when they see the people ... seeking to do them wrong, then at last they are forced to become oligarchs in reality; they do not wish to be, but the sting of the drones torments them and breeds revolution in them: Socrates’ representation of how wealthy men are forced against their will to oppose democratic governments involves some special pleading and seems tailored to support the political biases of Republic.

29 (8.566a) After a while he is driven out, but comes back, in spite of his enemies, a tyrant full grown: Plato probably intends his readers to think of the Athenian tyrant Peisistratus (mid-sixth century B.C.E.), whose rise to power is described in Herodotus, Histories 1.59-64.

30 (8.566b) Then comes the famous request for a body-guard: A corps of armed bodyguards was the hallmark of tyrants in ancient Greek city-states. Readers are probably meant to think of figures like Dionysius I of Syracuse and others, as well as Peisistratus. Some of the details Socrates gives concerning the tyrant’s brutal techniques for maintaining power also recall the strategies of the so-called Thirty Tyrants who seized control of Athens in 404 at the end of the Peloponnesian War. Plato’s original readers would have surely appreciated the irony in the fact that the word for “bodyguards” is phylakes, the very term that Socrates and his companions have used throughout Republic to designate the guardians of the ideal state.

31 (8.566c) “By pebbly Hermus’s shore he flees and rests not, and is not ashamed to be a coward”: This is a quotation from Herodotus, Histories 1.55. The Lydian king Croesus was a descendant of Gyges, who is mentioned in Republic at 2.359c-360a; he was counseled by the oracle at Delphi to flee when a “mule” (that is, Cyrus, who had ethnically mixed parentage) sat on the throne of Persia.

32 (8.567c) happy man, he is the enemy of them all, and must seek occasion against them whether he will or no, until he has made a purgation of the State: The emphasis on the ways in which the budding tyrant is compelled against his will (in this case, to kill all worthy rivals and allies) marks an important point in Socrates’ effort to discredit Thrasymachus’ assertion that the tyrant enjoys the maximum amount of “freedom.” Compare 1.344c and 9.578c-579c.

33 (8.568b) “Tyrants are wise by living with the wise”: The verse, which is also attributed to Euripides in Theages 125b, is in fact from Sophocles’ lost Ajax of Locris. Socrates’ ironic praise of tragedy’s “wisdom” resonates with the Iconcerns raised earlier about the problematic moral messages conveyed by poetic texts.

34 (8.568c) But they will continue to go to other cities and attract mobs, and hire voices fair and loud and persuasive, and draw the cities over to tyrannies and democracies: The insinuation that democracy is one step away from tyranny would have surely affronted most Athenians, who considered democracy, with its respect for law and guarantee of freedom, the opposite of tyranny.

35 (8.568e) Why, clearly, he said, then he and his boon companions, whether male or female, will be maintained out of his father’s estate: Athenians viewed the abuse and neglect of elderly parents with abhorrence, and the image of the tyrant as an ungrateful “son” who brutally abuses his aged parent (that is, the people, or demos) is viscerally jolting. See also 7.537e-538c, where the immature dialectician is compared to an ungrateful adopted son. In Aristophanes’ Clouds, Socrates is represented as indirectly responsible for a son’s beating of his aged and indulgent father. The strong aversion to such violence that is attributed to Socrates in this passage is perhaps another step in Plato’s effort to counter Aristophanes’ unflattering portrayal. See note 22 on 2.378b.

Book 9

1 (9.572b) even in good men, there is a lawless wild-beast nature, which peers out in sleep: Compare 9.588b-e, where Socrates suggests that the soul is like a hybrid creature that is part human, part lion, and part chimerical beast. These vivid formulations pave the way for Socrates’ conclusion concerning the value of justice in the individual—that is, that it is what strengthens the truly human element of the soul and is thus what “humanizes” human beings (9.588e-589c). As the agent of “humanization,” justice is thus the “excellence” (aretê) that enables human beings to fulfill their unique function (ergon) and so attain happiness (eudaimonia); compare 1.352e-354b. It is doubtless no accident that Thrasymachus, the proponent of injustice and self-aggrandizement, is initially represented as beast-like (1.336b).

2 (9.573b) And is not this the reason why, of old, love has been called a tyrant?: The overwhelming, “tyrannical” power of eros (“lust,” “sexual passion”) is a familiar poetic topic. Compare the description at 9.575a of the domination of the tyrant’s soul by sexual desire.

3 (9.573d) Love is the lord of the house within him, and orders all the concerns of his soul: The image of the tyrannical man as dominated by sexual appetite (eros) stands in contrast to the characterization developed in Reppublic and other dialogues of the philosopher who, though a “lover,” directs his erotic energy toward spiritual rather than physical pursuits and always prefers what is beneficial over what is gratifying. See note 16 on 3.402e. Socrates’ characterization of the tyrant/tyrannical man as a slave of eros also capitalizes on the fact that eros was metaphorically associated (especially in classical Athens) with “lust” for political power and prominence.

4 (9.574d) He first takes their property, and ... then he breaks into a house ... ; next he proceeds to clear a temple: The modus operandi of the tyrannical man, which includes the abuse of his parents and his reliance on an ever more powerful “bodyguard” (that is, of unruly appetites), mirrors that of the actual tyrant. See 8.566b and 8.568e-569c; also 9.575d.

5 (9.576d) There can be no mistake ... as to which is which, and therefore I will at once inquire whether you would arrive at a similar decision about their relative happiness and misery: Socrates’ assessment of the misery of the city-state ruled by a tyrant would have been very much in keeping with the judgment of most Athenians. It is his judgment of the tyrant’s personal misery that goes against the “common view,” as set forth by Thrasymachus in book 1 and again by Glaucon and Adeimantus in book 2.

6 (9.577a) I should have a judge whose mind can enter into and see through human nature? he must not be like a child who looks at the outside and is dazzled ... but let him be one who has a clear insight: Socrates similarly warns in book 10 against being “like children” and indulging in “childish love,” as he reminds Glaucon that emotions like grief ought to be restrained ( 10.604c), and that the poetry of Homer and “other tragedians” must be excluded from the ideal city-state (10.608a). Compare his insistence at 5.466b that the judgment of the best life ought not be clouded by “some youthful conceit of happiness.” Concerns about the “childishness” of (most) adults, who are readily taken in by appearances and more eager to obtain what is immediately gratifying than what is of lasting benefit, deeply inform Republic’s examination of justice and its formulations concerning the ideal state, and they go hand in hand with its concerns about the premium that most people put on pleasure. See note 2 on 3.391a; also Gorgias 521e-522a and Crito 49b.

7 (9.577b) where he may be seen stripped of his tragedy attire: See 8.568a-b for Socrates’ ironic commendation of tragedy’s glamorization of tyranny and tyrants.

8 (9.579b) he lives in his hole like a woman hidden in the house: The comparison of the tyrant to a woman “hidden in the house” aims to discredit in the most devastating terms the claims to freedom, “excellence,” and, by extension, manliness that Thrasymachus had made on behalf of the tyrant at 1.344a-c. In contrast to the “feminine” tyrant, the philosopher, whom many people might consider “unmanly” because of his failure to concern himself with material success (compare 8.549d), emerges as the true epitome of masculinity, in control of both himself and his life.

9 (9.580a-b) as the general umpire in theatrical contests proclaims the result: Participants in the dramatic competitions held in the Theater of Dionysus at Athens were awarded prizes by a panel of ten judges, one of whom was chosen to announce the results. The references in this passage to the judgment of and awarding of prizes to dramas in theatrical competitions, a process that presumably took into account public reactions to the performances, underscore how Glaucon’s assessments are influenced by neither showy exteriors nor the need to cater to popular sentiments. Compare, for example, 9.577b; also 7.527d-528a.

10 (9.580b) they are the royal: The word basilikon can also be translated as “kingly.” Socrates also calls the constitution of the ideal state and its corresponding individual “aristocratic” (for example, at 8.544e), since that which is “best” (aristos) rules in both. Compare 9.587c-d.

11 (9.580c-d) Then this, I said, will be our first proof; and there is another, which may also have some weight: Socrates actually offers three “proofs” of the tyrant’s misery and, conversely, of the happiness of the just man and philosopher. The second proof (9.580d-583a) argues that the pleasures experienced by “lovers of wisdom” are far superior to those of “lovers of gain,” and the third (9.583b-587c) argues that the “pleasures” valued by “lovers of gain” and “lovers of honor” are in fact not pleasures at all, but mere efforts to void pain.

The number three, which signified completeness in a variety of situations and phenomena (for example, the number of rounds in wrestling matches and other competitions, the number of libations poured at religious rituals, etc.), figures prominently in Republic. There are three “proofs” of the philosopher and just man’s happiness in book 9, and there are three arguments discrediting poetry’s claims to political and practical utility in book 10. The final calculation of the tyrant’s misery and the philosopher’s happiness is based on squaring and cubing the number 3 because, as it is decided, the tyrant is three times removed from the oligarchical man, who is in turn three times removed from the just “aristocratic” man (9.587c-588a); at 10.597e and 10.601d-602a, poetic imitation is determined to be three times removed from the truth. At 5.472a, Socrates likens Glaucon’s and Adeimantus’ challenges to his conception of the ideal state to three great waves. Most fundamentally, there are three classes in the ideal city-state and three corresponding parts of the soul.

Just as the definition of justice in book 4 harks back to Polemarchus’ initial effort to define justice as “giving what is due” (4.433a; compare 1.332a-c), the three proofs offered in book 9 of justice’s benefits return to but also reconfigure Thrasymachus’ definition of justice as “the advantage of the stronger” (or superior) (1.338c). Reason is the “strongest” (that is, best) element; the advantage that it pursues is for the benefit of the entire soul.

12 (9.582d) His experience, then, will enable him to judge better than anyone?: Socrates’ contention that the philosopher is the best judge of the relative merits of all pleasures may merit more scrutiny than Glaucon gives. It is consistent, nonetheless, with the presumptions about the philosopher’s competence that have been made throughout Republic. Compare also 9.577b, where Socrates and Glaucon assume that they are “able and experienced judges.”

13 (9.583b) Twice in succession, then, has the just man overthrown the unjust in this conflict: The metaphor is from wrestling (compare 8.544b). To win a match, the victor had to throw and pin his opponent three times.

14 (9.584e) Then can you wonder that persons who are inexperienced in the truth, as they have wrong ideas about many other things, should also have wrong ideas about pleasure and pain and the intermediate state[?]: The “un-philosophic” nature of most people has already been asserted at 6.494a, and the commonplace yet problematic identification of pleasure with “the good” is discussed at 6.505c; see also note 2 on 3.391a. This passage’s analysis of pleasure and pain as “motions” of the soul (9.583e) is ultimately aimed at discrediting the common identification of pleasure with bodily and emotional gratification. On Socrates’ argument, the apparent “pleasures” of eating, drinking, etc., are merely cessations of pain (that is, hunger, thirst, etc.) and are thus “states of rest” that, by definition, are not truly pleasant (9.583e). Moreover, the distinctions made by means of the divided line between phenomenal objects, which have a low “degree of truth” insofar as they are impermanent and subject to change, and intellectual objects that are permanent and unchanging (6.510a), permit Socrates to argue here that food, drink, and other “substances” provide satisfaction only in temporary and incomplete ways, since they are not in contact with “pure being,” whereas the substance of philosophical contemplation, “which is concerned with the invariable, the immortal” (9.585b-c), is able to supply something akin to genuine pleasure (9.587b). Compare Gorgias 491e-497a.

15 (9.586a) Like cattle, with their eyes always looking down and their heads stooping to the earth, that is, to the dining-table, they fatten and feed and breed: This powerful (and powerfully unflattering) image of the behavior of most people, who conduct themselves like animals, anticipates Socrates’ identification of justice as the aretê that humanizes human beings (9.588e-589c).

16 (9.586c) as Stesichorus says that the Greeks fought about the shadow of Helen at Troy, in ignorance of the truth: The lyric poet Stesichorus (sixth century B.c.E.) composed a poem, often called his “palinode,” in which he asserted that the gods sent a phantom image of Helen to Troy, while Helen herself went to Egypt. Plato has Socrates quote the opening lines of the palinode at Phaedrus 243a-b.

17 (9.586d-e) Then may we not confidently assert that the lovers of money and honor, when they seek their pleasures under the guidance ... of reason and knowledge... will also have the truest pleasures in the highest degree which is attainable to them ... ?: Socrates’ statement seems to suggest that non-philosophers can, within limits, achieve some pleasure and satisfaction in life. His argument concerning justice as a whole, however, raises fascinating questions about whether he would admit that non-philosophers are truly capable of being “just” and therefore happy. Compare, for example, 10.619c-d.

18 (9.587c) and the measure of his inferiority can only be expressed in a figure: As in the calculation at 8.546b-c of the number governing human births, there may be Pythagorean influences in this geometric expression of the distance between the philosopher’s happiness and the tyrant’s misery. The figure ultimately arrived at is a square-sided cube of 729 units that symbolizes the completeness of the philosopher’s happiness on two levels; first, it is the cube of the square of 3. (See note 11 on 9.580c for the significance of the number 3 in Republic). Since, as Jowett notes, it is also (nearly) the number of days and nights in a year, it suggests that the philosopher has more pleasure than the tyrant every day and every night of every year.

19 (9.588b) Let us make an image of the soul, that he may have his own words presented before his eyes: By envisioning the soul as a composite creature, part human but mostly animal, Socrates develops another powerful image that enables him to discredit injustice’s claim to conferring benefit. On the bestializing effect of injustice (9.588e-589c), see also 9.571c.

20 (9.589c) Come, now, and let us gently reason with the unjust, who is not intentionally in error: For the Socratic “maxim” that no one does wrong willingly, see 2.360c, 2.366c, and 3.413a; also 1.336e.

21 (9.589e) Who can imagine that a man who sold his son or daughter into slavery for money ... would be the gainer, however large might be the sum which he received?: Children, especially sons, represented continuity for the family; to sell one’s children into slavery constituted a violation of kinship ties and was also tantamount to destroying one’s family. Socrates’ analogy comparing the person who marginalizes his or her rational element to one who sells his children into slavery highlights how such marginalization leads only to short-term, inconsequential “gains” and long-term, permanent damage.

22 (9.590c) And why are mean employments and manual arts a reproach?: See note 14 on 2.371c.

23 (9.591a-b) What shall he profit, if his unjustice be undetected and unpunished ? He who is undetected only gets worse: Socrates makes an almost identical point in Gorgias 473b-479e.

Book 10

1 (10.595a-b) To the rejection of imitative poetry, which certainly ought not be received; as I see far more clearly now that the parts of the soul have been distinguished: As Socrates eventually argues (10.602c-606d), poetic mimesis appeals to and strengthens the appetitive part of the soul; it “feeds and waters the passions instead of drying them up; [and] lets them rule, although they ought to be controlled” ( 10.606d). In addition, poetic mimesis and all other forms of imitation strengthen the faculty of eikasia, which the divided line distinguishes as the least important cognitive faculty (6.509d-511e). Poetry is thus the opposite of the mathematical disciplines discussed at length in book 7, which strengthen the soul’s rational element by drawing “the mind to the contemplation of true being” (7.525a) and spurring the development of the faculties of dianoia and, ultimately, noesis. This analysis of poetry’s deleterious psychological effects, which complements what has already been asserted in books 2 and 3 about the problematic behavioral models provided in poetic texts such as Iliad, is preceded by two examinations of its distance from “the truth.” The first examination relies upon the divided line’s distinctions among objects of perception (10.596a-598d). Imitators such as painters and poets, who create reflections of phenomenal objects that are themselves mere “copies” of intelligible objects, work with no knowledge of or concern for “what is” and therefore impart no useful information (10.598b-e). Their work as creators of objects in the least significant segment of the divided line is contrasted with the work of real craftsmen, who create phenomenal objects such as beds and tables, and with the work of the maker of the ideas, who is simply identified as god (theos) in 10.597b-d, and they are ultimately characterized as ignorant men who appeal to others who are equally ignorant (10.601a-b). The second examination contrasts the knowledge that an imitator has of a given object with that of its user and its maker (10.601b-602c). It reaches the same conclusions as the first: that is, that imitators such as poets have no useful information to impart, and that their imitations are three times removed from what is true and real (10.602b; compare 10.597e). In the first examination particularly, Socrates uses the visual medium of painting to criticize the “truth-value” of poetry, and he rather crudely exploits the obvious differences between a bed in a painting and a bed that one actually sleeps on to suggest that artistic imitations are generally not “useful.” However we may judge his arguments, his narrowly utilitarian criteria put him in a position to challenge long-standing assumptions about the ethical value of poetic texts such as Iliad and Odyssey and, as well, reverential conceptions of Homer and his fellow poets as knowledgeable teachers of “virtue” (10.598d-601b). Book 10’s critique of poetry, then, takes readers back not only to the arguments for censorship in books 2 and 3, but also to the very beginning of book 1, where Polemarchus cites the poet Simonides as an authority on justice (1.331d).

2 (10.595c) for he is the great captain and teacher of the whole of that charming tragic company: The conception of Homer as a “tragedian,” reiterated below at 10.598d, 10.605c, and 10.607a, is novel but it is anticipated by the discussion of the different forms of poetic mimesis (that is, simple narration, direct imitation, and the mixture of narration and direct imitation) at 3.392d. Epic poems fall into the “mixed” category because they directly present speeches by figures such as Achilles and Agamemnon, and thus they can be considered kindred to tragedy, which is purely imitative. Socrates’ characterization of Homer as a tragedian may also be intended to draw attention to the general influence of epic poetry on Athenian drama in the classical period.

3 (10.595c) Can you tell me what imitation is? for I really do not know: Socrates’ disavowal of knowledge about the nature of “imitation” is noteworthy, given the detailed discussion of poetic mimesis in book 3. Nonetheless, it is consistent with his cautious professions of ignorance about the idea of the good and dialectic in books 6 and 7, and it is perhaps well motivated at this moment, since the theory of the ideas is about to become the basis for his argument against poetry’s ability to convey useful, “truthful” information.

4 (10.596b) But there are only two ideas or forms of them—one the idea of a bed, the other of a table: If all phenomenal objects owe their existence in the world of “becoming” to their “participation” in the ideas, which exist in the world of “being,” the positing of “ideas” of “bed” and “table” makes sense, and it plainly suits Socrates’ purposes at this point. It is debatable, however, whether Plato would have considered these ideas worthy of extended investigation, especially when compared with such ideas as those of justice, moderation, courage, and beauty, as well as the idea of the good.

5 ( 10.597a) At any rate, he replied, philosophers would say that he was not speaking the truth: Literally, “he would not seem [to say true things] to those who occupy themselves with arguments such as these.” Socrates apparently means that people who investigate “being” (that is, philosophers) would not admit that a physical bed made by a craftsman “exists,” since it is only part of the world of “becoming.”

6 (10.597e) And the tragic poet is an imitator, and, therefore, like all other imitators, he is thrice removed from the king and from the truth?: As at 9.587c-d, Socrates counts inclusively. “The king” in this sentence is god, the maker of the ideal bed. Compare 6.509d, where the idea of the good is said to be a “ruling power” (literally, “to be king”) over the realm of intelligible objects. Despite this coincidence in language, it is not safe to assume that the idea of the good is identifiable with “god.”

7 (10.598d-e) And so, when we hear persons saying that the tragedians, and Homer ... know all the arts and all things human, virtue as well as vice... we ought to consider whether here also there may not be a similar illusion: Such knowledge of “all things human” is, in effect, what Polemarchus claims for Simonides at 1.331d. Compare Adeimantus’ liberal quotations from poetry at 2.363a-366a, and the purported claims of the “eulogists of Homer” at 10.606e.

8 (10.599b) Then ... we must put a question to Homer: The point that poets have no true knowledge of their subject matter is made, in somewhat different terms, in Ion 533e-535a, where Socrates suggests to the rhapsode Ion that divine inspiration, and not expert knowledge (technê), is what enables artists like Homer to create poetry.

9 (10.600a) But, if Homer never did any public service, was he privately a guide or teacher of any?: In Gorgias 515a-b, Socrates poses an analogous question to the ambitious politician Callicles.

10 (10.600b) Creophylus, the companion of Homer : Some sources call Creophylus Homer’s hetairos (that is, “friend,” “companion,” also “disciple”), while others claim that he was a son-in-law. The name Creophylus “makes us laugh” because, as it is apparently derived from the words for “meat” (kreas) and “race” or “tribe” (phylon), it can be interpreted as meaning something like “made from meat” (hence Jowett’s interpolation, “that child of flesh”). The story about Creophylus’ disregard for Homer does not appear in other sources.

11 (10.600c) can you imagine... that he would not have had many followers, and been honored and loved by them?: In Gorgias 519c-d, Socrates similarly asserts that, if students mistreat their instructor (that is, a Sophist or rhetorician like Gorgias), the fault lies with the instructor and exposes his failure as an educator.

12 (10.600c) Protagoras of Abdera and Prodicus of Ceos: Protagoras, from Abdera in Thrace, was one of the most prominent and successful “sophists” in Athens in the mid-fifth century B.C.E. See note 2 on 5.449d for the educational claim that Plato puts in Protagoras’ mouth in Protagoras 318e-319a. If the “dramatic date” of Republic is meant to be 411 or 410 B.C.E., the reference to Protagoras in the present tense would be anachronistic. Prodicus, from the island Ceos, was another prominent and successful Sophist who was active in Athens during Socrates’ lifetime; in Protagoras, he and Protagoras are represented as staying in the home of the wealthy Athenian Callias.

13 (10.601c) only the horseman who knows how to use them—he knows their right form: The superior “knowledge” attributed in this passage to the per-Ison who uses a given object is not to be confused with the philosopher’s knowledge (epistemê) of the ideas.

14 (10.602b) Imitation is only a kind of play or sport; Compare Phaedrus 274c-278e; also Laws 3.685a, 4.712b, and 7.817a-d; Republic 7.536b-c. As these and other passages suggest, Plato would have readily acknowledged that his own dialogues, qua “imitations,” are in the final analysis “play,” albeit an especially constructive type of “play.”

15 ( 10.602d) And the arts of measuring and numbering and weighing come to the rescue of the human understanding ... and the apparent greater or less... give way before calculation and measure and weight?: Compare 7.522c-526c, especially 7.522e-524d.

16 (10.604e) And does not... the rebellious principle ... furnish a great variety of materials for imitation? Whereas the wise and calm temperament ... is not easy to imitate or to appreciate when imitated, especially... when a promiscuous crowd is assembled in a theatre.... : This concession that the sober behavior of upright, self-restrained figures does not make for “good theater” figures into a broad critique of the dynamics of public performance, whether in theatrical competitions or political assemblies or law courts, that takes shape in several Platonic dialogues. Gorgias 501d-511a, for example, highlights how dramatists and politicians alike, as they compete for public favor, are obliged to “flatter” their audiences and cater to their tastes; compare what Socrates says about sophists in Republic 6.493a-d. Plato’s dialogues themselves, we might imagine, offer alternatives to the unwholesome yet exciting exhibitions on the tragic stage, and they arguably live up to the standards Socrates establishes in this passage for imitations of “the wise and calm temperament.” Yet they were hardly intended for popular consumption by the “promiscuous crowd” and would thus bear out Socrates’ point that the “imitative poet who aims at being popular” is bound to prefer the easily imitated “passionate and fitful temper.”

17 ( 10.605c-d) the best of us... delight in giving way to sympathy, and are in raptures at the excellence of the poet who stirs our feelings most: Socrates’ acknowledgment of the powerful appeal of “moving” passages in poetry resonates with his repeated professions of affection for Homer, and also looks ahead to his conclusion that “hymns to the gods and praises of famous men are the only poetry which ought to be admitted into our State” ( 10.607a). This is a far stricter provision for “censorship” than what was argued for, vis-à-vis the education of children in the guardian classes, in books 2 and 3, and reflects the emerging concern in Republic’s later books that adults, even when intelligent and well disciplined, can readily become “childish.”

18 (10.607a) For if you go beyond this and allow the honeyed muse to enter, either in epic or lyric verse, not law and the reason of mankind, which by common consent have ever been deemed best, but pleasure and pain will be the rulers in our State : See note 2 on 3.391a and note 6 on 9.577a; also 6.505c.

19 (10.607b) let us tell her that there is an ancient quarrel between philosophy and poetry; of which there are many proofs: As far back as the archaic period, individuals such as Xenophanes criticized the representations of the gods in Homer. These men were themselves poets, but it is perhaps fair to identify in their works the beginnings of a “quarrel” between poetry and philosophy. On the other hand, it may be wise to take Socrates’ claim about the antiquity of the quarrel with a few grains of salt—since Xenophanes and his kind were not “philosophers” according to the standards developed in books 6 and 7 of Republic—and to construe what is said here as an effort to promote and justify the systematic critique of poetry and its cultural impact that Plato undertakes in his dialogues.

20 ( 10.608b) for great is the issue at stake, greater than appears, whether a man is to be good or bad: Literally, “for great is the contest....” See note 14 on 1.344e.

21 ( 10.608c) And yet no mention has been made of the greatest prizes and rewards which await virtue: The challenge that Glaucon and Adeimantus set up for Socrates in book 2 (culminating at 2.367a-e) was to demonstrate that justice is intrinsically “profitable” and injustice “unprofitable,” regardless of external circumstances such as rewards or penalties. At this point, which marks the beginning of Republic’s final section, Socrates argues that his companions should return to him what was “borrowed in the argument” (10.612c)—that is, the recognition of and rewards given for justice by both human beings and gods, in this life and the next. The consideration of the rewards for justice and penalties for injustice in the hereafter, which are of far longer duration and far greater consequence than what is received while one is alive, motivate the discussion of the soul’s immortality that begins just below.

22 (10.608d) Are you not aware, I said, that the soul of man is immortal and imperishable?: In Phaedo and Phaedrus, Plato has Socrates contend that the soul is immortal, and that the death or destruction of the body does not entail the death or destruction of the soul. Whereas Socrates simply assumes that the soul is immortal in Gorgias 523a-b, he offers explanations, or “proofs,” of its immortality here and also in Phaedo 64a-107d and Phaedrus 245c-246a. The argument made below in 10.608d-611a—that is, that things can be destroyed only by their own particular “evil” (kakon in Greek) and that, since the soul is not destroyed by its evil (that is, injustice), it cannot be destroyed at all and is therefore immortal—differs from what is adduced in Phaedo and Phaedrus, and these differences suggest that Plato did not intend Socrates’ arguments to be construed as offering definitive answers. Rather, the reason-Iing presented here about everything having a particular “evil” seems to hark back to and reinforce the crucial assumptions introduced at 1.352d-354a that each thing, whether living or inanimate, has a single function, and that there is a unique “excellence” that enables this function to be performed well.

23 ( 10.608d) He looked at me in astonishment, and said: No, by heaven: And are you really prepared to maintain this?: The notion that souls (psychai) somehow survived the body and were taken to the underworld (or, in special instances, to the Islands of the Blessed) was widely accepted, and it was central to both the Orphic and Pythagorean systems of belief. Socrates has already introduced the concept of the soul’s reincarnation at 6.498d. What surprises Glaucon at this moment is, perhaps, Socrates’ readiness to make a rational case for the immortality of the soul.

24 (10.611a-b) But this we cannot believe.. any more than we can believe the soul... to be full of variety and difference and dissimilarity: In Phaedo 72b, Plato has Socrates use similar reasoning to establish that the living “come from the dead”—that is, by the process of reincarnation. The contention immediately below that the soul “cannot be compounded of many elements” also corresponds with Phaedo 79d-80b, and the image of the soul as marred by communion with the body and other miseries resembles what Socrates asserts in Phaedo 67a and 82e. For the need to contemplate the soul “in her original purity” (that is, apart from the body), see also Gorgias 524d-525a.

25 (10.612c) Will you repay me, then, what you borrowed in the argument?: See book 2, especially 2.361c and 2.367c-e, as well as note 21 on 10.608c. Socrates’ language may deliberately echo the terms in which he, Cephalus, and Polemarchus initially discussed justice at 1.331a-332c—that is, as the repayment of debts and the giving of what is “due.”

26 (10.613c) And now you must allow me to repeat of the just the blessings which you were attributing to the fortunate unjust: At 2.360e-362c, Glaucon imagines the lot of the “happy” unjust man, who literally gets away with murder, and that of the wrongly tormented “unhappy” just man; here Socrates reverses their situations.

27 (10.614b) I will tell you a tale: Like Republic, Gorgias and Phaedo conclude with tales about the afterlife, which describe the experiences of the soul when separated from the body; in Phaedrus 246a-256e, Socrates presents another, quite lengthy eschatological myth. Like the myth of Er in Republic, these stories describe the rewards received after death by those who have been virtuous in life and, conversely, the punishments of those who have been unjust, but their details and emphases differ considerably. Glaucon prefaces the myth in Republic by claiming that nothing would be “more pleasant” (hedion in Greek—Jowett’s translation of Glaucon’s statement “there are few things which I would more gladly hear” is less than literal). Although the myth’s concerns are very serious, Glaucon’s words suggest that Plato did not mean his readers to take it as literal truth. As with the different arguments for the soul’s existence in Republic and other dialogues, it is worth considering how the details and emphases in this and the other eschatological myths may be determined by the particular concerns of their dialogues.

28 (10.614b) not one of the tales which Odysseus tells to the hero Alcinoüs, yet this, too, is a tale of a hero, Er the son of Armenius, a Pamphylian by birth: Books 9-12 of Odyssey, in which Odysseus tells Alcinoüs, king of the Phaea cians, about his wanderings after the fall of Troy, were traditionally called “the tales to Alcinoüs” (apologoi Alcinou). The phrase rendered by Jowett as “a tale of a hero” (apologon alkimou andros) is plainly meant to be a pun on apologos Alcinou. There has been a good deal of speculation since antiquity on Plato’s source(s) for the story of Er, son of Armenius. Pamphylia was a territory in southern Asia Minor, and the names “Er” and “Armenius” also suggest that the story has an origin in the Near East. Some scholars have also interpreted “Pamphylia” as meaning “from every tribe” (that is, pan + phylon), thus suggesting that Er is a figure universally representative of humanity.

29 (10.616b-c) another day’s journey brought them to the place, and there, in the midst of the light, they saw the ends of the chains of heaven let down from above: It is difficult to determine where exactly Er and his fellow travelers are standing; what kind of place could afford this comprehensive view of the cosmos, in all its enormity? Other elements in the description are equally challenging; how, for example, does the spindle of Necessity hang from the ends of the light shaft that binds heaven and earth together but also turn on Necessity’s knees? There is much scholarly debate over the significance of various details in the description that follows, and it seems wisest to approach the whole picture with a flexible imagination. However its details are construed, the overall purpose of Er’s vision of the light binding the universe together and of the spindle of Necessity is to convey the sense of cosmic order. All that happens in human life, including and especially the judgment of one’s past life and one’s choice of the next life ( 10.617d-620d), occurs in accordance with this order, and thus “justice” is shown to be a fundamental cosmic principle.

There is also disagreement about the sources of inspiration for the cosmic vision revealed to Er. The geocentric conception of the cosmos seems to reflect contemporary astronomical theories, as does the conception of the heavenly bodies, whose movements in the sky are contained (or reflected?) in the eight concentric hemispheres that comprise the whorl of Necessity’s spindle. Several scholars argue that these conceptions reflect Pythagorean speculation, at least in part. At 7.529a-530b, however, Socrates draws a distinction between the true astronomy practiced by philosophers, which is concerned with abstract problems of movement, and the pedestrian concerns of the Pythagoreans and others, who (so Socrates claims) content themselves with studying the motions of mere physical entities. The image of the concentric hemispheres of the heavens presented in the figure of Necessity’s whorl is plainly an ideal model concerned with elucidating cosmic order in toto, and as such it seems to accord with the aims and goals of what Socrates has defined as “true” astronomy. If the image draws on Pythagorean thinking, it perhaps also offers a critique of and corrective to it. Nonetheless, the placement of the image within a myth that has been characterized as “pleasant” (see note 27 on 10.614b) ought make us wary of believing that Plato intended his readers to take its details literally.

30 ( 10.616c) for this light is the belt of heaven, and holds together the circle of the universe: The “line of light, straight as a column” mentioned just above is envisioned as penetrating the center of both the heavens and the earth, which is itself at the center of the heavens. Some scholars interpret the reference to “under-girders of a trireme” to mean that bands of light must also wrap around the outside of the heavens. The term “under-girders” (hypozomata), however, can refer to cables that pass from bow to stern within a ship’s hull and hold it together lengthwise. If these kinds of cables are what Plato had in mind, then it seems likely that we are meant to envision heaven and earth held together by only a single, central shaft of light.

31 (10.616c) the whorl is made partly of steel and also partly of other materials: The whorl of Necessity’s spindle differs from ordinary whorls in that it is perfectly hemispherical and composed of eight hollow hemispheres of different thicknesses and materials and colors, which fit together, one inside the other. Each hemisphere contains or represents—it is not entirely clear which is the more proper conception—a heavenly body and its placement in the heavens, except for the outermost one, which contains or represents “the fixed stars” and so has several heavenly bodies. The “movements” of the heavenly bodies and the appearances of their different rates of speed are accounted for by the rotations (at different speeds) of the hemispheres, which are counter to the rotation of the spindle as a whole.

32 (10.617b) a siren, who goes round with them, hymning a single tone or note: The notion of “astral music” is clearly Pythagorean; compare 7.530d, where the studies of astronomy and harmonics are said, following the Pythagoreans, to be “sister sciences.”

33 (10.617b) The eight together form one harmony: Harmonia, literally “tuning,” usually refers to notes that are sequentially rather than simultaneously sung or played. Although it may be that the sirens emit their single notes simultaneously, it is perhaps more reasonable to assume that they sing in sequence, and that the notes they emit make up two tetrachords.

34 (10.617e) “the responsibility is with the chooser—God is justified”: The prophet’s pronouncement begins Republic’s final argument for the utility of philosophy. Not only does the person who practices philosophy choose wisely and so become “happy” while he or she is alive on earth, but the ability that he or she gains to “learn and discern between good and evil,” and to determine (literally, “reason out”) which qualities of the soul are better and worse, is the only thing that will enable him or her to choose the next life wisely, “undazzled by the desire of wealth or the other allurements of evil ...” (10.618b-619b). Without philosophy, one lacks the reasoning ability (logos) to make the best decisions, as is borne out by the example of the man whose aretê in his former life “was a matter of habit only,” and who has no logos to keep him from choosing the greatest tyranny as his next life (10.619b-d). So, too, it is only the saving grace of philosophic logos that keeps souls from drinking too much from the river of Unmindfulness (10.621a). The fact that the myth is offered as a fanciful and “pleasant” construction does not detract from the overall seriousness and significance of what it conveys. This passage, which accentuates the responsibility that individuals have for shaping their lives, is very much in keeping with the major concerns of Republic. That there is a lottery determining the order in which one may choose one’s future life is a concession to the fact that control over circumstances is not complete; nonetheless, as the prophet insists, “Even for the last comer, if he chooses wisely ... there is appointed a happy and not undesirable existence” (10.619b).

35 ( 10.621c) And it shall be well with us both in this life and in the pilgrimage of a thousand years which we have been describing: Literally rendered, the last words of Republic are, “and as we receive the rewards of justice, just like victors in games collecting prizes, both here and in the thousand-year journey that we have described, let us do well.” The phrase “let us do well” (eu prattômen) is in the subjunctive mood and is therefore hortatory, not declar ative. In Greek the expression “to do well” has some of the same ambiguities that it can have in English, since it means both “to act well” and “to do good things,” and also “to fare well.” Eu prattômen is a favorite phrase of salutation and farewell in the letters attributed to Plato, and it may reflect his personal usage. They are fitting closing words for Republic, which has been concerned all along with “doing” and “faring” well.

INSPIRED BY PLATO AND REPUBLIC

“The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.” Alfred North Whitehead’s wry assessment of Plato’s importance to the philosophical tradition of Europe is something of an exaggeration. Yet it is not wholly inaccurate. Beginning with Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.), who spent twenty years as Plato’s student at the Academy, virtually all philosophers and philosophical schools active in lands exposed to Hellenic culture owe significant debts of inspiration to Plato. As is abundantly evident from Aristotle’s extant works, the efforts of later philosophers to respond to key Platonic texts such as Republic have necessarily entailed the interpretation and transformation and (at times) misrepresentation of Plato’s thought. Thus, as we consider the legacy of Plato both in and beyond the field of philosophy, we will do well to keep in mind that, at times, the relationship between what Plato may have intended to convey and what he inspired can be tenuous.

Aristotle expected his readers and students to be familiar with the Platonic dialogues, and it is fair to say that some of his best-known works—Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, Poetics, and Metaphysics-are fundamentally “inspired by” Republic, insofar as they seek to refine and (in places) contest what Plato has Socrates suggest about the relationship between moral excellence and happiness in the individual, the proper organization of a functional political community, the need to censor poetry (especially tragedy), and the theory of the “ideas.” The Academy ceased to be the chief institution for the study and transmission of Plato’s thought in the third century B.C.E., but, by this time, Plato’s works were widely read in the Hellenic world, and they became popular in the elite philhellenic circles of Roman society during the second and first centuries B.C.E. The Roman politician, orator, and philosopher Marcus Tullius Cicero (106-43 B.C.E.) was profoundly influenced by Plato, and he modeled several of his philosophical treatises on Platonic dialogues, including his De republica (On the Commonwealth), which was intended as a Romanized version of Republic. A few centuries later Plotinus (205-270 C.E.), after settling in Rome to teach philosophy, developed a comprehensive system of philosophical thought and religious belief that was founded on key concepts derived from Plato’s works—most notably, the idea of the good in books 6-7 of Republic-which Plotinus identified with “the One.” This system came to be known as “Platonism,” or “NeoPlatonism”; its principal tenets are expounded in six collections of Plotinus’ writings, which Plotinus’ student Porphyry (c.234-c.305 C.E.) published at the beginning of the fourth century, and which came to be called Enneads. It is through Enneads and the writings of Porphyry that Saint Augustine (354-430 C.E.) was exposed to Platonism, ensuring that Plato’s thought had a lasting (albeit indirect) influence upon the philosophical direction of Christianity for the next thousand years. In 529 C.E., on the order of the emperor Justinian, the Academy (along with all other philosophical schools in Athens) was forced to close. Before this happened, the Neo-Platonist philosopher Proclus (c.410-485) brought the study of Plato back to the Academy. Proclus served as the Academy’s head for several years and wrote commentaries on Republic, Timaeus, and Parmenides, which are still extant today.

The writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas (c.1225-1274), particularly the Summa Theologica (1266-1273), established Aristotle as the most important ancient philosopher in the late Middle Ages and early Renaissance. “Platonism,” however, enjoyed a second flowering in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries thanks to the efforts of the Florentine scholar Marsilio Ficino (1433-1499), whose effort to forge a fresh integration of Platonic thought and Christianity—an effort that found its most complete expression in Platonic Theology (1482)—was deeply influenced by Plotinus and Proclus. By the end of the sixteenth century, literate people in Europe had access to printed texts of Plato’s dialogues, both in Greek and in translations into various modem languages. It is accordingly no surprise to find that, during the modern period, Plato’s words and thoughts have been quoted and referred to—and reaffirmed and disputed and praised and condemned—by numerous important philosophers in Europe and Great Britain: among them, Michel de Montaigne (1533-1592), François Marie Arouet (“Voltaire,” 1694-1778), Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768-1834), Georg Hegel ( 1770-1831 ), John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900), Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), and Karl Popper (1902-1994). Meriting special mention here is the famous group of “Cambridge Platonists,” led by Benjamin Whichcote (1609-1683), who sought at the beginning of the scientific age—in a particularly difficult period of British history—to reconcile Christian beliefs with the Platonic conception of a rationally ordered universe.

The practical influence of Republic is more difficult to gauge than its impact on the theorizing of later thinkers. Nonetheless, over the centuries, individuals have discovered in Plato’s works the inspiration for undertaking political or social or educational reform. The following two examples are illustrative. First, as is discussed in the introduction, Plato and his friend Dion (c.408-354 B.C.E.) evidently planned to educate the young Dionysius II of Syracuse in the hopes that, upon succeeding his father as the city’s ruler, he would put into practice the political ideals they cherished, which may have been something like the proposals for the ideal state and the government of philosopher-rulers that Plato has Socrates advance in Republic. More recently—and more modestly—Benjamin Jowett (1818-1893), the translator of this edition of Republic, placed Plato’s dialogues at the center of the humanities curriculum as part of his program of educational reform at Oxford University. It is interesting to note that Jowett seems to have met with more success than Dion. Whereas Dion was eventually assassinated for his zealous efforts to bring political and social reform to Syracuse and other Greek cities on Sicily, Jowett’s Plato-inspired campaign helped modernize Oxford and transform it into one of the world’s leading educational institutions.

Lastly, we may note that Republic has inspired not only much ex pository analysis, but also countless creative presentations, literary and otherwise. Many depictions of both utopian societies and their dystopian counterparts, ranging from Thomas More’s Utopia (1516) to Jonathan Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels (1726) to Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World (1932) to George Orwell’s 1984 (1949), have their roots in the ideal city brought to life by Socrates, Glaucon, and Adeimantus. Contemporary films such as Gattaca (1997) and The Matrix (1999) may not owe direct inspiration to Republic, but they participate in a long tradition of artistic works that ultimately trace their concerns back to the political, social, and metaphysical issues raised in Republic. Robert Pirsig’s Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance (1974) represents a different type of inventively constructed narrative that looks critically at the formulations of Platonic philosophy and the influence that Plato has had on subsequent ages.

 

The field of philosophy has greatly changed since Plato began to teach near the shrine of Academus on the outskirts of Athens. It has evolved into a complex and sophisticated discipline that deals with issues and problems that Plato and his contemporaries would have been unable to conceive of, much less address. Nonetheless, as Alfred North Whitehead has suggested, the philosophical studies pursued today in Europe, Britain, and the United States are (still) deeply indebted to Plato. Most basically, Plato seems to deserve much credit for establishing that it is appropriate and meaningful for “philosophers”—in the name of the “love of wisdom” (philosophia)—to pursue a variety of interests, from ethics to political theory to metaphysics to epistemology to theology to logic, and to discover for themselves the modes of expression that best permit them to convey their ideas.

COMMENTS & QUESTIONS

In this section, we aim to provide the reader with an array of perspectives on the text, as well as questions which challenge those perspectives. The commentary has been culled from sources as diverse as reviews contemporaneous with the work, letters written by the author, literary criticism of later generations, and appreciations written throughout the work’s history. Following the commentary, a series of questions seeks to filter Plato’s Republic through a variety of voices and bring about a richer understanding of this enduring work.

Comments

ARISTOTLE (384-322 B.C.E.)

The members of a state must either have (1) all things or (2) nothing in common, or (3) some things in common and some not. That they should have nothing in common is clearly impossible, for the constitution is a community, and must at any rate have a common place—one city will be in one place, and the citizens are those who share in that one city. But should a well-ordered state have all things, as far as may be, in common, or some only and not others? For the citizens might conceivably have wives and children and property in common, as Socrates proposes in the Republic of Plato. Which is better, our present condition, or the proposed new order of society?

There are many difficulties in the community of women. And the principle on which Socrates rests the necessity of such an institution evidently is not established by his arguments....

We ought to reckon, not only the evils from which the citizens will be saved, but also the advantages which they will lose. The life which they are to lead appears quite impracticable. The error of Socrates must be attributed to the false notion of unity from which he starts. Unity there should be, both of the family and of the state, but in some respects only. For there is a point at which a state may attain such a degree of unity as to be no longer a state, or at which, without actually ceasing to exist, it will become an inferior state.

—from book II, 1260b27-61a12, and 1263b29-34 in Politics,
translated by Benjamin Jowett, Oxford: Clarendon Press (1905)

 

PLUTARCH (C.50-120 C.E.)

It is unlikely that either the Romans or the Greeks will find fault with the Academy, since in this book, which presents the Lives of Dion and Brutus, each nation receives very similar treatment. Dion was a disciple of Plato who knew the philosopher personally, while Brutus was nurtured on his doctrines, so that both men were trained in the same wrestling school, one might say, to take part in the struggle for supreme power. There is a remarkable similarity in many of their actions, and so we should not be surprised that they often illustrate a particular conviction of their teacher of virtue, namely that power and good fortune must be accompanied by wisdom and justice if a man’s political actions are to be seen as noble as well as great.

—from “Dion,” chapter 1, in The Age of Alexander :
Nine Greek Lives by Plutarch,
translated by Ian Scott-Kilvert, Harmondsworth, UK:
Penguin Books, 1973

 

DESIDERIUS ERASMUS (C.1466-1536)

Surely you don’t believe that there is any difference between those who sit in Plato’s cave gazing in wonder at the images and likenesses of various things—as long as they desire nothing more and are no less pleased—and that wiseman who left the cave and sees things as they really are?

—from The Praise of Folly (1509),
translated by Clarence H. Miller, New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1979

 

GEORG WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL (1770-1831)

Plato’s Republic, which passes proverbially as an empty ideal, is in essence nothing but an interpretation of the nature of Greek ethical life. Plato was conscious that there was breaking into that life in his own time a deeper principle which could appear in it directly only as a longing still unsatisfied, and so only as something corruptive. To combat it, he needs must have sought aid from that very longing itself. But this aid had to come from on High and all that Plato could do was to seek it in the first place in a particular external form of that same Greek ethical life. By that means he thought to master this corruptive invader, and thereby he did fatal injury to the deeper impulse which underlay it, namely free infinite personality. Still, his genius is proved by the fact that the principle on which the distinctive character of his Idea of the state turns is precisely the pivot on which the impending world revolution turned at that time.

—from the preface to Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (1821),
translated by T. M. Knox,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1942

 

FRIEDRICH VON SCHLEGEL (1772-1829)

Plato’s philosophy is a dignified preface to future religion.

—from “Selected Ideas,” in Dialogue on Poetry and
Literary Aphorisms (1797-1800),
translated by Ernst Behler and Roman Struc,
University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1968

 

RALPH WALDO EMERSON (1803-1882)

Out of Plato come all things that are still written and debated among men of thought. Great havoc makes he among our original ities. We have reached the mountain from which all these boulders were detached. The Bible of the learned for twenty-two hundred years, every brisk young man who says in succession fine things to each reluctant generation,—Boethius, Rabelais, Erasmus, Bruno, Locke, Rousseau, Alfieri, Coleridge,—is some reader of Plato, translating into the vernacular, wittily, his best things. Even the men of grander proportion suffer some deduction from the misfortune (shall I say?) of coming after this exhausting generalizer. St. Augustine, Copernicus, Newton, Behmen, Swedenborg, Goethe, are likewise his debtors and must say after him. For it is fair to credit the broadest generalizer with all the particulars deducible from his thesis. Plato is philosophy, and philosophy, Plato.

—from “Plato; or The Philosopher,”
in Representative Men (1850),
J. M. Dent & Sons, 1908

 

SØREN KIERKEGAARD (1813-1855)

What Socrates really meant by wanting to have “the poets” expelled from the state was that by writing in the medium of the imagination instead of precipitating men into ethical realization in actuality, the poets spoiled them and weaned them or kept them from it. One could be tempted by and large to make the same charge against “pastors” today. Yes, compared to Socrates Plato himself is a misunderstanding. Only Socrates managed to hold his uncompromising position of continually expressing the existential, constantly remaining in the present—thus he had no doctrine, no system and the like, but had one in action. Plato took his time—with the help of this enormous illusion there came to be a doctrine. By degrees the existential disappeared from view and the doctrine grew dogmatically broader and broader.

—from “Socrates,” vol. 4, entry 4275,
in Søren Kierkegaard’s Journals and Papers,
edited and translated by Howard V Hong and
Edna H. Hong, Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1975

 

KARL MARX (1818-1883)

Plato’s Republic, in so far as division of labour is treated in it, as the formative principle of the State, is merely the Athenian ideal isation of the Egyptian system of castes, Egypt having served as the model of an industrial country to many of his contemporaries also, amongst others to Isocrates, and it continued to have this importance to the Greeks of the Roman Empire.

—from part 4, chapter 14, section 5, in Capital:
A Critique of Political Economy (1867-1894),
translated by Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling and
edited by Frederick Engels,
New York: Modern Library, 1906

 

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE (1844-1900)

It was modesty that in Greece coined the word “philosopher” and left the extraordinary insolence of calling oneself wise to the actors of the spirit—the modesty of such monsters of pride and conceit as Pythagoras, as Plato.

—from book 5, number 351, in The Gay Science (1882),
edited by Bernard Williams and
translated by Josefine Nauckhoff, Cambridge and
New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001

 

RICHARD GARNETT (1835-1906)

In estimating the Republic’s place in the history of thought we must take into account the circumstances under which it was composed. The exact date is uncertain, but whether it existed in the form of a book by 393 B.C. or not, its ideals certainly then existed in Plato’s mind and were known to his fellow-citizens, for the community of goods and the community of women are ridiculed in the Ecclesiazusae of Aristophanes, acted in that year. As a young man Plato had passed through terrible experiences, the complete shipwreck of the vessel of State by the disastrous termination of the Peloponnesian War, the atrocities of the oligarchical party who thereupon gained dominion in Athens, and the unjust execution of his own adored master by an ignorant and misguided democracy. Such events were well calculated to engender in Plato’s mind a distrust of all existing political systems, and to set him upon seriously projecting something to replace them. Ever since, the creation of ideal communities has been the frequent amusement of superior minds, and although every such endeavour has but strengthened the conviction that, as a matter of fact, the development of society must proceed upon the lines marked out for it from the beginning, in these, nevertheless, the aspiration after something is no unimportant factor. The winged genius which in ancient works of art accompanies the chariot of hero or demi-god adds nothing to the power or the speed, but stimulates the ardour of the charioteer.

Too bright and good
For human nature’s daily food

Plato is broadly distinguished from his successors, More, Campanella, Bacon, Brockden Brown, etc., and his later self in his Critias, in this respect, that whereas these represent their ideal communities as already existing and only needing to be described, his Republic exists merely in thought, and not even there until it has been provided with a sound basis by a preliminary discussion of the abstract principles of justice. “Nothing actually existing in the world,” says [translator Benjamin] Jowett, “at all resembles Plato’s ideal State, nor does he himself imagine that such a state is possible.”

—from‘Tlatos ‘Republic,’ “ in Modern English Essays, vol. 2,
London and Toronto: J. M. Dent and Sons, 1922

 

T. HERBERT WARREN (1853-1930)

The Republic [is] the greatest of Plato’s dialogues, because it is the most Platonic, because it exhibits best the peculiar merit of Plato, adequacy of style to subject, of manner to matter; because, while the matter is profoundly difficult and varied, the artistic handling, both as a whole and in detail, does not sink under this difficulty and variety, is not overlaid or embarrassed by it, but rises to it, is equal to it, and expresses and conveys it with the grace and ease of complete mastery.

The matter of the Republic is great. Its scope is nothing less than the whole of life and its surroundings in the world, aye, and in the other, beginning before the cradle, and extending beyond the grave.

How, placed as we are, shall we live best? How are we to make the best of one or of both worlds? What is right to do? What is the most perfect state of human society and life we can imagine if our dreams could come true?

This, under its many forms, and with all that it involves, is the grand question that is asked in the Republic as a practical question, and answered as a practical question, or if partly in dreaming, then with such dreams as are the inspiration of waking moments, when

“Tasks in hours of insight willed
Can be through hours of gloom fulfilled.”

For this is the secret of Plato, that he is a dreamer, but a dreamer who is also a man of the world who has known men and cities, kings and councils, and peoples.

—from his introduction to Republic,
London: Macmillan, 1888

ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD (1861-1947)

The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.

—from part 2, chapter 1, section 1,
in Process and Reality, New York:
Macmillan, 1929

 

WILLIAM BUTLER YEATS (1865-1939)

It is terrible to desire and not possess, and terrible to possess and not desire. Because of these we long for an age which has that unity which Plato somewhere defined as sorrowing and rejoicing over the same things.

—from a letter to Olivia Shakespear (May 25, 1933),
in Collected Letters of William Butler Yeats,
vol. 3 edited by John Kelly,
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997

 

ERICH KAHLER (1885-1970)

Plato’s was essentially a dualistic theory. To him, the divine ideas, the universals, the general qualities, the genera, were the only real beings, that, like the deities, had an absolute, independent existence. God himself was the supreme idea. The man, the animal, the beautiful, the good, the brave, and so on, represented realities, the archetypes of life of which the individuals, the earthly forms of those general qualities, as they appeared in daily life, were mere shadows and faint replicas.

—from “Reason and Science,”
in Man the Measure: A New Approach to History,
New York: Pantheon Books, 1943

 

HANNAH ARENDT (1906-1975)

Our tradition of political thought had its definite beginning in the teachings of Plato and Aristotle. I believe it came to a no less definite end in the theories of Karl Marx.

—from “Tradition and the Modern Age,”
in Between Past and Future,
New York: Penguin Books, 1954

Questions

1. What perspectives on justice and its relationship to happiness emerge from Republic? Do you think that Socrates and his companions make a convincing case for understanding justice as something that is concerned “not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man” (4.443c-d)? How would you respond to the claim that the just man is someone who “does not permit the several elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the work of others” and who “sets in order his own inner life” (4.443d)?
2. Are you convinced that justice, as Socrates and his companions define it, is something intrinsically valuable? Are you convinced that the just man can be “happy” even if he does not enjoy a reputation for justice, nor any other material benefit?
3. Have Socrates and his companions persuaded you that the ideal city-state they describe in Republic is truly the best political community possible? Why or why not? If you are not convinced, how would you respond to their arguments?
4. Do Socrates’ arguments for the censorship of poetry and music still hold water? Is he correct in asserting that “when modes of music change, the fundamental laws of the State always change with them,” and does he seem to have a point in claiming that artistic innovation “is full of danger to the whole State” (4.424c)? Why or why not? If you are not convinced by his arguments for censoring and controlling artistic expression, how would you counter them?
5. Is there anything of value in the critique of democracy that emerges in Republic, especially in 8.555b-558c? How do you respond to Socrates’ estimation that the “democratic constitution” is second only to tyranny in its dysfunction?

FOR FURTHER READING

Editions (with Greek Texts and English Commentaries)

Readers who do not know Greek may find the introductions and commentaries in these editions useful. Those by Halliwell and Murray are accessible and interesting.

 

Adam, James, ed. The Republic of Plato. Second edition. Introduction by D. A. Rees. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963.

Halliwell, Stephen, ed. Plato: Republic 10. Warminster, UK: Aris and Philips, 1988.

. Plato: Republic 5. Warminster, UK: Aris and Philips, 1993.

Jowett, Benjamin, and Lewis Campbell, eds. Plato’s Republic. 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894. Reprinted New York and London: Garland Publishing, 1987.

Murray, Penelope, ed. Plato on Poetry: Ion; Republic 376e-398b9; Republic 595-608b10. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Translations

Bloom, Allan, trans. The Republic of Plato. New York: Basic Books, 1991.

Cooper, John M., trans. Plato: Complete Works. D. S. Hutchinson, associate editor. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997.

Grube, G. M. A., trans. Plato: Republic. Revised by C. D. C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1992. Also in John M. Cooper, trans., Plato: Complete Works (see above), pp. 971-1223.

Lee, Desmond, trans. Plato: The Republic. New York and London: Penguin Books, 2003. Reissue of 1955 edition with updated bibliography.

Shorey, Paul, trans. Plato: Republic. 2 vols. London, New York, and Cambridge, MA: W. Heinemann, G. P. Putnam’s Sons, and Harvard University Press (Loeb Classical Library), 1930-1935.

Interpretative Guides to the Republic

Annas, Julia. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981.

Baracchi, Claudia. Of Myth, Life, and War in Plato’s Republic. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002.

Howland, Jacob. The Republic: The Odyssey of Philosophy. New York: Twayne Publishers, 1993.

Pappas, Nickolas. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Plato and the Republic. Second edition. New York and London: Routledge, 2003.

White, Nicholas. A Companion to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Black-well Press, 1979.

Critical Works on Plato

Annas, Julia, and Christopher Rowe, eds. New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and Ancient. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002.

Blondell, Ruby. The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

Guthrie, W. K. C. A History of Greek Philosophy (Vol. 4: Plato). Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1969.

Hobbs, Angela. Plato and the Hero: Courage, Manliness, and the Impersonal Good. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

Irwin, Terence. Plato’s Ethics. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.

Kahn, Charles H. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Morgan, Kathryn A. Myth and Philosophy from the Pre-Socratics to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

Nails, Debra. Agora, Academy, and the Conduct of Philosophy (Philosophical Studies Series, 63). Dordrecht, Netherlands, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995.

. The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2002.

Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

. “On Wandering and Wondering: Theôria in Greek Philosophy and Culture.” Arion 9.2 (third series; Fall 2001), pp. 23-58.

Philosophy Before Plato

Guthrie, W K. C. A History of Greek Philosophy (Vol. 3: The Sophists and Socrates). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.

Kerferd, G. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

McKirahan, Richard D., Jr. Philosophy Before Socrates: An Introduction with Text and Commentary. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1994.

Background on Greek and Athenian Culture

Davies, J. K. Democracy and Classical Greece. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.

Ober, Josiah. Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998.

Pomeroy, Sarah, and Stanley M. Burstein, Walter Donlan, Jennifer Tolbert Roberts. Ancient Greece: A Political, Social, and Cultural History. Oxford, and New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.

West, M. L. Ancient Greek Music. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992.

INDEX

A

ACADEMY

ACHILLES

ADEIMANTUS

AESCHYLUS

see also DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS; TRAGEDY

AFTERLIFE

AGAMEMNON

AJAX, SON OF TELAMON

ALCIBIADES

ALCINOUS

ALLEGORICAL INTERPRETATIONS (of poetry)

ANACHARSIS,

ANALOGIES (in Republic)

ANAXAGORAS

ANTIPHON

APHRODITE

APOLLO

APORIA, APORETIC [INCONCLUSIVE] DIALOGUES

APPETITES, DESIRES

APPETITIVE PRINCIPLE [ELEMENT] (as distinct from SPIRIT and the RATIONAL ELEMENT in the soul),

see also PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the soul)

APRAGMOSYNÊ

see also DOING ONE’S OWN WORK/MINDING ONE’S OWN BUSINESS; MEDDLESOMENESS

ARCHILOCHUS,

ARES,

ARISTOCRACY [RULE OF THE BEST]

see also IDEAL STATE

ARISTOCRATIC IDEOLOGY AND VALUES (in archaic and classical Greece)

ARISTOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL

see also JUST INDIVIDUAL; JUSTICE; PHILOSOPHER

ARISTON,

ARISTOPHANES

ARISTOTLE

ARITHMETIC [ARITHEMETIKÊ]

ART-see CENSORSHIP; IMITATION; PAINTING; POETRY; TRAGEDY

ARTEMIS,

ARTISANS—see BRONZE/IRON CLASS

ASCLEPIUS, ASCLEPIADAE

see also DOCTORS/PHYSICIANS/ MEDICINE

ASPASIA

ASTRONOMY

ATHENE [ATHENA]

ATHENS, ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

critiques of (in Plato’s dialogues)

development of maritime “empire,”

dissatisfaction with, among upper classes in Athens

ideological assumptions of

see also DEMOCRACY; MEDDLESOMENESS

ATHLETES, ATHLETIC CONTESTS

see also PHYSICAL TRAINING/CARE

AUTOLYCUS,

AUXILIARIES [SILVER CLASS]

see also GUARDIANS; PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the ideal state)

B

BARBARIANS

BEAUTY, THE IDEA OF

see also IDEAS, THE THEORY OF

BECOMING (as intermediate between BEING and NOT-BEING)

see also OPINION

BEING [“THAT WHICH IS”], (as distinct from BECOMING and NOT-BEING)

see also, GOOD, THE IDEA OF; IDEAS, THE THEORY OF; MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS

BENDIS, BENDIDEA

BIAS,

BIRTHS, REGULATION OF (in the ideal State)—see BREEDING

BLESSINGS (from the gods)

BLINDNESS (as metaphor for ignorance)

BREEDING,

BRONZE/IRON CLASS (in the ideal state)

see also PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the ideal state)

C

CALLICLES

CAVE, ALLEGORY OF

CENSORSHIP (of poetry/music in the ideal state)

see also CHILDREN; EDUCATION; GUARDIANS; POETRY

CEPHALUS

CHARMANTIDES

CHILDISHNESS

CHILDREN

of guardians, as observers on military campaigns,

see also BREEDING; CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; FAMILY

CIVIL STRIFE/DISUNITY [STASIS]

in Athens, during the Peloponnesian War

concerns about, in Republic

CLEITOPHON

CLEON

CLOUDS—see ARISTOPHANES

COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

COMEDY

see also ARISTOPHANES; DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS

COMMUNISM (among guardians of ideal state)

see also FAMILY; PRIVATE PROPERTY

CORINTH

COURAGE [ANDREIA]

as essential quality of guardians

as one of the four principal “virtues,”

CRAFTS, CRAFTSMEN—see TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONALS WITH; also BRONZE/IRON CLASS

CRETE,

CRITIAS

CRONUS

D

DAEDALUS

DAMON

DEATH

see also AFTERLIFE; COURAGE; PUNISHMENT

DELIAN LEAGUE

see also ATHENS, ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

DELPHI

see also APOLLO

DEMOCRACY

as degenerate political constitution, xlv-xlvi,

see also ATHENS, ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY

DEMOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL,

DEMOCRITUS

DEMOS [PEOPLE IN A DEMOCRACY] (as the father of the tyrant),

DIALECTIC

DIOMEDE(S)

DIANOIA [“UNDERSTANDING”]

see also COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

DION

DIONYSIUS

DIONYSIUS

DIONYSUS, DIONYSIAN FESTIVALS

see also DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS; TRAGEDY

DIOTIMA

DIVIDED LINE, FIGURE OF—see COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; also CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; SUN, SIMILE OF

DOCTORS/PHYSICIANS/MEDICINE,

affinities between doctors and rulers

proper treatment of the

see also ANALOGIES; TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONALS WITH

DOG, “PHILOSOPHICAL” TEMPERAMENT OF,

DOING ONE’S OWN WORK/MINDING ONE’S OWN BUSINESS

see also APRAGMOSYNÊ ; JUSTICE; MEDDLESOMENESS

DOXA

see also OPINION; PISTIS; EIKASIA

DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS (in Athens)

see also AESCHYLUS, ARISTOPHANES, EURIPIDES, HOMER, SOPHOCLES, TRAGEDY

DREAMS,

DRONES,

E

EDUCATION

traditional, xxiv

of children of the guardians,

of future philosopher-rulers,

see also CHILDREN; CENSORSHIP; PHYSICAL TRAINING; SOPHISTS

EIKASIA [“PERCEPTION OF SHADOWS,” “IMAGINATION”]

see also COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

EMPEDOCLES

END [FUNCTION],

see also DOING ONE’S OWN WORK/MINDING ONE’S OWN BUSINESS; JUSTICE

ENSLAVEMENT (of tyrant and tyrannical individual)

see also FREEDOM; HAPPINESS; JUSTICE; TYRANNICAL INDIVIDUAL; TYRANNY, TYRANT

EPISTEMÊ [KNOWLEDGE]

see also KNOWLEDGE

EPISTEMOLOGY—see COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

ER, MYTH OF

ERISTIC

EROS, EROTIC/SEXUAL DESIRE

see also APPETITES/DESIRES

EURIPIDES

see also DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS; TRAGEDY

EUTHYDEMUS

EXCELLENCE [ARETÊ, VIRTUE]

see also END [FUNCTION]; HAPPINESS; PHILOSOPHER; ARISTOCRACY; ARISTOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL; JUSTICE; COURAGE; TEMPERANCE; WISDOM

F

FALSEHOOD (dangerous, unnecessary)

see also CENSORSHIP; POETRY; TRAGEDY; TRUTHFULNESS

FALSEHOOD (useful, necessary)

FAMILY/FAMILY LIFE

FATES [MOIRAI],

FORMS—see IDEAS, THEORY OF

FREE WILL

FREEDOM

as enjoyed by the philosopher/ just man

as manifest in democracy and in the democratic individual

see also ENSLAVEMENT

G

GEOMETRY

plane,

solid (stereometry)

GIANTS, GIGANTOMACHY

GLAUCON

GLAUCUS,

GNOSIS

see also KNOWLEDGE; DIANOIA; NOESIS

GOD(S)

as worshipped in Greek religion

as represented in poetry

true nature of

as maker of the ideas

see also CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; MUSIC; POETRY

GOLD CLASS (in the ideal state)—see GUARDIANS; RULERS; PHILOSOPHERS; PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the ideal state)

GOOD, IDEA OF THE

GOODS (in life)

GORGIAS

GREEKS (as distinct from barbarians)

GUARDIANS (in the ideal state)

nature/temperament of,

divided into two classes (rulers and auxiliaries)

see also AUXILIARIES; RULERS; BREEDING; EDUCATION; FAMILY; MARRIAGE; NATURAL ABILITY; WOMEN

GYGES

H

HABIT

importance of cultivating good habits in the young,

insufficiency of (for inculcating logos),

HAPPINESS [EUDAIMONIA]

see also PLEONEXIA; PROFIT; JUSTICE; FREEDOM; ENSLAVEMENT

HARMONICS [SCIENCE OF HARMONY]

HARMONIAI [“MODES” IN MUSIC]

HARMONY

among people and in the soul

in music,

HECTOR,

HEALTH (of the soul)

HELEN,

HELLAS, HELLENES—see GREEKS

HELMSMEN/PILOTS (on ships)

see also TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONALS WITH; ANALOGIES

HEPHAESTUS

HERACLES

HERACLITUS

HERE [HERA]

HERODOTUS

HEROES, as represented in poetry

see also CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; MUSIC; POETRY

HESIOD

HIPPIAS

HOMER AND HOMERIC EPICS

Homer as “first” of the tragedians,

HOMOEROTIC RELATIONSHIPS

HONOR, HONORS

see also REWARDS

I

IDEAL MODELS, VALUE OF

IDEAL STATE [KALLIPOLIS], PRINCIPAL FEATURES OF

see also GUARDIANS; RULERS; AUXILIARIES; PHILOSOPHERS; PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] IN THE IDEAL STATE; EDUCATION; BREEDING; FAMILY

IDEAS [IDEAI], THEORY OF

see also GOOD, IDEA OF THE

IGNORANCE [AGNOIA],

ILIAD—see HOMER AND HOMERIC EPICS

IMITATION/MIMESIS

different manners of imitation,

three times removed from what is real

harmful psychological effects of

see also DRAMA; PAINTING; POETRY; GODS; HEROES

IMPIETY, PROSECUTION FOR (in classical Athens)

INCEST—see BREEDING

INFANTICIDE—see BREEDING

INJUSTICE

as leading to profit and happiness

as source of disunity and strife in the state and in the soul

INJUSTICE (continued)

see also JUSTICE; STRIFE/DISUNITY; HAPPINESS; PLEONEXIA; TYRANNICAL INDIVIDUAL; TYRANT, TYRANNY

INNOVATION, PROBLEMS CAUSED BY

INTELLIGENCE—see KNOWLEDGE; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

INTELLIGIBLE objects—see BEING; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; IDEAS, THEORY OF MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS; CAVE, ALLEGORY OF

ISLANDS OF THE BLESSED

ISMENIAS,

ISOCRATES

J

JUDGES (contrasted with doctors)

JUST INDIVIDUAL,

see also ARISTOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL; JUSTICE; PHILOSOPHER

JUSTICE [JUST CONDUCT, RIGHT BEHAVIOR]

traditional and non-traditional conceptions of

in Republic:

problem of defining

method for defining adopted in Republic

definition of, xliv,

as one of the four principal “virtues,”

relationship to personal profit and happiness, xliii-xliv, xlvi,

JUSTICE, CORRECTIVE

in the afterlife

see also PUNISHMENT

K

KATABASIS

KNOWLEDGE (as distinct from OPINION [DOXA] and IGNORANCE [AGNOIA]),

see also BEING; CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; IDEAS, THEORY OF; PHILOSOPHY

L

LABOR, DIVISION OF

see DOING ONE’S OWN WORK/MINDING ONE’S OWN BUSINESS

LAWLESSNESS

fostered by lax education

fostered by premature exposure to philosophy/dialectic,

LEUCIPPUS

LIGHT—see BLINDNESS; CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; SUN, SIMILE OF

LOGOS [REASON, ARGUMENT]

LYSIAS

LYCURGUS,

M

MANLINESS, MASCULINITY

MARRIAGE,

see also FAMILY; BREEDING; WOMEN

MATERIALISM IN GREEK CULTURE (as criticized in Plato’s dialogues)

see also PRIVATE PROPERTY; POVERTY; WEALTH; HONOR, HONORS; PLEASURE

MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS (in relationship to the IDEAS)

see also COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; IDEAS, THEORY OF

MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES (as distinguished from DIALECTIC)—

see also ARITHMETIC, ASTRONOMY, GEOMETRY, HARMONICS

MERCHANTS/TRADESMEN contempt for see also BRONZE/IRON CLASS

MEDDLESOMENESS [POLYPRAGMOSYNÊ]

see also STRIFE/DISUNITY

METAPHYSICS—see BEING; GOOD, THE IDEA OF; IDEAS, THE THEORY OF; PARMENIDES

METICS

METRE/RHYTHM (in poetry),

MOTION, PRINCIPLES OF—see ASTRONOMY

MOUSIKÊ/MUSIC (broadly defined as “cultural cultivation”),

see also CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; IMITATION; POETRY

MUSAEUS,

MUSE(S)

MUSICAL ACCOMPANIMENT, INSTRUMENTS,

MUSICIANS,

see also ANALOGIES; TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONAL WITH

MYSTERIES/MYSTERY CULTS,

Eleusinian

Orphic,

MYTH—see GODS; HEROES; ER, MYTH OF; EDUCATION; POETRY; FALSEHOOD (dangerous, unnecessary)

N

NATURAL ABILITY, NATURE [PHYSIS]

see also DOING ONE’S OWN WORK/MINDING ONE’S OWN BUSINESS

NECESSITY (goddess)

NICERATUS

NOBLE [ROYAL] LIE

see also FALSEHOOD (useful, necessary)

NOESIS [“REASON”]

see also COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF

NOT-BEING (as distinct from BEING and BECOMING),

see also BEING; IDEAS, THEORY OF; KNOWLEDGE

NUMERICAIJGEOMETRICAL FIGURES

comprehending the period of human births,

comprehending the difference between the just individual’s happiness and the tyrant’s misery,

O

ODYSSEUS

ODYSSEY—see HOMER AND THE HOMERIC POEMS

OEDIPUS,

OLD AGE

OLIGARCHICAL INDIVIDUAL

OLIGARCHY [PLUTOCRACY]

OLYMPIC GAMES/VICTORS

OPINION [DOXA] (as intermediate between KNOWLEDGE [EPISTEMÊ, GNOSIS] and IGNORANCE [AGNOIA]),

see also CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; PHENOMENAL/VISIBLE OBJECTS

OPINIONS, COMMONLY HELD

about the tyrant’s happiness

about justice and injustice

about the gods,

about objects that are considered beautiful, good, etc.

about the uselessness and corruption of philosophers

about identifying the good with pleasure

catered to, by sophists, poets, and other prominent men

OPPOSITES (in sense perceptions),

ORPHEUS

ORPHICS/ORPHISM

OVER-LEGISLATION, POINTLESSNESS OF

p

PAINTING

see also IMITATION

PALAMEDES,

PARMENIDES

PATROCLUS

PEIRITHOUS

PEISISTRATUS

PELOPONNESIAN WAR

PERDICCAS,

PERIANDER,

PERICLES

PHENOMENAL/VISIBLE OBJECTS—see BECOMING; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; OPINION

PHILOTHEAMONES [“LOVERS OF SIGHTS”] (as distinguished from philosophers)

see also BECOMING; OPINION

PHILOSOPHERS

definition of,

innate qualities of,

bad reputation of

as rulers of the ideal state,

pleasures of,

happiness of,

see also GUARDIANS; RULERS; JUST INDIVIDUAL; NATURAL ABILITY, NATURE; DIALECTIC

PHILOSOPHY [PHILOSOPHIA]

dangers of premature exposure to,

see also BEING; COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; DIALECTIC; IDEAS, THEORY OF; PHILOSOPHERS

PHOCYLIDES,

PHYSICAL TRAINING/CARE [GYMNASTIKÊ],

PINDAR

PIRAEUS

PISTIS [“FAITH”],

see also COGNITION, FOUR FACULTIES OF; OPINION

PITTACUS,

PLANETS,

PLATO

see also PLATONIC DIALOGUES AND OTHER WORKS; SOCRATES, SOCRATICS; APORIA, APORETIC DIALOGUES

PLATONIC DIALOGUES AND OTHER WORKS

composition and dating of Plato’s works

Apology

Crito

Euthydemus

Euthyphro

Gorgias

Ion

Laches

Laws

Menexenus

Meno

Parmenides

Phaedo

Phaedrus

Philebus

Protagoras

Republic

Seventh Letter

Statesman

Symposium

Timaeus

PLEASURE

see also APPETITES/DESIRES; CHILDISHNESS; DEMOCRACY; OPINIONS, COMMONLY HELD

PLEONEXIA [SELF-AGGRANDIZEMENT]

POETRY AND POETIC TRADITIONS

importance of, in Greek culture

as carrier of basic values

arguments for censorship of

see also CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; GODS; HEROES; HOMER AND HOMERIC EPICS; IMITATION; TRAGEDY

POLITICAL CONSTITUTIONS

degenerate forms of

relationship to individual character

see also ARISTOCRACY; IDEAL STATE; DEMOCRACY; OLIGARCHY; TIMOCRACY; TYRANNY, TYRANT

POLEMARCHUS

POLIS [INDEPENDENT CITY-STATE]

see also ATHENS, ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY; IDEAL STATE, PRINCIPAL FEATURES OF

POLITICAL CLUBS [“BROTHERHOODS”] (in classical Athens)

POLUS

POVERTY,

see also WEALTH; PRIVATE PROPERTY; DRONES

PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS]

three in the ideal state

three in the human soul

correspondence between principles [elements] in the state and in the soul,

PRIVATE PROPERTY

see also WEALTH; POVERTY; IDEAL STATE, PRINCIPAL FEATURES OF; GUARDIANS; STRIFE/DISUNITY; UNITY; PLEONEXIA

PRODICUS

PROFIT [PERSONAL ADVANTAGE, SELF-INTEREST]

see also HAPPINESS; JUSTICE; PHILOSOPHY; PHILOSOPHERS; PLEASURE; PLEONEXIA

PROTAGORAS

PUNISHMENT

see also AFTERLIFE; DEATH; JUSTICE, CORRECTIVE; REWARDS

PYTHAGORAS, PYTHAGOREANS, PYTHAGOREAN SCHOOL

PYTHIA, PYTHIAN ORACLE—see APOLLO; DELPHI

R

RATIONAL PRINCIPLE [ELEMENT], REASON (as distinct from SPIRIT and the APPETITIVE ELEMENT in the soul),

RATIONAL RECKONING-See LOGOS; also DIALECTIC; PHILOSOPHY; PHILOSOPHERS

REINCARNATION,

REWARDS

for rulers,

for guardians,

for being just

for seeming just,

see also AFTERLIFE; ER, MYTH OF; HONOR, HONORS; PLEASURE; PUNISHMENT

RELIGION, RELIGIOUS BELIEFS AND PRACTICES

in Athens and Greece

in the ideal state

RHETORIC [RHETORIKÊ], RHETORICIANS

see also SOPHISTS

ROYAL [KINGLY] CONSTITUTION AND INDIVIDUAL—see ARISTOCRACY; ARISTOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL

RULERS [GOLD CLASS]

see also GUARDIANS; PHILOSOPHER; PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the ideal state); GOOD, IDEA OF

S

SAPPHO

SCIENTIFIC INQUIRY AND SPECULATION (in the archaic and classical periods)

SELECTION

of future guardians,

of future philosophers,

see also EDUCATION; NATURAL ABILITY, NATURE

SEXUAL DESIRE—see EROS/EROTIC DESIRE; HOMOEROTIC RELATIONSHIPS; TYRANNY, TYRANT

SHIP OF STATE (as metaphor),

see also HELMSMEN/PILOTS; TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONALS WITH; ANALOGIES

SICILY—see SYRACUSE

SIGHT (as metaphor for knowledge, wisdom)

philosophers as “lovers of the vision of the truth,”

see also BLINDNESS; CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; COGNITION, FACULTIES OF; SUN, SIMILE OF

SIMONIDES

SILVER CLASS (in the ideal state)—see AUXILIARIES; PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the ideal state)

SIRENS,

SLAVES

in Athens and other Greek city-states

in the ideal state

SOCRATES, xxx-xxxiii

SOCRATICS, SOCRATIC CIRCLE

SOLON

SOPHOCLES

see also DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS; TRAGEDY

SOPHISTS

see also GORGIAS; HIPPIAS; PRODICUS; PROTAGORAS; THRASYMACHUS; RHETORIC, RHETORICIANS

SOUL

challenge of properly orienting the soul toward the world of being, xxxix,

function and excellence of,

immortality of,

contemplated in pure state, apart from body,

see also PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] in the human soul; APPETITIVE PRINCIPLE [ELEMENT]; RATIONAL PRINCIPLE [ELEMENT]; SPIRIT, PASSION; EDUCATION; NATURAL ABILITY, NATURE [PHYSIS]

SPARTA

SPIRIT, PASSION [THUMOS] (as distinct from the RATIONAL and APPETITIVE ELEMENTS of the soul),

see also PRINCIPLES [ELEMENTS] (in the soul)

STESICHORUS

SUN, SIMILE OF, see also CAVE, ALLEGORY OF; SIGHT

SYRACUSE (SICILY)

see also DION; DIONYSIUS; DIONYSIUS

T

TECHNICAL EXPERTISE [TECHNÊ], PROFESSIONALS WITH

see also ANALOGIES; DOCTORS/PHYSICIANS/MEDICINE; HELMSMEN/PILOTS; MUSICIANS

TEMPERANCE, MODERATION [SOPHROSYNÊ]

as an essential quality of guardians

as one of the four principal “virtues,”

THALES,

THEAGES,

THEATER—see DRAMA, DRAMATIC PRODUCTIONS AND COMPETITIONS; TRAGEDY

THEBES

THEMISTOCLES

THEOCONY—see Hesiod

THEÔRIA [CONTEMPLATION]

THESEUS

THIRTY TYRANTS

THRASYMACHUS

THUCYDIDES

TIMARCHY, TIMOCRACY

TIMARCHIC/TIMOCRATIC INDIVIDUAL,

TRADE (between states),

TRAGEDY, TRAGEDIANS

see also CENSORSHIP; EDUCATION; HOMER AND HOMERIC EPICS; IMITATION; MUSIC; POETRY

TRUTHFULNESS, LOVE OF TRUTH

of god(s),

of philosophers

see also FALSEHOODS (useful, necessary); PHILOSOPHY; DIALECTIC

TYRANNICAL INDIVIDUAL,

see also EROS, EROTIC/SEXUAL DESIRE; ENSLAVEMENT; TYRANNY, TYRANT

TYRANNY, TYRANT

U

UNITY (among citizens in the ideal state),

see alsoSTRIFE/DISUNITY; FAMILY; PRIVATE PROPERTY

URANUS [OURANOS],

USURY,

V

VIRTUE—see EXCELLENCE

W

WAR

children of guardians as observers in,

conduct of,

WARRIORS

guardians in the ideal state as,

see also EDUCATION; GUARDIANS; AUXILIARIES; RULERS; WAR; WOMEN

WEALTH, xlii,

see alsoSTRIFE/DISUNITY; PLEONEXIA; POVERTY; PRIVATE PROPERTY

WISDOM [SOPHIA]

as one of the four principal “virtues,”

WOMEN

in classical Athens

in the guardian classes of the ideal state

as warriors,

see also BREEDING; FAMILY; NATURAL ABILITY, NATURE [PHYSIS]

WORKS AND DAYS—see HESIOD

X

XENOPHANES

XENOPHON

pseudo-Xenophon, The Constitution of the Athenians [The Old Oligarch]

XERXES,

Y

YOUTH—see CHILDREN; EDUCATION; PHILOSOPHY (dangers of premature exposure to)

Z

ZENO, xxvii

ZEUS

a

American Journal of Philology 13 (1892), pp. 349—372.

b

Information about Socrates, Thrasymachus, and other interlocutors in Republic is given in the introduction.

c

The major port city of Attica, about 4 miles from Athens.

d

The Thracian deity Bendis, identified by Greeks with the goddess Artemis. The cult of Bendis was officially accepted in Piraeus in 430 or 429 B.C.E.

e

The phrase evokes the Homeric poems; compare Iliad 22.60 and 24.487, and Odyssey 15.246.

f

Literally, “we who are approximately the same age often come to the same place.”

g

Athenian tragedian (c.496-406 B.C.E.), active as a playwright until his death.

h

Athenian general (c.528-462 B.C.E.) who masterminded the defeat of the Persian navy at the battle of Salamis in 480 B.C.E.

i

Seriphos is a small island in the Aegean Sea.

j

Lyric poet (c.518-438 B.C.E.) whose work is cited again at 2.365b. The poem from which Cephalus quotes does not survive.

k

Lyric and elegiac poet (c.548-468 B.C.E.) from the island Ceos, whose work is also alluded to at 2.365c. The saying attributed to Simonides here does not match anything in the extant fragments of his poetry.

l

The grandfather of Odysseus (the hero of Odyssey), who is described in Odyssey 19.392-398.

m

Bias and Pittacus were legendary wise men (“sages”) who lived in the sixth century B.C.E. Bias was from Priene (in Ionia), Pittacus from Mytilene (on the island Lesbos in the Aegean).

n

The expression suggests that, in Thrasymachus’ view, Socrates is wrangling unscrupulously for the sake of personal gain.

o

That is, an attendant at a public bath. Aristophanes, Knights 1403 stereotypes bathmen, along with prostitutes, as disreputable individuals.

p

“Good” here is agathos in Greek, the positive form of the superlative adjective aristos.

q

“Lyre” (lyra) can refer to any number of stringed instruments commonly played in ancient Greece.

r

Festival in honor of the goddess Bendis; see the first paragraph of 1.327.

s

In book 1 of his Histories, Herodotus (c.490-420 B.C.E.) relates a somewhat different story about how Gyges came to be king of Lydia (in western Asia Minor) in the late eighth century B.C.E. His descendant Croesus ruled Lydia in the middle of the sixth century B.C.E.

t

Athenian tragedian (c.525-456 B.C.E.). The reference here is to Seven Against Thebes 592-594.

u

Aeschylus, Seven Against Thebes 574-575.

v

An ancient commentator (scholiast) states that the source of the proverb is Odyssey 16.97-98; compare Iliad 21.308-309.

w

Poet from Boeotia (c. late eighth century B.C.E.), author of several major poems in dactylic hexameter, including the extant Theogony (about the origins of various gods and their conflicts with one another) and the didactic poem Works and Days. As far back as the fifth century B.C.E., Hesiod was frequently linked to (or contrasted with) Homer.

x

Hesiod, Works and Days 232-233.

y

Odyssey 19.109-112.

z

Musaeus was a legendary singer, often associated with the singer Orpheus and also with the god Apollo, the Muses, and the Moon (see below at 2.364e). “His son” probably refers to Eumolpus, the legendary ancestor of the Eumolpidae clan in Eleusis.

aa

God of the underworld; by extension, the underworld itself.

ab

Itinerant prophets and seers, as well as bards and musicians, would have traditionally been guests in the households of wealthy, powerful men in Greek city-states.

ac

Hesiod, Works and Days 287-289.

ad

Adapted from Iliad 9.497-501.

ae

Legendary Thracian singer and founder of the religious movement called Or phism, which entertained ideas about reincarnation and transmigration of the soul. The phrase “host of books” refers to Orphic texts.

af

From a poem by Pindar that is no longer extant.

ag

The allusion is to a poem by Simonides.

ah

Archilochus was an iambic and elegiac poet (early seventh century B.C.E.) from the island Paros; two extant fragments of Archilochus’ poetry deal with clever foxes.

ai

From Iliad 9.497-501, adapted above at 2.364d-e.

aj

Literally, “sons of that man”—that is, Thrasymachus. Glaucon and Adeimantus are Thrasymachus’ “sons” insofar as they have continued the argument he began in book 1.

ak

Possibly Critias (460-403 B.C.E.), a distant relation of Plato and his brothers, who eventually led the oligarchic coup of 404-403 B.C.E.

al

There were battles at Megara in 424 and 409 B.C.E.; if the “dramatic date” of Republic is meant to be 411 or 410 B.C.E., reference to the battle in 409 would be an anachronism.

am

The name Ariston evokes the adjective aristos (“best”); compare 9.580b.

an

That is, a polis, or city-state.

ao

The Greek means, literally, “our need will create [or determine] it.”

ap

Hetairai in Greek. “Courtesans and cakes” are juxtaposed in lists of luxuries in, for example, Aristophanes, Acharnians 1090-1092.

aq

That is, to raise pigs for food. Although animals in the “healthy city” would be slaughtered for their hides, the inhabitants would apparently subsist on a vegetarian diet (2.372b).

ar

Uranus (Ouranos in Greek), the ancient deity of the sky and mate of Gaia (Earth), was castrated by his son Cronus (Hesiod, Theogony 154-181); Cronus was in turn deposed by his son, Zeus, the current ruler of the cosmos (Hesiod, Theogony 453-506).

as

Pigs were typically sacrificed in the initiatory rites for the mystery cult at Eleusis.

at

There are several accounts of battles between the Olympian gods, led by Zeus, and the giants (created, according to Hesiod, Theogony 185, when the blood of the castrated Uranus fell onto Gaia).

au

The story of Hephaestus’ binding of his mother Here (Hera), the wife and sister of Zeus, was apparently related by Pindar. Hephaestus is the god of fire and metal-working crafts.

av

Iliad 1.586-594. Zeus’ punishment left Hephaestus permanently lame.

aw

This quotation and the two following are from Iliad 24.527-532.

ax

Source unknown.

ay

In Iliad 4, the Trojan Pandarus breaks the truce between the Greeks and the Trojans by shooting an arrow at Menelaus, the husband of Helen and the brother of Agamemnon, the leader of the Greek forces.

az

Daughter of Zeus, goddess of war, wisdom, and crafts, and patron of the Greeks at Troy. In Iliad 4.85-104, Athena disguises herself as a Trojan and prompts Pandarus to wound Menelaus.

ba

Probably a reference to Iliad 20.1-74, where Zeus dispatches the goddess Themis to call the gods to the council.

bb

From a lost play about Niobe by Aeschylus.

bc

Daughter of Tantalus and wife of Amphion, Niobe boasted that her twelve children made her more blessed than the goddess Leto, mother (by Zeus) of the gods Apollo and Artemis. Apollo and Artemis killed all the children of Niobe, who subsequently turned to stone in grief.

bd

Odyssey 17.485-486.

be

Odyssey 4.455-460 describes the shape-changing of Proteus, a minor sea-god.

bf

Pindar, in the fourth Nemean ode, describes how Thetis, a minor goddess who became (by the mortal Peleus) the mother of the mortal warrior Achilles, transformed herself in order to avoid marrying Peleus.

bg

From a lost play by Aeschylus.

bh

Indicated here are the tales about “bogey monsters,” such as those mentioned in Aristophanes, Frogs 293.

bi

Iliad 2.1-34.

bj

Perhaps from Aeschylus’ lost Contest of Arms (Hoplon krisis). Whatever the origin of the quotation, “her fair progeny” refers to Achilles, and “Phoebus” refers to the god Apollo.

bk

Odyssey 11.489-491. The verses, spoken by the ghost of Achilles in the underworld, are also quoted in Republic at 7.516d. From this point on, the representation of Achilles’ conduct (in Iliad) is one of the chief foci of Socrates’ criticism of poetry’s content.

bl

Iliad 20.64-65. Pluto is another name for Hades, the god of the underworld.

bm

Iliad 23.103-104.

bn

Odyssey 11.493-495. Tiresias is the legendary blind Theban prophet. In Odyssey 11, in order to learn about his future, Odysseus calls up the spirit of Tiresias from the underworld.

bo

Iliad 16.856-857.

bp

Iliad 23.100.

bq

Odyssey 246-249.

br

Two rivers in the underworld.

bs

Allusion to Iliad 24.10-12, which describes the grief of Achilles as he mourns for his recently killed companion Patroclus.

bt

Allusion to Iliad 18.23, when Achilles first learns of Patroclus’ death.

bu

Iliad 22.414-415. Priam, king of Troy, is “kinsman of the gods” because he is descended from Zeus.

bv

Iliad 18.54. Thetis, Achilles’ mother, is the speaker.

bw

Iliad 22.168. The speaker is Zeus.

bx

Iliad 16.433. Again, the speaker is Zeus. Sarpedon is Zeus’ son by a mortal woman and is hence himself mortal. Zeus laments his pending death at the hands of Patroclus.

by

Iliad 1.599.

bz

Odyssey 17.383-384.

ca

Iliad 4.412. Diomedes was one of the Greek chieftains at Troy.

cb

These verses do not follow Iliad 4.412. The first is Iliad 3.8, the second Iliad 4.431.

cc

Iliad 1.225, addressed by Achilles to Agamemnon. Although Achilles is the best warrior in the Greek army, Agamemnon is its commander; hence the judgment that Achilles’ words are “ill spoken.”

cd

Odyssey 9.8-10.

ce

Odyssey 12.342.

cf

Iliad 14.281. In Iliad 14, Here (Hera) seduces Zeus and thus temporarily distracts him from his supervision of the battle between the Greeks and the Trojans. The description above of Zeus lying awake “devising plans” is actually derived from Iliad 2.1-4.

cg

In Odyssey 8.266-366, the Phaeacian bard Demodocus relates a story about how Hephaestus caught his wife, Aphrodite, the goddess of lust and sensuality, in bed with the handsome young war-god Ares.

ch

Odysseus in Odyssey 20.17-18.

ci

Saying attributed to Hesiod.

cj

In Iliad 9, Phoenix (along with Odysseus and Ajax) brings gifts from Agamemnon to Achilles in an effort to persuade Achilles to relent in his anger toward Agamemnon and to rejoin the fighting against the Trojans.

ck

Although Achilles refuses the gifts from Agamemnon in Iliad 9, he accepts them in Iliad 19 as he prepares to go back into battle.

cl

Achilles kills Hector, the leading warrior of the Trojans and Priam’s son, in Iliad 22. In Iliad 24, he accepts ransom for Hector’s body and returns it to Priam.

cm

Iliad 22.15 and 20.

cn

Achilles fights the river-god Scamander in Iliad 21.

co

Iliad 23.140-151. Achilles vowed to offer locks of his hair to the river Spercheius if he safely returned to Greece after the war; by the time he prepares Patroclus’ funeral pyre in Iliad 23, however, he knows that he will die in Troy.

cp

Iliad 24.14-17.

cq

Iliad 23.175-177.

cr

Cheiron was the centaur (half-human, half-horse) who was Achilles’ tutor.

cs

Theseus was a legendary king of Athens and descendant of Poseidon, god of the sea; he and his companion Peirithous ventured to the underworld to steal away Persephone, goddess of the underworld, from her husband, Hades.

ct

Both quotations are from Aeschylus’ tragedy Niobe. Ida is the mountain near the city of Troy.

cu

Iliad 1.15-16. Chryses, priest of Apollo in a town near Troy that had been plun dered by the Greeks, seeks to pay ransom for his daughter Chryseis but is rebuffed by Agamemnon, who has taken her as a concubine. The god who becomes angered against the Greeks because of Chryses’ prayer is Apollo.

cv

The Greeks in Iliad and Odyssey are typically called Achaeans, Danaans, and Argives.

cw

Dithyrambs were narrative poems performed by large choruses (some composed of men, some of boys); they were featured, along with tragedies and comedies, in festal competitions at the Theater of Dionysus in Athens.

cx

Once again, physis; see note 9 on 2.367e, page 358.

cy

In Greek, harmonia (“harmony,” referring literally to the “attunement” of lyre strings); also translated as “mode.”

cz

Although the word aulos is commonly translated as “flute,” the aulos is not, properly speaking, flute-like. “Pipe” is a more accurate rendering of aulos; it is a different instrument from the rustic Pan’s pipe (syrinx) that Socrates deems appropriate for shepherds.

da

The Greek actually reads “the lyre and cithara”; the cithara was the specific type of lyre used by professional musicians (citharists, who played the instrument but did not sing, and citharodes, who played and sang).

db

Anubis; compare 9.592a and Gorgias 428b. Plato at times represents Socrates swearing unusual oaths—for example, “by the goose.”

dc

Influential theorist on music from Athens (fifth century B.C.E.).

dd

That is, a prostitute.

de

Cakes (pemmata); compare 2.373a for the juxtaposition of “courtesans” and cakes.

df

The Asclepiadae were a group of physicians with schools in Cyrene, Rhodes, and elsewhere. Asclepius was a legendary healer and son of Apollo.

dg

Greek chieftain at Troy. Socrates plainly refers to Iliad 11.833, but it was Machaon, not Eurypylus, who was given the wine-barley-cheese drink in Iliad 11.614. The sons of Asclepius at the Trojan War are Machaon and Podalirius, the two doctors in the Greek army.

dh

Physician (from Megara, fifth century B.C. E.) who was an expert in physical training and diet. He is not to be confused the brother of the Sicilian rhetorician Gorgias, also named Herodicus, who is mentioned in Gorgias 448b and was also a physician.

di

Poet from Miletus (sixth century B.C.E.). Plato distorts the emphases of Phocylides’ verse.

dj

Adaptation of Iliad 4.218.

dk

King of Phrygia in northwestern Asia Minor (late eighth to early seventh century B.C.E.) who was proverbially wealthy. Plato perhaps alludes here to a line in a poem by Tyrtaeus (Spartan but possibly of Athenian birth, early seventh century B.C.E.). The story of Midas’ “golden touch” can be found in the Roman poet Ovid’s Metamorphoses 11.

dl

That is, by representing heroic figures such as Asclepius taking bribes; compare 3.390e-391a.

dm

The conception of the earth (Gaia) as a mother-figure is well established in ancient Greek mythology.

dn

For the concept that different people have different “natures,” see note 9 on 2.367e and note 12 on 2.370b.

do

That is, the hypothetical questioner posited at 4.419a.

dp

An obscure reference. On the divided nature of all other cities, see 8.551d.

dq

Compare Odyssey 1.351-352.

dr

The Hydra was a mythical monster with multiple heads; when one head was cut off, two more grew back in its place.

ds

Site of an important pan-Hellenic sanctuary dedicated to Apollo. The oracular shrine at Delphi, where Apollo was thought to prophesy through his priestess (the Pythia), was conceived of as resting on the supposed center (“navel”) of the earth.

dt

Daimones in Greek; that is, guardian spirits.

du

Figures such as Achilles, Heracles, Theseus, and Helen, as well as less well known and locally important figures, were worshiped throughout the Greek world in hero cults.

dv

That is, chthonic deities such as the Furies (Eumenides) and Persephone.

dw

that is, Apollo.

dx

The concept of self-mastery (literally, being “superior” to oneself) was integral to the popular understanding of moderation (sophrosynê).

dy

The “weaker” class is the “bronze/iron” class of artisans and farmers; the “stronger” is the “gold” class of rulers, and the “middle” is the “silver” class of auxiliaries.

dz

Compare Compare 2.370b; also 2.372a.

ea

In a fragment of a lost comedy, someone named Leotrophidas is said to seem as “comely as a corpse” to a certain Leontius, who is presumably the same individual as the one described in this anecdote.

eb

Odyssey 20.17, quoted with approval above at 3.390d.

ec

Compare 4.424a.

ed

Goddess and personification of retribution.

ee

That is, a wrestling school. Spartan women exercised and trained in public. Athenians of the classical period found the Spartan practice distasteful and ridiculous.

ef

That is, the hypothetical critics of Socrates’ proposals concerning the training of female guardians. See also the references to “the adversary’s position” and “our opponents” below in 453a-b.

eg

Arion (seventh century B.C.E.) was a musician from Lesbos; a dolphin supposedly rescued him after he was thrown overboard.

eh

From a lost poem by Pindar.

ei

Literally, in the city of the eudaimones; see note 13 on 1.344a.

ej

Some ancient medical writers claimed that children are not born in the eighth month of pregnancy; this perhaps explains Socrates’ choice of wording.

ek

See 4.427b for Socrates’ designation of Apollo as the patron deity of the ideal state and for Apollo’s association with the Pythian oracle at Delphi; compare 7.540b-c.

el

Works and Days 40.

em

That is, with garlands.

en

Reference to Iliad 7.321-322.

eo

Iliad 8.162.

ep

Works and Days 121-122. The verses describe how members of the primeval golden race became, after their blessed lives and painless deaths, “guardians” (phylakes) of the living.

eq

That is, Apollo; compare 5.470a.

er

Literally, an “erotic man” (anêr erotikos); see note 16 on 3.402e.

es

Momus is, properly speaking, the personification of censure and faultfinding.

et

That is, the hypothetical critic posited by Adeimantus at 6.487c.

eu

The saying was attributed to Simonides.

ev

Literally, “those who practice opposite things”—that is, politicians and their ilk who, in their bids for power, displace philosophers from political leadership, just as the mutinous sailors in the image of the ship stand in the way of the true helmsman.

ew

Theages was a member of Socrates’ circle who predeceased Socrates; a dialogue titled Theages has been preserved in the Platonic corpus but is probably not by Plato.

ex

Heracleitus (today more commonly spelled Heraclitus) posited that the sun was extinguished every evening and rekindled every morning.

ey

Compare Iliad 1.131.

ez

That is, at 3.412c-414b.

fa

A pun on the word tokos, which means both “offspring” and “interest owed on a debt.”

fb

The sun (Helios) was traditionally conceived of as a deity; in later times, Apollo (Phoebus) came to be thought of as the god of the sun. Helios in Greek is a masculine noun; in this passage and again in book 7, Jowett uses masculine pronouns to refer to it.

fc

Jowett uses the masculine possessive adjective to refer to the idea of the good, although it is a neuter entity (to agathon), presumably because Socrates here conceives of “the good” as the “parent” or “father” of the sun.

fd

That is, epístemê (also translated as “knowledge”), the cognitive faculty whereby intelligible objects (the ideas, as opposed to objects in the phenomenal realm) are known; see note 24 on 5.476d.

fe

Duranos (also transliterated as “Uranus”) refers to the sky (or “heavens”) and to the primeval god of the sky. Horatos is a verbal adjective meaning “that which is seen.”

ff

Once again, the word for sun in Greek (helios) is masculine—hence the masculine pronouns in Jowett’s translation.

fg

Odyssey 11.489. Socrates criticizes the verse at 3.386c.

fh

That is, as would happen in the rigorous training of future guardians that is described in books 2 and 3.

fi

The place where those who have led virtuous or exemplary lives were typically thought to be ensconced after death; see also 7.540b.

fj

The references in this paragraph are to 4.419a-421c and 3.414b-415d.

fk

See note 20 on 2.376e for the broad semantic range of mousikê, the word translated here as “music.”

fl

Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides all composed tragedies about Palamedes, a Greek chieftain at Troy, who was traditionally credited with the invention of numbers and also writing; in other sources, the god Prometheus is credited with the invention of numbers.

fm

The term arithmetikê, here translated as “arithmetic,” has more to do with the “science of number”—that is, the study of the characteristics of certain types of numbers (for example, even and odd)—than with simple addition, subtraction, etc.

fn

That is, plane geometry.

fo

Legendary artist and craftsman. Among other achievements, he constructed the labyrinth on Crete to contain the Minotaur.

fp

Literally, “the craftsman (demiourgos) of heaven.” Compare “the artificer (demiourgos) of the senses” at 6.507c.

fq

See notes 32 on 6.509d and 33 on 510b.

fr

The distinction is between doxa and epistemê, as at 5.476d-480a.

fs

Compare 3.412c—414b; also 6.494a-495b.

ft

That is, megaloprepeia (high-mindedness); compare 6.486a.

fu

That is, at 3.412c; compare 6.498b—c.

fv

Athenian statesman and poet (late seventh to early sixth centuries B.C.E.).

fw

Compare 5.467a—e.

fx

See note 6 on 5.454a for the distinction between eristic and dialectic.

fy

Compare 1.347c.

fz

The oracle of Apollo at Delphi. See 5.461e and 4.427b.

ga

Compare 5.455b—457b.

gb

Compare 6.501a.

gc

That is, 4.445c-e.

gd

According to an ancient commentator, the reference is to the way in which wrestlers, after being thrown, rose and resumed their positions.

ge

Compare Odyssey 19.162. For the assumption that the characters of individuals determine the characters of states, see 4.435e.

gf

At 1.344c.

gg

Timê in Greek means “honor”; timokratia and timarchia are Platonic neologisms for the philotimos politeia (“honor-loving constitution” or, as Jowett translates, “government of honor”) in which the ambitious silver class dominates. See 8.548c—e.

gh

Throughout books 8 and 9, Socrates uses the term “aristocracy” to refer to the government of “the best” that is only possible, he argues, in the ideal state.

gi

Adapted from Iliad 16.112.

gj

“That which is of divine birth” is perhaps meant to signify the world as a whole; compare Timaeus 30a.

gk

That is, a period of gestation. The “perfect number” that describes the period of gestation of “that which is divinely born” is left unspecified.

gl

That is, by squaring a number and then multiplying it again by its square (cubing).

gm

More literally, “comprehending three distances and four limits.” “Three distances” refers perhaps to the height, width, and depth of a square or rectangular cube. “Four limits” may signify the four comer points on a cube that define its height, width, and depth.

gn

Alternatively, “of elements that make things like and unlike and cause increase and decrease....” These “elements” are perhaps the numbers 3, 4, and 5, which are the lengths of the sides of the Pythagorean triangle. It may be significant that the combined cubes of these numbers (that is, 33+43+53) yield 216, which some ancient theorists (for example, the Pythagoreans) identified as the minimum number of days for human gestation.

go

Literally, “the base ‘thirded,’ yoked to 5, yields two harmonies when thrice increased.” The base is 3, which is first multiplied by one and one-third times itself (that is, 3 x 4/3, equaling 4); this figure (that is, 3 x 4, or 12) is then multiplied by 5, yielding 60. 60 is then multiplied by itself raised to the third power (that is, 60x603); this yields 12,960,000, which can also be expressed as (3×4×5)4. The number 12,960,000 “comprehends” two geometric figures representing “two harmonies.” The first figure is a square with sides measuring 3600 units (3600 × 3600 = 12,960,000); the second is a rectangle with sides measuring 4800 and 2700 units (4800 x 2700 =12,960,000). Readers should note that, in the original text, the number 12,960,000 is reached through a series of multiplications; Jowett’s translation, “the base of these with a third added,” misrepresents Socrates’ mathematical logic.

gp

The side of the square in question is 36 “100 times as great”—that is, 36 x 100, which equals 3600.

gq

Alternatively, “a figure having one side equal to the other, but oblong [that is, in a rectangle; two sides instead of four have the same measurement], having one side that is 100 squares of the rational diameter of 5, minus 100.” The rational diameter of 5 is 7, because the diameter of a square with sides of 5 units is the square root of 50, and the closest rational number (that is, integer) to the square root of 50 is 7, since 7 x 7 = 49. “100 squares of the rational diameter of 5,” then, is 100 x 7 x 7, or 4900. Subtracting 100 from 4900 yields 4800.

gr

This is shorthand for “or of 100 squares of irrational diameters, wanting 2 each,” which presents an alternative way of arriving at the number 4800: that is, (50-2) x 100. The irrational diameter is the square root of 50; the square of this number is 50; “wanting 2 each” means that 2 must be subtracted from 50, yielding 48.

gs

That is, 100 x 33 = 2700.

gt

Compare 4.423e.

gu

Compare 3.415a—c.

gv

Adapted from Aeschylus, Seven Against Thebes 451 and 570.

gw

See 8.544c.

gx

The distinction between necessary and unnecessary appetites (and pleasures) is fleshed out at 8.558d—559d.

gy

That is, Ploutos, the god of wealth.

gz

Another pun on the word tokos, which means both “offspring” and “interest (on a loan)”; compare 6.507a.

ha

Compare 6.492a and 6.496a—b.

hb

Compare Odyssey 9.82—104. The reference here is to the “drone desires” mentioned at 8.559d.

hc

Literally, unmixed wine. Greeks typically drank wine mixed with water.

hd

Adapted from a lost play.

he

The proverb in question is “Like mistress, like her dog”; it refers to the imitation by female slaves of their mistresses’ ways.

hf

The speaker’s platform in, for example, the Assembly.

hg

“Demagogic” politicians (such as Cleon, who died in 422 B.C.E.) styled themselves as “champions [prostatai] of the people.”

hh

That is, Zeus the wolf-god. Tales about werewolves were popular in antiquity.

hi

That is, the rational part of the soul.

hj

For the reliance of tyrants on bodyguards, see 8.566b.

hk

“Motherland” (metris), as opposed to the more typical “fatherland” (patris), was apparently the favored expression on Crete.

hl

Compare 9.580a and 1.344c-d.

hm

That is, aretê; see note 6 on 1.335b.

hn

Ariston’s name is derived from the adjective aristos (“best”); see 2.368a and also note 6 on 1.335b.

ho

That is, the “spirit” (thumos).

hp

The temple of Zeus at Olympia was an important pan-Hellenic site; dedication to Olympian Zeus marks the significance of an object or deed.

hq

That is, “deprivations.” The Greek word kenosis literally means an “emptying.”

hr

The tyrannical man is “three times removed” from his oligarchical counterpart if one counts inclusively, as the Greeks regularly did; compare 10.597e.

hs

That is, since the “timarchic” man is between them. Once again, Socrates counts inclusively.

ht

The tyrant is 3×3 (that is, 9) times removed from the “kingly” man; the kingly man’s pleasure—which Socrates envisions in a “solid” figure—is therefore 93 (that is, 729) times greater than the tyrant’s.

hu

Mythological monsters: The Chimera was envisioned as a conflation of a lion, a goat, and a serpent. The sea-dwelling Scylla had six heads and twelve feet. Cerberus was the triple-headed dog that guarded the underworld.

hv

Oedipus’s son Polyneices, exiled from Thebes by his brother Eteocles, sought to restore himself to power with the help of King Amphiareus of Argos; to secure the reluctant King’s cooperation, he bribed Amphiareus’ wife, Eriphyle, with a necklace.

hw

Compare 3.399e.

hx

Compare 5.472d-e.

hy

See note 24 on 2.379a.

hz

On Asclepius and the Asclepiadae, see 3.405d-406c.

ia

The traditional founder of the Spartan (Lacedaemonian) constitution and way of life (perhaps early eighth century B.C.E.).

ib

Lawgiver in the city-state Catana (on Sicily) and Rhegium (in southern Italy) who was active in the sixth century B.C.E.

ic

By the classical period, the Homeridae (literally, “sons of Homer”) established themselves as authoritative interpreters of the works attributed in antiquity to Homer.

id

Thales (late seventh to early sixth century B.C.E.) of Miletus was credited in antiquity with predicting the occurrence of a solar eclipse that took place in 585 B.C.E.; he is often cited as one of the “seven sages” and is credited with bringing Egyptian techniques of “land measurement” (that is, geometry) to the Greek world.

ie

Anacharsis apparently traveled widely in Greece in the early sixth century B.C.E.; he was credited by some with the invention of the anchor and the potter’s wheel.

if

The Pythagoreans were known for their asceticism.

ig

Rhapsodes were professional (often itinerant) performers of epic poetry; see note 5 on 1.334a.

ih

Compare 4.439c-441c.

ii

Compare 3.387d-e.

ij

Compare 10.608a and also 9.577a.

ik

That is, poetry, which is referred to by feminine pronouns through Jowett’s translation of this passage. In subsequent pages, Jowett also uses feminine pronouns when referring to the soul (psyche in Greek) and justice (dikaiosynê) .

il

The sources of these sayings are unknown.

im

Jowett’s translation is less than literal; literally translated, the Greek reads, “This entire time, from childhood to old age, would be something slight compared to everything [that is, the whole of time].”

in

Eye inflammation.

io

Fisherman who was transformed into a sea-god.

ip

That is, at the soul’s “philosophy.”

iq

That is, material goods, including wealth, fame, and prestige.

ir

The dog-skin “cap of Hades,” which provides invisibility, is mentioned in Iliad 5.844.

is

Literally, “the prizes of victory which it [that is, justice] acquires through reputation and confers on those who possess it [that is, individuals who are just]”; compare “the palms of victory which the gods give the just,” at 10.613b.

it

See 1.352b.

iu

The “goal” is in the mid-course turning point. Both foot and chariot races were typically run in two segments, the first going to and the second returning from a turning point (or post).

iv

Compare 10.608c.

iw

Compare Phaedrus 249b.

ix

A fictional figure.

iy

Compare Gorgias 525c-d.

iz

That is, Tartarus, the lowest place in the underworld. Compare Gorgias 523b and Phaedo 112a-b.[p. 000]

ja

Warship with three banks of oars.

jb

Various “pre-Socratic philosophers,” such as Empedocles and Parmenides, conceived of “Necessity” as a cosmic principle. The personification of Necessity in this passage is in keeping with traditional poetic practices.

jc

That is, the weight on the end of a spindle that keeps it twirling.

jd

The sirens in Odyssey 12 are singers whose alluring song dangerously distracts passing seafarers. In contrast, Socrates envisions them simply as immortal singers.

je

In sources dating to the archaic period, the Fates (Moirai, or “Apportioners”) are identified as daughters of the goddess Night, or of Zeus and Themis; they are traditionally conceived of as spinners who spin and cut threads that determine the courses of individual human lives. Clotho means “Spinner”; Lachesis, “Getting-by-Lot”; and Atropos, “Irresistible.”

jf

That is, “guardian spirit” (daimon).

jg

Swans were thought to sing when they were about to die; Orpheus was supposed to have been killed by Maenads (female worshipers of Dionysus).

jh

Thamyras was a legendary Thracian singer who was punished for challenging the Muses to a contest; the songs of nightingales were considered sweet but mournful.

ji

Ajax (in Greek, Aias) was a Greek chieftain (from the island Salamis) at Troy who figures prominently in Iliad. According to various traditions, Ajax committed suicide after the armor of the dead Achilles was awarded to Odysseus.

jj

Legendary Arcadian maiden and huntress who, since she was unwilling to marry, challenged all her suitors to footraces. ∥Epeus (also spelled Epeius) was the architect of the Trojan horse; see Odyssey 8.493.

jk

A commoner in the Greek army at Troy who dares to criticize Agamemnon and is beaten by Odysseus; compare Iliad 2.211-277.

jl

Also mentioned as a feature of the underworld in Aristophanes, Frogs 186 (produced in 405 B.C.E.).

Leave a Comment

0
(0)
Book Cover

Republic – Read Now and Download Mobi

Author
Plato & C.D.C. Reeve [Reeve, C.D.C.]

Rights
Copyright 2004 by Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.

Language
en

Published
2004-09-30

ISBN

Read Now

How useful was this post?

Click on a star to rate it!

Average rating 0 / 5. Vote count: 0

No votes so far! Be the first to rate this post.


image 9781603842761_0001_001a 9781603842761_0001_001b

Copyright © 2004 by Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.

 

All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America

 

10   09   08   03     4   5   6   7   8

 

For further information, please address:

Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.

P.O. Box 44937

Indianapolis, Indiana 46244-0937

 

www.hackettpublishing.com

 

Cover design by Abigail Coyle
Interior design by Jennifer Plumley
Composition by William Hartman

 

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Plato.

[Republic. English]

Republic / translated from the new standard Greek text, with
introduction, by C.D.C. Reeve.

p.   cm.

Includes bibliographical references and indexes.

ISBN 0-87220-737-4 (hardcover)—ISBN 0-87220-736-6 (pbk.)

1. Political science—Early works to 1800. 2 Utopias. I. Reeve, C.D.C.,
1948– . II. Title.

JC71.P513         2004
321'.07—dc22                                           2004013418

 

ISBN-13: 978-0-87220-737-0 (cloth)
ISBN-13: 978-0-87220-736-3 (pbk.)

 

PRC ISBN: 978-1-60384-106-1

 

For Daddy on his 88th birthday,
with much love.

Contents

 

Preface

Introduction

Select Bibliography

Synopsis

Note to the Reader

THE REPUBLIC

 

Book 1

Book 2

Book 3

Book 4

Book 5

Book 6

Book 7

Book 8

Book 9

Book 10

 

Glossary of Terms

Glossary and Index of Names

Preface

 

I have been a student of the Republic since I first encountered it as an undergraduate at Trinity College, Dublin. In 1988 I published a book about it (Philosopher-Kings). Four years later, I published a revision of G. M. A. Grube’s excellent translation. Perhaps I should have rested content with that, but my desire to have a Republic translation of my own proved too strong. The fruit of five years’ work, it is now in print. Naturally, I hope it improves on existing translations. If so, I have their producers largely to thank. Certainly, I have ransacked them for assistance. Tom Griffith has helped greatly, Robin Waterfield too, and also (in the case of Books 5 and 10) Stephen Halliwell. Over the years, my respect has grown for earlier translations—for that of George Grube, from which I learned a huge amount, but also for those of Allan Bloom and Paul Shorey.

Every translation, even the most self-consciously and flat-footedly slavish, is somewhat interpretative. There is no avoiding that. But I have tried to make this one as uninterpretative and close to the original as possible. One conscious deviation from strict accuracy, however, will be obvious at a glance. The Republic is largely in reported speech. Socrates is relating a conversation he had in the past. But I have cast his report as an explicit dialogue in direct speech, with identified speakers. In the Theaetetus, Plato has Eucleides adopt a similar stratagem. “This is the book,” he says to Terpsion; “You see, I have written it out like this: I have not made Socrates relate the conversation as he related it to me, but I represent him as speaking directly to the persons with whom he said he had this conversation.” Decades of teaching the Republic have persuaded me that the minimal loss in literalness involved in adopting Eucleides’ stratagem is more than made up for in readability and intelligibility.

I renew my gratitude to John Cooper for his always judicious advice, and to Paul Woodruff for his. I am also grateful to the publisher’s readers, Christopher Rowe and the team of Patrick Miller and Christopher Childers. The latter—in particular—saved me from numerous errors and omissions. My debt to their care and scholarship is unrepayable. I am grateful to Hackett Publishing Company itself for trusting me with what is, in many ways, its flagship text; to my editor, Deborah Wilkes, for her encouragement and support; to Jenevieve Maerker for her help with the Introduction and, with Abigail Coyle, for the cover design. Many warm thanks, finally, to Janet Zweig for suggesting the wonderfully appropriate cover photograph.

Chapel Hill, June 2004

Introduction

 

No one doubts that the Republic is one of the very greatest works of Western philosophy. Like nothing before it and very little since, it combines philosophical and literary resourcefulness of the highest order in an attempt to answer the most important question of all—how should we live if we want to live well and be happy? Justly or unjustly? Morally or immorally? Moreover, the answer it develops is based on an unusually rich account of our nature and the nature of reality. Ethics, politics, aesthetics, philosophy of religion, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, epistemology, and metaphysics are all woven together in it, and their later developments have been decisively shaped by its contribution to them. Contemporary philosophers read the Republic, as their predecessors did, not out of piety, but because it continues to challenge, disquiet, and inspire. Western philosophy is not, to be sure, simply a series of footnotes to this amazing text, but many of its best stories begin here.

PLATO

Plato was born in Athens in 429 BCE and died there in 348/7. His father, Ariston, traced his descent to Codrus, who was supposedly king of Athens in the eleventh century BCE; his mother, Perictione, was related to Solon, architect of the Athenian constitution (594/3). While Plato was still a boy, his father died and his mother married Pyrilampes, a friend of the great Athenian statesman Pericles. Hence Plato was familiar with Athenian politics from childhood and was expected to enter it himself. Horrified by actual political events, however, including the execution of his mentor and teacher Socrates in 399 BCE, he turned instead to philosophy, thinking that only it could bring true justice to human beings and put an end to civil war and political upheaval (see Seventh Letter 324b–326b). In the Republic, written around 380 BCE, he lays out the grounds for this at once pessimistic and optimistic assessment.

Plato’s works, which are predominantly dialogues, all seem to have survived. They are customarily divided into four chronological groups, though the precise ordering (especially within groups) is controversial:

 

Early: Alcibiades, Apology, Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Hippias Minor, Hippias Major, Ion, Laches, Lysis, Menexenus, Theages

Transitional: Euthydemus, Gorgias, Meno, Protagoras

Middle: Cratylus, Phaedo, Symposium, Republic, Phaedrus, Parmenides, Theaetetus

Late: Timaeus, Critias, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus, Laws

 

Besides writing his dialogues, Plato contributed to philosophy by founding the Academy, arguably the first university. This was a center of research and teaching, both in theoretical subjects and also in more practical ones. Eudoxus, who gave a geometrical explanation of the revolutions of the sun, moon, and planets, brought his own students with him to join Plato and studied and taught in the Academy; Theaetetus developed solid geometry there. But cities also invited members of the Academy to help them in the practical task of developing new political constitutions.

The Academy lasted for some centuries after Plato died, ending around 80 BCE. Its early leaders, including his own nephew, Speusippus, who succeeded him, all modified his teachings in various ways. Later, influenced by the early Socratic dialogues, which end in puzzlement (aporia), the Academy, under Arcesilaus, Carneades, and other philosophers, defended skepticism; later still, influenced by Plato’s other writings, Platonists were more dogmatic, less unsure. Platonism of one sort or another—Middle or Neo-or something else—remained the dominant philosophy in the pagan world of late antiquity, influencing St. Augustine among others, until the emperor Justinian closed the pagan schools at Athens in 529 CE. Much of what passed for Plato’s thought until the nineteenth century, when German scholars pioneered a return to Plato’s writings themselves, was a mixture of these different “Platonisms.”

Given the vast span and diversity of Plato’s writings and the fact that they are dialogues, not treatises, it is little wonder that they were read in many different ways, even by Plato’s ancient followers. In this respect nothing has changed: different schools of philosophy and textual interpretation continue to find profoundly different messages and methods in Plato. Doctrinal continuities, discontinuities, and outright contradictions of one sort or another are discovered, disputed, rediscovered, and redisputed. Neglected dialogues are taken up afresh, old favorites newly interpreted. New questions are raised, old ones resurrected and reformulated: is Plato’s Socrates really the great ironist of philosophy or a largely non-ironic figure? Is Plato a systematic philosopher with answers to give or a questioner only? Is he primarily a theorist about universals, or a moralist, or a mystic with an otherworldly view about the nature of reality and the place of the human psyche in it? Is the Republic a totalitarian work, a hymn to freedom properly conceived, or a reductio ad absurdum of the very argument it seems to be advancing? Does the dramatic structure of the dialogues undermine their apparent philosophical arguments? Should Plato’s negative remarks about the efficacy of written philosophy (Phaedrus 274b–278b) lead us to look behind his dialogues for what Plato’s student Aristotle refers to as the “so-called unwritten doctrines” (Physics 209b 14–5)?

Besides this continued engagement with Plato’s writings, there is, of course, the not entirely separate engagement with the problems Plato brought to philosophy, the methods he invented to solve them, and the solutions he suggested and explored. So many and various are these, however, that they constitute not just Plato’s philosophy, but a large part of philosophy itself. Part of his heritage, they are also what we inevitably bring to our reading of his works.

SOCRATES

Socrates is the central figure in the Republic, as in most of Plato’s works. In some dialogues he is thought to be—and probably is—based to some extent on the historical Socrates. These are often called “Socratic” dialogues for this reason. In the transitional, middle, and late dialogues, however, he is thought to be increasingly a mouthpiece for ideas that go well beyond Plato’s Socratic heritage.

In the Socratic dialogues, philosophy consists almost exclusively in questioning people about the conventionally recognized moral virtues. What is piety (Euthyphro)? Or courage (Laches)? Or temperance (Charmides)? These are his characteristic questions. He seems to take for granted, moreover, that there are correct answers to them—that temperance, piety, courage, and the rest are each some definite characteristic or form (eidos, idea). He does not discuss the nature of these forms, however, nor develop any explicit theory of them or our knowledge of them. He does not, for that matter, explain his interest in definitions, nor justify his claim that if we do not know what, for example, justice is, we cannot know whether it is virtue, whether it makes its possessor happy, or anything else of any significance about it (Republic 354b–c).

Socrates’ style of questioning is called (by us, not him) an elenchus—from the Greek verb elengchein, meaning to examine or refute. He asks what justice is. His interlocutor puts forward a definition he sincerely believes to be correct. Socrates refutes this definition by showing that it conflicts with other beliefs the interlocutor sincerely holds and is unwilling to abandon. In the ideal situation, which is never actually portrayed in the Socratic dialogues, this process continues until a satisfactory definition emerges, one that is not inconsistent with other sincerely held beliefs, and so can withstand elenctic scrutiny.

The definitions Socrates encounters in his examinations of others prove unsatisfactory. But through these examinations—which are always at the same time self-examinations (Charmides 166c–d, Hippias Major 298b–c, Protagoras 348c–d)—he comes to accept some positive theses that have resisted refutation. Among these are the following three famous Socratic “paradoxes”:

 

The conventionally distinguished virtues—justice, piety, courage, and the rest—are all identical to wisdom or knowledge, conceived of as a type of craft (technê) 1 or expertise (Charmides 174b–c, Euthydemus 281d–e, Protagoras 329b–334c, 349a–361d). This is often referred to as the unity of the virtues doctrine.

Possession of this knowledge is necessary and sufficient for happiness (Crito 48b, Gorgias 470e).

No one ever acts contrary to what he knows or believes to be best, so that weakness of will is impossible (Protagoras 352a–359a).

Together these three doctrines constitute a kind of ethical intellectualism: they imply that what we need in order to be virtuous and happy is expert craft knowledge.

The goal of an elenchus is not just to reach adequate definitions of the virtues or seemingly paradoxical doctrines about weakness of will and virtue, however. Its primary aim is moral reform. For Socrates believes that, by curing people of the hubris of thinking they know when they do not, leading the elenctically examined life makes them happier and more virtuous than anything else. Philosophizing is so important for human welfare, indeed, that Socrates is willing to accept execution rather than give it up (Apology 29b–d, 30a, 36c–e, 38a, 41b–c).

In the transitional dialogues, as well as in some earlier ones, Socrates, as the embodiment of true philosophy, is contrasted with the sophists.2 They are, for the most part, unscrupulous, fee-taking moral relativists who think that moral values are based on convention; he is an honest, fee-eschewing moral realist, who thinks that the true virtues are the same for everyone everywhere. The problem latent in this contrast is that if people in different cultures have different beliefs about the virtues, it is not clear how the elenchus, which seems to rely wholly on such beliefs, can reach knowledge of objective or non-culture–relative moral truth.

THE REPUBLIC

The Republic is specifically about the virtue of justice and about whether it pays better dividends in terms of happiness than does injustice. It begins, therefore, with a characteristically Socratic search for justice’s definition (331b–c). Polemarchus provides the first candidate: justice is giving to each what he is owed (331e). Socrates proceeds to examine this definition by testing its consistency with other beliefs Polemarchus holds and is unwilling to abandon. When it proves to be inconsistent with them, it is taken to have been refuted (335e). Socrates must be presupposing, therefore, that some of Polemarchus’ sincerely held ethical beliefs are true, since inconsistency with false beliefs is no guarantee of falsehood. The problem is that there seems to be little reason to accept this presupposition.

Socrates’ next interlocutor, Thrasymachus, explains why. He argues that those who are stronger in any society—the rulers—control education and socialization through legislation and enforcement. But he thinks that the rulers, like everyone else, are self-interested. Hence they make laws and adopt conventions—including linguistic conventions—that are in their own best interests, not those of their weaker subjects. It is these conventions that largely determine a subject’s conception of justice and the other virtues. By being trained to follow or obey them, therefore, a subject is unwittingly adopting an ideology—a code of values and behavior—that serves his ruler’s, rather than his own, interests. Consequently, Thrasymachus defines justice not as what socialized subjects like Socrates and Polemarchus think it is (something genuinely noble and valuable that promotes their own happiness), but as what it really is in all cities: the interest of the stronger.

As in the case of Polemarchus, Socrates again uses the elenchus to try to refute Thrasymachus. But his attempts are not found wholly adequate, either by Thrasymachus himself or by the other interlocutors (350d–e, 357a–b, 358b–c). And we can see why: by arguing that ethical beliefs are an ideologically contaminated social product, Thrasymachus has undercut the elenchus altogether. He may get tied up in knots by Socrates, but his theory is invulnerable to elenctic refutation (as Thrasymachus points out at 349a). For elenctic refutation appeals to ideologically contaminated ideas in order to counter his theory, but his theory maintains that these have no validity. That is why Plato has Socrates abandon the elenchus in subsequent books and attempt to answer Thrasymachus (whose views are taken over by Glaucon and Adeimantus) by developing a positive defense of justice of his own.

THE ARGUMENT OF THE REPUBLIC IN OUTLINE

At the center of Socrates’ defense of justice stand the philosopher-kings—who unite political power and authority with philosophical knowledge of the transcendent, unchanging form of the good (the good-itself)—and the ideal city they come to rule, Kallipolis (“beautiful city” or “noble city” in Greek). Because this knowledge is based, as Socrates argues, in mathematics and science, it is unmediated by conventionally controlled concepts of good and bad, just and unjust. Hence it is free from the distorting influence of power or ideology, and so immune to the challenge Thrasymachus poses to the elenchus.

What the philosopher-kings do is construct a political system—including primarily a system of socialization and education—that will distribute the benefits of their specialized knowledge of the good among the citizens at large. The system they construct relies on Plato’s theory of the soul or mind (psychê), the seat of consciousness, emotion, desire, and decision-making. According to this theory, there are three fundamentally different kinds of desires: appetitive ones for food, drink, sex, and the money with which to acquire them; spirited ones for honor, victory, and good reputation; and rational ones for knowledge and truth (437b ff., 580d ff.). Each of these types of desire “rules” in the soul of a different type of person, determining his values. People most value what they most desire, and so those ruled by different desires have very different conceptions of what is valuable or good, or of what would make them happy. Just which type of desire rules an individual’s soul depends on the relative strengths of his desires and on the kind of education and socialization he receives. The fundamental goal of ethical or political education isn’t to provide knowledge, therefore, but to socialize desires, so as to turn people around (to the degree possible) from the pursuit of what they falsely believe to be happiness, to the pursuit of true happiness (518b–519d).

The famous allegory of the cave illustrates the effects of such education (514a). Uneducated people, tethered by their unsocialized appetites, see only images of models of the good (shadows cast by puppets on the walls of the cave). Such people are not virtuous to any degree, since they act simply on their whims. When their appetites are shaped through physical training and that mix of reading and writing, dance and song that the Greeks call mousikê (musical training), they are released from these bonds and are ruled by their socialized appetites. They have at least that level of virtue required to act prudently and postpone gratification. Plato refers to them as money-lovers, because they pursue money as the best means of reliably satisfying their appetitive desires in the long term (580d–581a). They see models of the good (the puppets that cast the shadows), for stable satisfaction of appetitive desires is a sort of good.

Further education, this time in mathematical science, leaves people who are eligible for it ruled by their spirited desires. They are honor-lovers, who seek success in difficult endeavors and the honor and approval it brings. They have the true beliefs about virtue required for such success, and hence that greater level of virtue Plato calls “political” virtue (430c).

Finally, yet further education in dialectic (a sort of philosophical training that is a descendant of the Socratic elenchus) and practical city management results in people who are bound only by their rational desires. They are free from illusion and see, not mere images of the good, but the good itself. They are wisdom-lovers or philosophers, who have knowledge rather than mere true belief about virtue, and so are fully virtuous.

Not everyone, however, is able to benefit from all these types of education: there are some at each stage whose desires are too strong for education to break. That is why there are producers, guardians, and philosopher-kings in the ideal city. That is why, too, these groups can cooperate with one another in a just system, where the money-loving producers trade their products for the protection provided by the honor-loving guardians and the knowledge provided by the wisdom-loving kings, rather than competing with them for the very same goods (462e–463b). Nonetheless, everyone in this ideal system is enabled to travel as far toward the sun (the good) as education can take him, given the innate strength of his desires. Thus everyone comes as close to being fully virtuous, and so to pursuing and achieving genuine happiness, as he can. It is this that makes Plato’s city both an ethical and a prudential ideal, both maximally just and maximally happy. And because it is both, it constitutes a response to the Thrasymachean challenge raised anew by Glaucon and Adeimantus in Republic 2. For if maximal justice and maximal happiness go together, then it pays, in terms of happiness, to be just rather than unjust.3

THE THEORY OF FORMS

In a number of dialogues, Plato connects the relativist doctrines he attributes to the sophists with the metaphysical theory of Heraclitus, according to which the perceptible things or characteristics we see around us are in constant flux or change—always becoming, never being. In the Theaetetus, he argues that Protagoras’ claim that “man is the measure of all things” presupposes that the world is in flux; in the Cratylus, he suggests that the theory of flux may itself be the result of projecting Protagorean relativism onto the world (411b–c). Nonetheless, Plato seems to accept some version of this theory himself (see Aristotle, Metaphysics 987a32–4). In Republic 5, for example, he characterizes perceptible things and characteristics as lying “in between what purely is and what in every way is not” (478a–479d; see also Timaeus 52a).

The theory of flux clearly exacerbates the problem we noticed earlier with the Socratic elenchus. If perceptible things and characteristics are always in flux, how can justice and the other virtues be stable forms? How can there be stable definitions of them to serve as correct answers to Socrates’ questions? And if there are no stable definitions, how can there be such a thing as ethical knowledge? More generally, if perceptible things and characteristics are always in flux, always becoming, how can anything be something definite or determinate? How can one know or say what anything is? Aristotle tells us that it was reflection on these fundamental questions that led Plato to “separate” the forms from perceptible things and characteristics (Aristotle, Metaphysics 987a29–b1). The allegories of the sun and line (Republic 507a–511e), which divide reality into the intelligible part and the visible (perceptible) part, seem to embody this separation.

Conceived in this way, forms seemed to Plato to offer solutions to the metaphysical and epistemological problems to which the elenchus and flux give rise. As intelligible objects set apart from the perceptible world, they are above the sway of flux, and so available as stable objects of knowledge; stable meanings or referents for words. As real, mind-independent entities, they provide the basis for the definitions of the virtues that Socratic ethics needs.

Like many proposed solutions to philosophical problems, however, Plato’s raises new problems of its own. If forms really are separate from the world of flux our senses reveal to us, how can we know them? How can our words connect with them? If items in the perceptible world really are separate from forms, how can they owe whatever determinate being they have to forms? In the Meno, Phaedo, and Phaedrus, Plato answers the first of these questions by appeal to the doctrine of recollection (anamnêsis). We have knowledge of forms through prenatal, direct contact with them; we forget this knowledge when our souls become embodied at birth; then we “recollect” it in this life when our memories are appropriately jogged. He answers the second question by saying that items in the world of flux “participate” in forms by resembling them. Thus perceptible objects possess the characteristic of beauty because they resemble the form of beauty, which is itself beautiful in a special and basic way (see Phaedo 100c, Symposium 210b–211e).

The doctrine of recollection presupposes the immortality of the soul—something Plato argues for in Republic 10 and elsewhere (Phaedo 69e ff., Phaedrus 245c ff.). It also presupposes some method of jogging our memories in a reliable way. This method is dialectic, which is a descendant of the Socratic elenchus. It is introduced in the Republic as having a special bearing on first principles—a feature it continues to possess in Aristotle (Topics 101a37–b4)—particularly on those of the mathematical sciences.

The importance of these sciences in Plato’s thought is twofold. First, they provided a compelling example of a rich body of precise knowledge organized into a deductive system of axioms, definitions, and theorems—a model of what philosophy itself might be. Second, the brilliant mathematical treatment of harmony (musical beauty) developed by Pythagoras of Samos and his followers (Aristotle, Metaphysics 987a29–8a17) suggested a role for mathematics within philosophy itself. It opened up the possibility of giving precise definitions in wholly mathematical terms of all characteristics, including such apparently vague and evaluative ones as beauty and ugliness, justice and injustice, good and evil, and the other things of which Socrates sought definitions (Republic 530d–533e).

Despite the benefits these sciences promised, however, Plato found a problem with them: they treat their first principles as “absolute” starting points, to be accepted without argument (510c–d). Yet if these starting points are false, the entire system collapses. It is here that dialectic comes in. Dialectic defends these definitional starting points—it renders them “unhypothetical”—not by deriving them from something yet more primitive (which is impossible, since they are “starting” points), but by defending them against all objections, by solving all the aporiai, or problems, to which they give rise (534b–c, 437a). With the objections solved, our intellectual vision is cleared and we are able then to see the forms these definitions define in something like the way we did before our souls became embodied (540a–b).

In the process of their dialectical defense, the definitions themselves also undergo conceptual revamping, so that their consistency with one another—and hence their immunity to dialectical (elenctic) refutation—is revealed and assured. This enables the philosopher (to whom the craft of dialectic belongs) to knit them all together into a single unified theory of everything that exhibits “their kinship with one another and with the nature of what is” (537c). It is this unified, holistic theory that provides the philosopher—and him alone—with genuine knowledge (533d–534a).

The first principle of this entire theory, Plato claims, the greatest object of knowledge (505a), is the form of the good, which seems to be an ideal of rational order or unity expressed in mathematical terms. It is the model the philosopher uses to design his ideally just and happy Kallipolis (540a–b). On a larger scale, it also provides the maker of the cosmos—the Demiurge—with the knowledge he needs to perform his cosmic task (Timaeus 29e ff.). For even the gods are bound by the objective truths and values embodied in the forms (Euthyphro 10a ff.).

FORMS AND THE GOOD

In the discussion of music and poetry in Republic 2, Socrates says: “You and I are not poets at present, Adeimantus, but we are founding a city. And it is appropriate for the founders to know the patterns on which the poets must base their stories, and from which they must not deviate. But they should not themselves make up any poems” (378e–379a). Adeimantus responds by asking what these patterns for stories about the gods actually are. Socrates’ lengthy answer may be summed up without much loss as follows: no bad images of “what the gods and heroes are like” (377e); only stories that will make the guardians “least likely to fear death” (386a); no “terrible and frightening names for the underworld” (387b–c); no “lamentations of famous men” who have suffered defeat and died (387e); no representation of “worthwhile people as overcome by laughter” (388e–389a); no representation of gods or heroes as failing “to rule over the pleasures of drink, sex, and food for themselves” (389d–e); none of the “headstrong things that private individuals say to their rulers in works of prose or poetry” (390a); no imitators except “the pure imitator of the good person” (397d); no musical harmonies except the Dorian and Phrygian (399a); no music played on flutes, triangular lutes, harps, or no “multi-stringed or polyharmonic instruments” (399c); no rhythms except those appropriate to “a life that is ordered and courageous” (399d).

The way the philosopher reaches these patterns, moreover, is clear. He looks at the effects that various kinds of poetry have on a guardian’s soul. He determines what kind of soul the guardians should have by looking to the role of guardians in the good city (500b–501c, 618b–e). And he determines what that role should be by looking to the good itself, since it is only through knowing it that he knows any other kind of good at all (534b–c).

The patterns the philosopher reaches in this way are forms. But they are, as we have seen, quite unspecific: they are not detailed blueprints for actual poems. All they determine are the features that a good poem must have. The same, presumably, is true of the forms of other things. Thus the philosopher’s pattern of an F simply specifies the features an F must have, or must lack, if it is to be good.

To see more clearly what such a form or pattern is, we turn to the allegory of the sun:

 

What gives truth to the things known and the power to know to the knower is the form of the good. And as the cause of knowledge and truth, you must think of it as an object of knowledge. Both knowledge and truth are beautiful things. But if you are to think correctly, you must think of the good as other and more beautiful than they. In the visible realm, light and sight are rightly thought to be sunlike, but wrongly thought to be the sun. So, here it is right to think of knowledge and truth as goodlike, but wrong to think that either of them is the good—for the state of the good is yet more honored. (508e–509a)

The form of the good, then, is something like a self-illuminating object that can shed the intelligible analogue of light on other objects of knowledge—other paradigms—in such a way as to render them intelligible: it is an intelligible object that is somehow a condition of the intelligibility of other things. This suggests that the “light” the good itself gives off is something like rational or logical order, and that it itself is a paradigm of such order.

A second side of the sun allegory is about reality and its nature:

 

The sun, I think you would say, not only gives visible things the power to be seen but also provides for their coming-to-be, growth, and nourishment—although it is not itself coming to be. . . . Therefore, you should also say that not only do the objects of knowledge owe their being known to the good, but their existence and being are also due to it; although the good is not being, but something yet beyond being, superior to it in rank and power. (509b)

Visible things—including the sun—are components of the visible realm. But the sun has a very special role therein: without it there would be no such realm. The same holds of the form of the good considered as a paradigm of rational order: it is a component of the intelligible realm, without which there would be no such realm. Hence its superior rank.

The form of the good is a standard or paradigm, then, that enables the philosopher to determine what poetical, political, or any other kind of goodness is. That is why other types of expertise need philosophy. Consider shoemaking, for example. The shoemaker knows how to make a shoe—he has access to the form of a shoe (596b). But he does not, qua shoemaker, know how to make a good shoe—one that reliably contributes to human happiness. For that he must turn to the philosopher, since only he can judge the goodness of the cities of which shoemakers, and all other experts, must form a part if human happiness is to be reliably achieved. That, and the philosopher’s need for the sustenance and protection these experts provide, is what makes the good city possible in Plato’s view (369b ff.).

SPECIALIZATION AND THE STRUCTURE OF KALLIPOLIS

We might expect that Socrates’ first step would be to draft a set of laws for Kallipolis. Instead, he focuses almost exclusively on designing a social structure that will dispose all the citizens to virtue. The reason for this is ultimately psychological. Socrates thinks that unless socialization (including education) makes people’s appetites and emotions as responsive as possible to reason, so that they acquire civic virtue, no system of laws will be effective, but that once they have acquired such virtue, legislation by philosopher-kings is a routine matter (422e–427d). Put the other way around, he believes that the threat posed to political good order by lawless or unnecessary appetites is the greatest political evil of all. It is this belief that explains so much that we are likely to find most abhorrent in the Republic, such as the lies of the rulers, the critique of the family and private property, and the censorship of art. Of more immediate relevance, it is also what explains the sort of labor specialization that Socrates claims must be mandatory in Kallipolis.

In Republic 2 through 5, Socrates accepts unique aptitudes—a descriptive principle according to which each person is born with a natural aptitude for a unique craft (454d, 455e). On the basis of it, he also accepts strong specialization—a normative principle requiring everyone in Kallipolis to practice exclusively throughout life the unique craft for which he has a natural aptitude, on the grounds that better products will be produced in greater abundance, ensuring greater well-being (370a–b, 374a–c, 394e, 423c–d, 433a, 443b–c, 453b). Nonetheless, he eventually seems to abandon these views, or to accept them only in a much more restricted form.

What Socrates does finally accept is the upper-bound doctrine, according to which a person’s ruling desires set a unique upper limit to his cognitive development. Indeed, this doctrine, as we saw in the allegory of the cave, is the very cornerstone of his psychological theory. Moreover, because he accepts it, he also accepts weak specialization, which states that each person in Kallipolis must practice exclusively, throughout life, whichever of the three crafts—producing, guardianship, or ruling—demands of him the highest level of cognitive development of which he is capable: money-lovers must be producers of some kind; honor-lovers must be guardians; philosophers must be kings (434a–b).

That is why, as we learn in Republic 4, strong specialization was merely a provisional first stab at its weaker analogue and is explicitly replaced by it. If all the practitioners of the various ordinary crafts exchanged tools, that would not do “any great harm to the city” (434a). If the producers, guardians, and rulers did the same, on the other hand, it would “destroy the city” (434a–b). For strong specialization was never anything more than “a sort of image of justice” (443c), whereas weak specialization is its very essence: a soul is just if its three constituent parts (reason, spirit, appetite) obey this doctrine, as is a city when its parts (rulers, guardians, producers) do the same (434c, 443c–d).

THE LIES OF THE RULERS

On a couple of occasions, Socrates tells us that the rulers of Kallipolis will often find it necessary or useful to lie to the guardians and producers. The specter of Thrasymachean false ideology and exploitation is immediately raised. In this section, we shall try to determine how large an obstacle it poses to the ethical acceptability of Plato’s politics.

At the end of Republic 2, Socrates distinguishes between two types of lies or falsehoods. A “true lie,” or a “real lie” (382a, 382c), is a lie told by someone “about the most important things to what is most important in himself ” (382a–b). A real lie, therefore, must so mislead reason, which is the most important part of the soul, as to prevent the soul from achieving its overall good (441e–442c). A “lie in words,” by contrast, is a “sort of imitation” of a genuine lie (382b–c) that can be used to prevent people from doing something bad out of ignorance or insanity (382c–d).

What we have to imagine, then, is something like this: B is attempting to do x, falsely believing, because he is mad or ignorant, that it is good to do it. A knows that it is not good for B to do x, and so tells B something that he himself knows to be false in order to prevent B from doing it. A has lied to B. But B does not come to have a false belief about the good in the rational part of his soul as a result. Indeed, he is steered toward the good, not away from it.

A genuine lie misleads reason about the good. A verbal lie may seem to do the same—especially to the person (B in our example) who discovers he has been misled. For B, of course, believes that doing x is a good thing to do. That is why a verbal lie is a “sort of imitation” of a genuine lie. But it is not a pure lie because it does not in fact mislead reason about the good. The verbal lie comes “after” the genuine lie (382b–c), because A cannot reliably lie in words until he knows the form of the good and is in a position to tell genuine lies that mislead reason about it. That is why everyone except the philosopher-kings must avoid lies altogether (389b–c).

That the lies of the rulers are all intended to be verbal rather than genuine is made clear by Socrates’ examples. One of these is the well-known myth of the metals (414b–415d). Since it is referred to as “one of those useful lies we were talking about a while ago” (414b–c), it is clearly intended to be verbal. Its function is to tie the members of Kallipolis to one another by bonds of love or friendship (415d). But their friendship is in fact well founded in mutual self-interest. So, this lie fits our account. Those who believe it do not come to believe a genuine lie, for the belief benefits them and leads them toward the good, not away from it.

We last hear about the lies of the rulers in Republic 5 in connection with the lottery secretly rigged by the rulers to ensure that the best men have sex with the best women as frequently as possible (459c–460a). Here again the lie that luck, not planning, controls the sexual lottery is intended to be verbal, since it is supposed to benefit the city as a whole by preserving the quality of the guardian class. One cannot help feeling, however, that Plato’s intentions are less than well realized here. For sex is something even honor-loving guardians enjoy—that is why getting to have it often is a reward for them (460b, 468b–c). Consequently, the loss of it, which inferior guardians suffer in Kallipolis, is a real loss—one, moreover, for which they are not compensated.

This defect in Kallipolis is surely a minor one, however. Plato has, for contingent historical reasons, simply chosen a less than optimum solution to the problem at hand. For he has no objection to sex per se—when guardians are beyond the age of reproduction, they are allowed to have sex with anyone they want, provided they avoid incest (461b–c). Hence contraception would provide a better solution to the eugenics problem than rigged lotteries.

To grasp the philosophical significance of all this, we need to draw a few rough and ready distinctions. If the subjects in a society falsely believe they are happier there than elsewhere, in part because the worldview they have been taught is false and known to be false by their rulers, they are the victims of false ideology. If, on the other hand, they believe truly that they are happier, but do so because they have been taught to accept a worldview that is false and known to be false by their rulers, their ideology is falsely sustained. Finally, if they believe they are happier there and their belief is both true and sustained by a true worldview, they and their society are ideologyfree. Because the lies of the rulers are verbal lies, it is clear that the producers and guardians who believe them are not the victims of false ideology. But because what they believe is false, and known by the philosopher-kings to be false, their ideology is falsely sustained.

The worldviews available to the producers and guardians in Kallipolis are intended to be as close to the truth, however, as their natural abilities and ruling desires allow. So, although the producers and guardians do not see their values or their place in Kallipolis with complete clarity, their vision is as undistorted as their natures—fully developed by education—allow.

It is obvious that everyone has a self-interested reason to avoid a society in which he is the victim of false ideology. That, after all, is the gist of Thrasymachus’ argument. But it is not so clear that everyone has a reason to avoid one in which his ideology is falsely sustained—especially if the degree of falsehood involved is minimal. Indeed, it may be rational for him to prefer such a society to one that is altogether ideology-free. It all depends on what his natural abilities are and what he most wants in life. If what he most wants is the pleasure of making money or the pleasure of being honored, for example, he has every reason to trade some truth in his worldview for more of his own favorite pleasure. Indeed, if he lacks the natural ability to escape ideology altogether, he may have no choice in the matter.

So, the fact that the ideologies of the guardians and producers are falsely sustained while the philosopher-kings are ideology-free seems to be a strength in Kallipolis, rather than a weakness. There, and only there, do honor-lovers and money-lovers get the benefits of the freedom from ideology of which they are themselves incapable.

PRIVATE LIFE AND PRIVATE PROPERTY

On his return in Republic 5 to the topic of the way of life appropriate to the guardians, Socrates raises the question of how female guardians should be trained and educated. Should they reduce the amount of work required of the males by sharing their duties, or should they “stay indoors and look after the house” (451d)? It is argued by Socrates’ critic, as it has been throughout the ages, that a difference in reproductive roles does indeed entail a difference in social ones. Socrates sees through this, however, pointing out that it is not clear that one’s role in reproduction has anything to do with one’s aptitude for a type of work or occupation (454d–e). Hence, in Kallipolis, women will not be confined to the house but trained in the craft for which their natural aptitude is highest.

These provisions are certainly enlightened, even by our own standards, but because they form a part of the discussion of guardian women, it may seem that they are intended to apply only to female guardians, not to female producers. Stray remarks that have clear application to the latter, however, suggest that this may not be the case. Specialization, for example, is said to apply to “every child, woman, free person, craftsman, ruler, and subject” (433d1–5). The implication is that female producers will be trained in the occupation for which they are naturally best suited. Since Socrates implies that there are women with a natural aptitude for carpentry (454d), explicitly mentions female physicians, and claims that natural aptitudes for each occupation are to be found in both sexes (455d–e), it seems that female producers are intended to be apprenticed in an appropriate occupation in precisely the same way as the males.

It must be conceded, however, that Plato is not a feminist. He shows no interest in liberating women as such and implies that they are generally inferior to men (455c–d). Moreover, his casual remarks reveal a streak of unregenerate sexism and misogyny (431b–c, 469d, 557c, 563b). But these are relatively small matters and do not affect the general point that in Kallipolis men and women with the same natural assets will receive the same education and have access to the same careers. Still, Plato is regrettably vague about the producers, whether male or female, and has left us somewhat in the dark on the important question of who will do the housework and rear the children if both parents are employed full-time outside the household.

In the case of the guardians, he is more forthcoming, although what he describes may not appeal to us. If the guardians and producers were in competition for the same social goods, producers would fare very badly, since the guardians are armed and trained for warfare in a way that the producers are not (419a). Hence the guardians are segregated from the producers and denied both private property and private family life (the objects of the producers’ ruling appetitive desires), on the grounds that “if they acquire private land, houses, and money themselves, they will be household managers and farmers, instead of guardians—hostile masters of the other citizens instead of their allies” (417a–b). The result is all the things that are likely to estrange us most from the Republic: sex by lottery as part of a state-sponsored eugenics program; state-run “rearing pens” for guardian offspring (451c–461e); and the totalitarian domination of the private sphere by the public.

Part of what has led Plato in this unattractive direction, to be sure, is his profound suspicion of the appetites and the politically destructive potential of greed and self-interest. Removing the things that stimulate them therefore becomes appealing. Even so, it is difficult not to see the cure as at least as bad as—if not worse than—the disease.

CENSORSHIP

The most important political institutions in Kallipolis, or in any other society, in Socrates’ view, are educational. The “one great thing,” he says, is education and upbringing. Hence “what the overseers of our city must cling to, not allow to become corrupted without their noticing it, and guard against everything, is this: there must be no innovation in musical or physical training that goes against the established order” (423d–424c). It should come as no surprise, therefore, that having completed the account of his own revolutionary educational proposals, and having justified them by showing that they promote both maximal justice and maximal happiness in those who receive them, Socrates should turn in Republic 10 to attack his competition—the poets and playwrights who were the purveyors of traditional Greek ethical education. The philosophers, not the poets, he argues, are the true teachers of virtue.

The reasons he gives are these: first of all, being able to imitate virtue or virtuous people in rhythms and rhymes that please and entertain most people does not qualify one to teach human beings how to live. The poet or dramatist writes for a nonspecialist audience. Hence he must employ a conceptual framework similar to theirs. Character, motive, plot—all must be drawn from folk psychology; not, say, from cognitive science or whatever the true theory of the soul turns out to be. This means that art represents people and their motives and actions, not necessarily as they really are, but only as they seem to people without specialist training. The languages of art are not, then, the technical mathematics-like language of Platonic truth. The scientist, or philosopher-king, by contrast, is free of this constraint, since his is primarily an audience of fellow specialists (601a–b, 603b–605c).

Second, poetry and drama, like all art, aim to provide a certain characteristic pleasure or satisfaction (606b), which on Plato’s view, as on Freud’s, is related to repression. Art enables us to satisfy without reproach or shame the very desires we must repress in real life. These are characteristically appetitive desires, especially sexual ones. This might plausibly be taken to entail that representations of ethically good people do not provide the kind of satisfaction art typically provides and are not what a poet needs to know how to produce (604e–605a). If we suppose, as Plato does (485d), that even artistic indulgence of repressed desires strengthens them and weakens the repressive mechanisms, we will see reason here to mistrust art in general (605b, 606b).

Finally, we must look at the poet himself, and why he writes. Plato is confident that no one would be satisfied merely to represent life if he knew how to live it well, or could teach others how to do so (599b–601a). If we think again of the characteristic pleasure art provides, his view becomes intelligible and, again, rather like a view of Freud’s. A life devoted to making things that provide a fantasy satisfaction for unnecessary appetites could not rank very highly among lives.

These arguments are unlikely simply to command our assent. But even if we find them inconclusive, they extend the right invitation to philosophers who think that art has something to teach us about how to live: develop metaphysics, epistemology, psychology, and politics, on the basis of which it will be clear that the knowledge a good poet or dramatist needs is relevant to ethics. It is precisely as such an invitation, indeed, that Plato himself seems to understand them (607d–e).

FREEDOM AND AUTONOMY

A person’s needs, wants, and interests are determined by the natural genetic lottery, by education and upbringing, and by actual circumstances. They also depend on his beliefs, which in turn depend to some extent on the same factors as do his needs, wants, and interests themselves. His real interests are those he would form under optimal conditions—those in which his needs are satisfied, he is neither maltreated nor coerced nor the victim of false ideology, and he is as aware as possible of his actual circumstances and the real alternatives to them. Happiness is optimal satisfaction of real interests in the long term.

The relevance of this picture to the Republic is no doubt clear. For Kallipolis has emerged as a community intended by Plato to provide optimal conditions of the type in question. Each of its members has his needs satisfied, is neither maltreated nor coerced nor the victim of false ideology, and is educated and trained so as to develop a conception of the world and his place in it that is as close to the truth as his nature—fully developed with an eye to his maximal happiness—permits. Each has his ruling desires satisfied throughout life. Thus each develops his real interests and is made really happy.

Even when we bear all that in mind, the Republic is still likely to feel authoritarian and repressive. Some of that is due to controversial beliefs we bring to it. For example, we are inclined to presuppose that no amount of knowledge of the way the world is validates or underwrites a unique conception of the good (we cannot derive ought from is, value from fact). Different conceptions are determined by what different individuals happen to want or prefer. The state exists, not to judge among these conceptions, but to allow each individual to realize his own conception as far as is compatible with others’ realizing theirs to the same extent. In this way, the state at once respects the individuality of its members and treats them equally. An activity, institution, or issue is paradigmatically political for us, indeed, if it pertains to disputes between people who may have different conceptions of the good, yet must coexist and have dealings with one another in the same community or the same world. Individual freedom, on this broadly liberal conception, is freedom to do what one wants; freedom to live in accordance with a conception of the good that is rooted in one’s own desires, preferences, or choices. And a state is free to the extent that it limits individual freedom only to guarantee equal freedom to all its members. It is not surprising, then, that when in imagination we project ourselves into Kallipolis, we do feel repressed and unfree.

This conception of political freedom is not the only one, however. Freedom to do what we want—instrumental freedom—is certainly important. But its importance can be undermined by the very desires on which it depends. For if we would not have the desires we are free to satisfy had we engaged in a process of ideal, rational deliberation, then being free to satisfy them seems less worth caring about. If our desires, like those of a drug addict, can make us unfree, instrumental freedom seems insufficient for real freedom or autonomy.

Perhaps, then, we should think instead in terms of deliberative freedom, which is the freedom to have and to satisfy those desires we would choose to have if we were aware of the relevant facts, were thinking clearly, and were free from distorting influences. If so, we can see at once that a state that guaranteed deliberative freedom might look and feel very repressive to someone solely concerned about instrumental freedom. It would very much depend on what his desires happened to be. Since the psychological and political cost of repression is high, however, we can well imagine that an enlightened state, committed to deliberative freedom, would want to devote much of its resources to education and training so as to ensure that its members are as close to being deliberatively rational as possible. Such a state would already begin to look a little like Kallipolis, and to share some of its priorities.

In any case, it seems clear that Kallipolis is intended to provide its members with as much deliberative freedom as their natures, fully developed in optimal conditions, permit:

 

Why do you think someone is reproached for menial work or handicraft? Or shall we say that it is for no other reason than because the best element is naturally weak in him, so that it cannot rule the beasts within him, but can only serve them and learn what flatters them? . . . In order to ensure, then, that someone like that is also ruled by something similar to what rules the best person, we say that he should be the slave of that best person who has the divine ruler within himself. It is not to harm the slave that we say he should be ruled, as Thrasymachus supposed was true of all subjects, but because it is better for everyone to be ruled by a divine and wise ruler—preferably one that is his own and that he has inside himself—otherwise one imposed on him from outside, so that we may all be as alike and as friendly as possible, because we are all captained by the same thing. (590c–d; also 395b–c)

Thus, even if we retain our liberal suspicion about the possibility of a science of values, we might still, by coming to see merit in the idea of deliberative freedom, also come to see the Republic, not as predominantly a totalitarian hymn to the benefits of repression and unfreedom, but as an attempt to design a city whose members enjoy as much real happiness, and as much real freedom, as possible.

1 See Glossary of Terms s.v. craft.

2 See Glossary of Terms s.v. sophists.

3 First-time readers may want to skim over the remainder of the Introduction, returning to it for more careful study after they have read the Republic itself.

Select Bibliography

 

Adam, J. The Republic of Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1902. (Critical edition of the Greek text, with notes and commentary.)

Annas, J. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981.

Bobonich, C. Plato’s Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.

Burnyeat, M. “Platonism and Mathematics: A Prelude to Discussion.” In Mathematics and Metaphysics in Aristotle, edited by A. Graeser, pp. 213–40. Bern: Paul Haupt, 1987.

———. “Plato on Why Mathematics is Good for the Soul.” In Mathematics and Necessity, edited by T. Smiley, pp. 1–81. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

———. “Plato.” Proceedings of the British Academy 111 (2000): 1–22.

Cooper, J. M. “The Psychology of Justice in Plato.” American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977): 151–7. Reprinted in his Reason and Emotion, pp. 138–50. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.

———. “Plato’s Theory of Human Motivation.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 1 (1984): 3–21. Reprinted in his Reason and Emotion, pp. 118–37. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999.

Ferrari, G. City and Soul in Plato’s Republic. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, 2003.

Fine, G., ed. Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

———. Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

Irwin, T. Plato’s Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.

Kraut, R., ed. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

———, ed. Plato’s Republic: Critical Essays. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Little-field, 1997.

Moravcsik, J., and P. Temko, eds. Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1982.

Murdoch, I. The Fire and the Sun: Why Plato Banished the Artists. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.

Popper, K. The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971.

Reeve, C. Philosopher-Kings: The Argument of Plato’s Republic. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988.

Sachs, D. “A Fallacy in Plato’s Republic.” Philosophical Review 72 (1963): 141–58.

Vlastos, G. “The Theory of Social Justice in the Polis in Plato’s Republic.” In Interpretations of Plato: A Swarthmore Symposium, edited by H. North, pp. 1–40. Leiden: Brill, 1977.

———. “Elenchus and Mathematics: A Turning-point in Plato’s Philosophical Development.” American Journal of Philology 109 (1988): 362–96.

Wagner, E., ed. Essays on Plato’s Psychology. Lanham, Md.: Lexington Books, 2001.

White, N. A Companion to Plato’s Republic. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1979.

———. Individual and Conflict in Greek Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.

Synopsis

 

BOOK 1

On his way home from a religious festival, Socrates meets Polemarchus and accompanies him to the house of his aged father, Cephalus. • Socrates and Cephalus discuss the burdens of old age. Cephalus claims that, while these burdens are eased by wealth, it is people’s characters and habits, not their ages, that determine what their lives are like. Wealth is mostly important, he claims, because it reduces the likelihood of being tempted into injustice by poverty and so lessens the fear of what will happen after death. This leads to a discussion of justice, which will itself culminate—many books later—in a myth about the afterlife (Book 10). • Cephalus claims that justice consists in speaking the truth and paying one’s debts. Before he can respond to Socrates’ criticism of his definition, Polemarchus interrupts. Cephalus hands over the argument to him and goes off to attend to a sacrifice to the gods. An examination of Polemarchus follows, in the course of which he is forced to abandon a number of different views about justice that he has adopted along the way. • Thrasymachus demands that Socrates give his own positive account of justice but is persuaded to give an account himself instead. Justice, he claims, is what is advantageous for the stronger. Thrasymachus defends it with two separate arguments (338d–341a, 343a–344c), which Socrates then attempts to refute.

BOOK 2

Unsatisfied with the outcome of Book 1, Glaucon and Adeimantus renew Thrasymachus’ views. In response, Socrates must show that justice is choiceworthy (a) because of itself, and (b) because of its consequences (357a–358a). Socrates does not complete his argument for (a) until the end of Book 9. • Socrates shifts the debate from individual justice to political justice. He will describe an ideal or completely good city—Kallipolis. Having located justice in it, he will then look for it in the soul. • The first city he describes is dismissed by Glaucon as fit only for pigs, not for sophisticated Athenians. • The second city is more luxurious. But the presence in it of appetites for more than the necessities provided in its simpler predecessor leads to civil faction and war. To prevent these from destroying the city, soldier-police are needed. These are the guardians. • The natural assets they need and the education they must have are next described. Since musical training begins before physical training, its content—more specifically the sorts of stories that the future guardians should hear about gods and heroes—is the first item of business (377e).

BOOK 3

The discussion of these stories continues. Once complete, Socrates turns to the content of stories about human beings, only to postpone his discussion until Book 10. (He explains why at 392a–c.) • The appropriate style for these stories to have and the appropriate harmonies and rhythms for lyric odes and songs are characterized. • Physical training is next. • The final topic is the selection of rulers (including the “myth of the metals”), and the housing and lifestyles of the guardians (412b–417b).

BOOK 4

A question from Adeimantus about the happiness of the guardians leads Socrates to clarify the goal of Kallipolis, which is not to make any one group of citizens outstandingly happy at the expense of others, but to make everyone as happy as his nature allows (421c). This goal will be achieved, he argues, if the guardians protect the system of elementary education described in Books 2 and 3. For it is what provides the training in political virtue without which no system of laws or constitution can hope to achieve anything worthwhile (423c–427a). • The place of religion in Kallipolis is then very briefly discussed (427b–c). • Kallipolis is pronounced complete (427d). Since it is completely good (427e), it must have all the virtues of a city (see 352d–354a): wisdom, courage, temperance, and justice. By the time that search for them is concluded (434d), they have all been identified with distinct structural features of Kallipolis. • This leads to the argument for the division of the soul into three elements—appetitive, spirited, and rational—that correspond to the three major classes in Kallipolis—producers, guardians, and rulers (435c–441c). Once this argument is in place, it remains to find the virtues in the soul and to show that they are the same structural features of it as of Kallipolis (441c–444e). • Glaucon is ready at this point to pronounce justice more choiceworthy than injustice, but Socrates is not (445a–b). In his view, the question cannot be answered until much more work has been done on virtue and vice.

BOOK 5

The discussion of that topic is interrupted by Polemarchus and the other interlocutors, all of whom want Socrates to explain the remark he made (423e4–424a2) about the guardians sharing their women and children. Socrates’ lengthy response occupies the majority of the book. In it, he makes the revolutionary proposal that children should be brought up by the city rather than by their biological parents, and that men and women with the same natural abilities should receive the same education and training and do the same kind of work, including guarding and ruling. • The smallest change that would transform an already existing city into Kallipolis, Socrates now argues, is for its kings or rulers to become philosophers, or vice versa. The remainder of Book 5 is the beginning of Socrates’ portrait of philosophers, which continues until the end of Book 7. It consists of a complex argument intended to show that only they can have access to forms, and that without such access knowledge is impossible (474c4–480a13).

BOOK 6

Real philosophers are contrasted with those popularly called philosophers. • The former must master the most important subjects (503e), the ones that lead to knowledge of the form of the good (504e–505b). • Socrates cannot explain directly what this is, but in the sun and line analogies he tries to give an indirect account of them (507a–511e).

BOOK 7

Book 7 begins with the famous allegory of the cave, which is intended to fit together with the sun and line (517b), by illustrating the effects of education on the soul (514a). • The discussion of the education of the philosophers continues. Primary education in musical and physical training and elementary mathematics (535a–537b) is followed by two or three years of compulsory physical training (537b–c), ten years of education in the mathematical sciences (537c–d, 522c–531d), five years of training in dialectic (537d–540a, 531e–535a), and fifteen years of practical political training (539e–540a). After such education, its recipients are ready to see the good itself and to be philosopher-kings (540a).

BOOK 8

The description of Kallipolis and the person whose character resembles it—the philosopher-king—is now complete. So, Socrates returns to the argument interrupted at the beginning of Book 5. He describes four types of people and four types of constitutions that result when people of these types rule a city. He presents these as four stages in the increasing corruption or decline of Kallipolis, explaining why Kallipolis will decline by appeal to the Muses’ story of the “geometrical number” (546a–547a). • The first of the defective cities Socrates describes is a timocracy, which is ruled by people who are themselves ruled by the spirited element in their souls. • The second is an oligarchy, which is ruled by people ruled by their necessary appetites. • The third is a democracy, which is ruled by people ruled by their unnecessary appetites. • The worst city of all is a tyranny, which is ruled by someone ruled by his lawless unnecessary appetites.

BOOK 9

A lengthy description of the tyrant begins the book. Socrates is then ready to respond to the challenge Glaucon raised in Book 2. • His response consists of three complex arguments. The first (580a–c) appeals to the description of the five cities and the five corresponding character types. It concludes that a philosopher-king is the happiest and most just of people, a timocrat second, an oligarch third, a democrat fourth, and a tyrant least happy and least just. The second argument (580d–583b) appeals to the triadic division of the soul. Socrates argues that a philosopher’s assessment of the relative pleasantness of his life and those of money-lovers and honor-lovers is more reliable than their assessments of the relative pleasantness of his life and theirs. The third argument (583b–588a) uses the metaphysical theory developed in Books 5 through 7, together with the psychological theory of Book 4, to develop a complex theory of pleasure. It concludes that a philosopher’s pleasures are truer and purer than those of a money-lover or an honor-lover.

BOOK 10

The kind of poetry about human beings permitted in Kallipolis—postponed in Book 3 (392a–c)—can now be revisited. Given the importance attributed to musical and physical training (424b–425a), this topic is not anticlimactic, but rather the moment at which Socrates’ new, philosophy-based education confronts the traditional, poetry-based one. Central to the discussion is a new account of mimesis—imitation—based on the metaphysical theories of Books 5 through 7. • The next topic is the immortality of the soul. • Finally, by appeal to the myth of Er, Socrates argues that the good consequences of justice, both in this life and the next, far outweigh those of injustice. This completes the argument that justice is choiceworthy both for its own sake and for its consequences, and so belongs in the best of the three classes of goods that Glaucon distinguished.

Note to the Reader

 

All proper names and place names are listed, most of them with brief identifications, in the Glossary and Index of Names. Unfamiliar concepts are defined in the Glossary of Terms. Marginal page numbers, known as “Stephanus” page numbers (after an earlier editor of Plato’s works), are standardly used in scholarly citations. Line numbers, which are approximate in translations (including this one), refer to John Burnet, Platonis Opera, vols. I–V (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1900–1907). The basis for the present translation is S. R. Slings, Platonis Rempublicam (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003).

Book 1

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION BEGINS: I went down to the Piraeus yesterday with Glaucon, the son of Ariston, to say a prayer to the goddess,1 and also [327a] because I wanted to see how they would manage the festival, since they were holding it for the first time. I thought the procession of the local residents was beautiful, but the show put on by the Thracians was no less so, in my view. [5] After we had said our prayer and watched the procession, we started back toward town.2 Then Polemarchus, the son of Cephalus, saw us from a distance [b] as we were hurrying homeward, and told his slave boy to run and ask us to wait for him. The boy caught hold of my cloak3 from behind.

 

SLAVE: Polemarchus wants you to wait.

 

I turned around and asked where he was.[5]

 

SLAVE: He is coming up behind you; please wait for him.

 

GLAUCON: All right, we will.

 

Shortly after that, Polemarchus caught up with us. Adeimantus, Glaucon’s [c] brother, was with him, and so were Niceratus, the son of Nicias, and some others, all of whom were apparently on their way from the procession.

 

POLEMARCHUS: It looks to me, Socrates, as if you two are hurrying to get away to town. [5]

 

SOCRATES: That isn’t a bad guess.

 

POLEMARCHUS: But do you see how many we are?

 

SOCRATES: Certainly.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Well, then, either you must prove yourselves stronger than all these people or you will have to stay here.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Isn’t there another alternative still: that we persuade you that you should let us go?

 

POLEMARCHUS: But could you persuade us, if we won’t listen?

 

GLAUCON: There is no way we could.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Well, we won’t listen; you had better make up your mind to that.

 

[328a] ADEIMANTUS: You mean to say you don’t know that there is to be a torch race on horseback for the goddess tonight?

 

SOCRATES: On horseback? That is something new. Are they going to race [5] on horseback and hand the torches on in relays, or what?

 

POLEMARCHUS: In relays. And, besides, there will be an all-night celebration that will be worth seeing. We will get up after dinner and go to see the festivities. We will meet lots of young men there and have a discussion. So [b] stay and do as we ask.

 

GLAUCON: It looks as if we will have to stay.

 

SOCRATES: If you think so, we must.

 

So, we went to Polemarchus’ house, and there we found Lysias and Euthydemus[5] , the brothers of Polemarchus, and what is more, Thrasymachus of Chalcedon was there too, and Charmantides of Paeania, and Clitophon, the son of Aristonymus. Polemarchus’ father, Cephalus, was also inside, and I thought he looked quite old. You see, I hadn’t seen him for some time. He [c] was sitting on a sort of chair with cushions and had a wreath on his head, as he had been offering a sacrifice in the courtyard. We sat down beside him, since some chairs were arranged in a circle there. As soon as he saw me, Cephalus[5] greeted me:

 

Socrates, you don’t often come down to the Piraeus to see us. Yet you should. If it were still easy for me to make the trip to town, you wouldn’t have to come here. On the contrary, we would come to you. But as it is, [d] you ought to come here more often. I want you to know, you see, that in my case at least, as the other pleasures—the bodily ones—wither away, my appetites for discussions and their pleasures grow stronger.4 So please do as I [5] ask: have your conversation with these young men, and stay here with us, as you would with your close friends and relatives.

 

SOCRATES: I certainly will, Cephalus. In fact, I enjoy engaging in discussion [e] with the very old. I think we should learn from them—since they are like people who have traveled a road that we too will probably have to follow—what the road is like, whether rough and difficult or smooth and easy. And I would be particularly glad to find out from you what you think about it, since you have reached the point in life the poets call old age’s [5] threshold.5 Is it a difficult time of life? What have you to report about it?

 

CEPHALUS: By Zeus, Socrates, I will tell you exactly what I think. You see, [392a] a number of us who are more or less the same age often get together, so as to preserve the old saying. 6 When they meet, the majority of our members lament, longing for the lost pleasures of their youth and reminiscing about sex, drinking parties, feasts, and the other things that go along with them. [5] They get irritated, as if they had been deprived of very great things, and had lived well then but are not living now. Some others, too, even moan about the abuse heaped on old people by their relatives, and for that reason [b] recite a litany of all the evils old age has caused them. But I don’t think they blame the real cause, Socrates. After all, if that were the cause, I too would have had the same experiences, at least as far as old age is concerned, and so would everyone else of my age. But as it is, I have met others in the past [5] who don’t feel that way—in particular, the poet Sophocles. I was once present when he was asked by someone, “How are you as far as sex goes, Sophocles? Can you still make love to a woman?” “Quiet, man,” he replied, [c] “I am very glad to have escaped from all that, like a slave who has escaped from a deranged and savage master.” I thought at the time what he said was sensible, and I still do. You see, old age brings peace and freedom from all [5] such things. When the appetites cease to stress and importune us, everything Sophocles said comes to pass, and we escape from many insane masters. But in these matters, and in those concerning one’s relatives, the real [d] cause isn’t old age, Socrates, but the way people live. If they are orderly and contented, old age, too, is only moderately onerous; if they aren’t, both old age, Socrates, and youth are hard to bear. [5]

 

I admired him for saying that, and I wanted him to tell me more, so I urged him on.

 

I imagine when you say that, Cephalus, the masses7 do not accept it. On [e] the contrary, they think you bear old age more easily, not because of the way you live, but because you are wealthy. For the wealthy, they say, have many consolations. [5]

 

CEPHALUS: That’s true, they are not convinced. And there is something in EPHALUS their objection, though not as much as they think. Themistocles’ retort is relevant here. When someone from Seriphus insulted him by saying his high reputation was due to his city, not to himself, he replied that, had he [330a] been a Seriphian, he would not be famous; but nor would the other, had he been an Athenian.8 The same account applies to those who are not rich and find old age hard to bear: a good person would not easily bear old age [5] if it were coupled with poverty, but one who wasn’t good would not be at peace with himself even if he were wealthy.

 

SOCRATES: Did you inherit most of your wealth, Cephalus, or did you make it yourself?

 

CEPHALUS: What did I make for myself, Socrates, you ask. As a moneymaker [b] I am in between my grandfather and my father.You see, my grandfather and namesake inherited about the same amount of wealth as I possess and multiplied it many times. However, my father, Lysanias, diminished [5] that amount to even less than I have now. As for me, I am satisfied to leave my sons here no less, but a little more, than I inherited.

 

SOCRATES: The reason I asked is that you do not seem particularly to love [c] money. And those who have not made it themselves are usually like that. But those who have made it themselves love it twice as much as anyone else. For just as poets love their poems and fathers their children, so those who have made money take their money seriously both as something they [5] have made themselves and—just as other people do—because it is useful. This makes them difficult even to be with, since they are unwilling to praise anything except money.

 

CEPHALUS: That’s true.

 

[d] SOCRATES: Indeed, it is. But tell me something else. What do you think is the greatest good you have enjoyed as a result of being very wealthy?

 

CEPHALUS: What I have to say probably would not persuade the masses.[5] But you are well aware, Socrates, that when someone thinks his end is near, he becomes frightened and concerned about things he did not fear before. It is then that the stories told about Hades, that a person who has been unjust here must pay the penalty there—stories he used to make fun of—[e] twist his soul this way and that for fear they are true. And whether because of the weakness of old age, or because he is now closer to what happens in Hades and has a clearer view of it, or whatever it is, he is filled with foreboding and fear, and begins to calculate and consider whether he has been [5] unjust to anyone. If he finds many injustices in his life, he often even awakes from sleep in terror, as children do, and lives in anticipation of evils [331a] to come. But someone who knows he has not been unjust has sweet good hope as his constant companion—a nurse to his old age, as Pindar says. For he puts it charmingly, Socrates, when he says that when someone lives a [5] just and pious life,

 

Sweet hope is in his heart

Nurse and companion to his age

Hope, captain of the ever-twisting

Mind of mortal men.

How amazingly well he puts that. It is in this connection I would say the [10] possession of wealth is most valuable, not for every man, but for a good and orderly one. Not cheating someone even unintentionally, not lying to him, [b] not owing a sacrifice to some god or money to a person, and as a result departing for that other place in fear—the possession of wealth makes no small contribution to this. It has many other uses, too, but putting one [5] thing against the other, Socrates, I would say that for a man with any sense, that is how wealth is most useful.

 

SOCRATES: A fine sentiment, Cephalus. But speaking of that thing itself, justice,9 are we to say it is simply speaking the truth and paying whatever [c] debts one has incurred? Or is it sometimes just to do these things, sometimes unjust? I mean this sort of thing, for example: everyone would surely [5] agree that if a man borrows weapons from a sane friend, and if he goes mad and asks for them back, the friend should not return them, and would not be just if he did. Nor should anyone be willing to tell the whole truth to someone in such a state.

 

CEPHALUS: That’s true. [d]

 

SOCRATES: Then the following is not the definition of justice: to speak the truth and repay what one has borrowed.

 

Polemarchus interrupted:

 

It certainly is, Socrates, if indeed we are to trust Simonides at all. [5]

 

CEPHALUS: Well, then, I will hand over the discussion to you, since it is time for me to look after the sacrifices.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Am I, Polemarchus, not heir of all your possessions?

 

Cephalus replied with a laugh:

 

Certainly.

 

And off he went to the sacrifice.

 

SOCRATES: Then tell us, heir to the discussion, just what Simonides said [e] about justice that you think is correct.

 

POLEMARCHUS: He said it is just to give to each what is owed to him. And a fine saying it is, in my view.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Well, now, it is not easy to disagree with Simonides, since he is a wise and godlike man. But what exactly does he mean? Perhaps you know, Polemarchus, but I do not understand. Clearly, he does not mean what we said a moment ago—namely, giving back to someone whatever he has lent to you, even if he is out of his mind when he asks for it. And yet [332a] what he has lent to you is surely something that is owed to him, isn’t it?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: But when he is out of his mind, it is, under no circumstances, [5] to be given to him?

 

POLEMARCHUS: True.

 

SOCRATES: Then it seems Simonides must have meant something else when he says that to return what is owed is just.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Something else indeed, by Zeus! He meant friends owe [10] something good to their friends, never something bad.

 

SOCRATES: I understand. You mean someone does not give a lender what he is owed by giving him gold, when the giving and taking would be [b] harmful, and both he and the lender are friends. Isn’t that what you say Simonides meant?

 

POLEMARCHUS: It certainly is.

 

SOCRATES: Now what about this? Should one also give to one’s enemies [5] whatever is owed to them?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes, by all means. What is in fact owed to them. And what an enemy owes an enemy, in my view, is also precisely what is appropriate—something bad.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, Simonides was speaking in riddles—just like a [c] poet!—when he said what justice is. For what he meant, it seems, is that it is just to give to each what is appropriate to him, and this is what he called giving him what he is owed.

 

POLEMARCHUS: What else did you think he meant?

 

SOCRATES: Then what, in the name of Zeus, do you think he would [5] answer if someone asked him: “Simonides, what owed or appropriate things does the craft10 we call medicine give, and to which things?”

 

POLEMARCHUS: Clearly, he would say it gives drugs, food, and drink to [10] bodies.

 

SOCRATES: And what owed or appropriate things does the craft we call cooking give, and to which things?

 

POLEMARCHUS: It gives pleasant flavors to food. [d]

 

SOCRATES: Good. Now what does the craft we would call justice give, and to whom or what does it give it?

 

POLEMARCHUS: If we are to follow the previous answers, Socrates, it gives benefit to friends and harm to enemies. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Does Simonides mean, then, that treating friends well and enemies badly is justice?

 

POLEMARCHUS: I believe so.

 

SOCRATES: And who is most capable of treating sick friends well and enemies [10] badly in matters of disease and health?

 

POLEMARCHUS: A doctor.

 

SOCRATES: And who can do so best in a storm at sea? [e]

 

POLEMARCHUS: A ship’s captain.11

 

SOCRATES: What about the just person? In what actions and what work is he most capable of benefiting friends and harming enemies?

 

POLEMARCHUS: In wars and alliances, I imagine. [5]

 

SOCRATES: All right. Now when people are not sick, Polemarchus, a doctor is useless to them.

 

POLEMARCHUS: True.

 

SOCRATES: And so is a ship’s captain to those who are not sailing?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes. [10]

 

SOCRATES: So to people who are not at war, a just man is useless?

 

POLEMARCHUS: No, I don’t think that at all.

 

SOCRATES: So justice is also useful in peacetime?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes, it is useful. [333a]

 

SOCRATES: And so is farming, isn’t it?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: For providing produce?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And shoemaking as well, of course?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: For the acquisition of shoes, I suppose you would say?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Tell me, then, what is justice useful for using or acquiring in peacetime?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Contracts, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: And by contracts you mean partnerships, or what?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Partnerships, of course.

 

[b] SOCRATES: So is it a just man who is a good and useful partner in a game of checkers, or an expert checkers player?

 

POLEMARCHUS: An expert checkers player.

 

SOCRATES: And in laying bricks and stones, is a just person a better and [5] more useful partner than a builder?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Well, in what kind of partnership, then, is a just person a better partner than a builder or a lyre player, in the way a lyre player is better than a just person at hitting the right notes?

 

[10] POLEMARCHUS: In money matters, I think.

 

SOCRATES: Except, I presume, Polemarchus, in using money. You see, whenever one needs to buy or sell a horse jointly, I think a horse breeder is [c] a more useful partner. Isn’t he?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: And when it is a boat, a boat builder or a ship’s captain?

 

POLEMARCHUS: It would seem so.

 

[5] SOCRATES: In what joint use of silver or gold, then, is a just person a more useful partner than anyone else?

 

POLEMARCHUS: When yours must be deposited for safekeeping, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: You mean whenever there is no need to use it, but only to keep it?

 

[10] POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So when money is not being used, that is when justice is useful [d] for it?

 

POLEMARCHUS: It looks that way.

 

SOCRATES: And when one needs to keep a pruning knife safe, justice is useful both in partnerships and for the individual. When you need to use it, however, it is the craft of vine pruning that is useful?

 

[5] POLEMARCHUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: And would you also say that when one needs to keep a shield and a lyre safe and not use them, justice is a useful thing, but when you need to use them it is the soldier’s craft or the musician’s that is useful?

 

POLEMARCHUS: I would have to.

 

SOCRATES: And so in all other cases, too, justice is useless when they are [10] in use, but useful when they are not?

 

POLEMARCHUS: It looks that way.

 

SOCRATES: Then justice cannot be something excellent, can it, my friend, [e] if it is only useful for useless things. But let’s consider the following point. Isn’t the person who is cleverest at landing a blow, whether in boxing or any other kind of fight, also cleverest at guarding against it?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.[5]

 

SOCRATES: And the one who is clever at guarding against disease is also cleverest at producing it unnoticed?

 

POLEMARCHUS: That is my view, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: And the one who is a good guardian of an army is the very [334a] one who can steal the enemy’s plans and dispositions?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So whenever someone is a clever guardian of something, he is also[5] clever at stealing it.

 

POLEMARCHUS: It seems so.

 

SOCRATES: So if a just person is clever at guarding money, he must also be clever at stealing it.

 

POLEMARCHUS: So the argument suggests, at least.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that a just person has turned out to be a kind of thief. You probably got that idea from Homer. For he loves Autolycus, the [10] maternal grandfather of Odysseus, whom he describes as better than everyone [b] at stealing and swearing false oaths.12 According to you, Homer, and Simonides, then, justice seems to be some sort of craft of stealing—one that benefits friends and harms enemies. Isn’t that what you meant?[5]

 

POLEMARCHUS: No, by Zeus, it isn’t. But I do not know anymore what I meant. I still believe this, however, that benefiting one’s friends and harming one’s enemies is justice.

 

SOCRATES: Speaking of friends, do you mean those a person believes to be [c] good and useful, or those who actually are good and useful, even if he does not believe they are, and similarly with enemies?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Probably, one loves those one considers good and useful [5] and hates those one considers bad.

 

SOCRATES: But don’t people make mistakes about this, so that lots of those who seem to them to be good and useful aren’t, and vice versa?

 

POLEMARCHUS: They do.

 

[10] SOCRATES: So, for them, good people are enemies and bad ones friends?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: All the same, it is then just for them to benefit bad people and [d] harm good ones?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: Yet good people are just and are not the sort to do injustice.

 

POLEMARCHUS: True.

 

SOCRATES: According to your account, then, it is just to do bad things to [5] those who do no injustice.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Not at all, Socrates. It is my account that seems to be bad.

 

SOCRATES: It is just, then, is it, to harm unjust people and benefit just [10] ones?

 

POLEMARCHUS: That seems better than the other view.

 

SOCRATES: Then it follows, Polemarchus, that it is just for many people—[e] the ones who are mistaken in their judgment—to harm their friends, since they are bad for them, and benefit their enemies, since they are good. And so we will find ourselves claiming the very opposite of what we said Simonides meant.

 

[5] POLEMARCHUS: Yes, that certainly follows. But let’s change our definition. For it looks as though we did not define friends and enemies correctly.

 

SOCRATES: How did we define them, Polemarchus?

 

POLEMARCHUS: We said that a friend is someone who is believed to be good.

 

SOCRATES: And how are we to change that now?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Someone who is both believed to be good and is good is [10] a friend; someone who is believed to be good, but is not, is believed to be a [335a] friend but is not. And the same goes for enemies.

 

SOCRATES: According to that account, then, a good person will be a friend and a bad one an enemy.

 

[5] POLEMARCHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So you want us to add something to what we said before about the just man. Then we said that it is just to treat friends well and enemies badly. Now you want us to add to this: to treat a friend well, provided he is good, and to harm an enemy, provided he is bad?[10]

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes, that seems well put to me.[b]

 

SOCRATES: Should a just man really harm anyone whatsoever?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course. He should harm those who are both bad and enemies.[5]

 

SOCRATES: When horses are harmed, do they become better or worse?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Worse.

 

SOCRATES: With respect to the virtue13 that makes dogs good, or to the one that makes horses good?

 

POLEMARCHUS: With respect to the one that makes horses good.

 

SOCRATES: And when dogs are harmed, they become worse with respect [10]to the virtue that makes dogs, not horses, good?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: And what about human beings, comrade; shouldn’t we say that, when they are harmed, they become worse with respect to human virtue? [c]

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But isn’t justice human virtue?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes, that’s necessarily so, too. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then, my dear Polemarchus, people who have been harmed are bound to become more unjust.

 

POLEMARCHUS: So it seems.

 

SOCRATES: Now, can musicians use music to make people unmusical? [10]

 

POLEMARCHUS: No, they can’t.

 

SOCRATES: Or can horsemen use horsemanship to make people unhorse-manlike?

 

POLEMARCHUS: No.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, can just people use justice to make people unjust? In a word, can good people use their virtue or goodness to make people bad? [d]

 

POLEMARCHUS: No, they can’t.

 

SOCRATES: For it isn’t the function of heat to cool things down, I imagine, but that of its opposite.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Nor the function of dryness to make things wet, but that of its [5] opposite.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So the function of a good person isn’t to harm, but that of his opposite.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: And a just person is a good person?

 

[10] POLEMARCHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So it isn’t the function of a just person to harm a friend or anyone else, Polemarchus, but that of his opposite, an unjust person.

 

POLEMARCHUS: I think you are absolutely right, Socrates.

 

[e] SOCRATES: So if someone tells us it is just to give to each what he is owed, and understands by this that a just man should harm his enemies and benefit his friends, the one who says it is not wise. I mean, what he says is not [5] true. For it has become clear to us that it is never just to harm anyone.

 

POLEMARCHUS: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: You and I will fight as partners, then, against anyone who tells us that Simonides, Bias, Pittacus, or any of our other wise and blessedly happy men said this.

 

[10] POLEMARCHUS: I, for my part, am willing to be your partner in the battle.

 

[336a] SOCRATES: Do you know whose saying I think it is, that it is just to benefit friends and harm enemies?

 

POLEMARCHUS: Whose?

 

[5] SOCRATES: I think it is a saying of Periander, or Perdiccas, or Xerxes, or Ismenias of Thebes, or some other wealthy man who thought he had great power.

 

POLEMARCHUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: All right. Since it has become apparent, then, that neither justice nor the just consists in benefiting friends and harming enemies, what else should one say it is?

 

Now, while we were speaking, Thrasymachus had tried many times to take [b] over the discussion but was restrained by those sitting near him, who wanted to hear our argument to the end. When we paused after what I had just said, however, he could not keep quiet any longer: crouched up like a wild beast [5] about to spring, he hurled himself at us as if to tear us to pieces. Polemarchus and I were frightened and flustered as he roared into our midst:

 

What nonsense you two have been talking all this time, Socrates! Why do you act like naïve people, giving way to one another? If you really want to [c] know what justice is, don’t just ask questions and then indulge your love of honor by refuting the answers. You know very well it is easier to ask questions than to answer them. Give an answer yourself and tell us what you say [5] the just is. And don’t tell me it is the right, the beneficial, the profitable, the [d] gainful, or the advantageous, but tell me clearly and exactly what you mean. For I won’t accept such nonsense from you.

 

His words startled me and, looking at him, I was afraid. And I think if I had [5] not seen him before he looked at me, I would have been dumbstruck.14 But as it was, I happened to look at him just as he began to be exasperated by our argument, so I was able to answer; and trembling a little, I said: [e]

 

Do not be too hard on us, Thrasymachus. If Polemarchus and I made an error in our investigation of the accounts, you may be sure we did so involuntarily. If we were searching for gold, we would never voluntarily give way to each other, if by doing so we would destroy our chance of finding [5] it. So do not think that in searching for justice, a thing more honorable than a large quantity of gold, we would foolishly give way to one another or be less than completely serious about finding it. You surely must not think that, my friend, but rather—as I do—that we are incapable of finding it. Hence it is surely far more appropriate for us to be pitied by you clever [10] people than to be given rough treatment. [337a]

When he heard that, he gave a loud sarcastic laugh:

 

By Heracles! That is Socrates’ usual irony15 for you! I knew this would happen. I even told these others earlier that you would be unwilling to answer, that you would be ironic and do anything rather than give an answer, if [5] someone questioned you.

 

SOCRATES: That is because you are a wise fellow, Thrasymachus. You knew very well if you ask someone how much twelve is, and in putting the question you warn him, “Don’t tell me, man, that twelve is twice six, or [b] three times four, or six times two, or four times three; for I won’t accept such nonsense from you”—it was obvious to you, I imagine, that no one could respond to a person who inquired in that way. But suppose he said to you: “What do you mean, Thrasymachus; am I not to give any of the [5] answers you mention, not even if twelve happens to be one of those things? You are amazing. Do you want me to say something other than the truth? Or do you mean something else?” What answer would you give him? [c]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Well, so you think the two cases are alike?

 

SOCRATES: Why shouldn’t I? But even if they are not alike, yet seem so to the person you asked, do you think he is any less likely to give the answer [5] that seems right to him, whether we forbid him to do so or not?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Is that what you are going to do, give one of the forbidden answers?

 

SOCRATES: I would not be surprised—provided it is the one that seems [10] right to me after I have investigated the matter.

 

THRASYMACHUS: What if I show you another answer about justice, one [d] that is different from all these and better than any of them? What penalty would you deserve then?

 

SOCRATES: The very one that is appropriate for someone who does not know—what else? And what is appropriate is to learn from the one who [5] does know. That, therefore, is what I deserve to suffer.

 

THRASYMACHUS: What a pleasant fellow you are! But in addition to learning, you must pay money.

 

SOCRATES: I will if I ever have any.

 

GLAUCON: He has it already. If it is a matter of money, speak, Thrasymachus. [10] We will all contribute for Socrates.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Oh yes, sure, so that Socrates can carry on as usual: he [e] gives no answer himself, and if someone else does, he takes up his account and refutes it.

 

SOCRATES: How can someone give an answer, my excellent man, when, [5] first of all, he does not know and does not claim to know, and then, even if he does have some opinion about the matter, is forbidden by no ordinary man to express any of the things he thinks? No, it is much more appropriate [338a] for you to answer, since you say you do know and can tell us. Don’t be obstinate. Give your answer as a favor to me and do not begrudge your teaching to Glaucon and the others.

 

While I was saying this, Glaucon and the others begged him to do as I asked. [5] Thrasymachus clearly wanted to speak in order to win a good reputation, since he thought he had a very good answer. But he pretended to want to win a victory at my expense by having me do the answering. However, he agreed in the end, and then said:

 

[b] That is Socrates’ wisdom for you: he himself isn’t willing to teach but goes around learning from others and isn’t even grateful to them.

 

SOCRATES: When you say I learn from others, you are right, Thrasymachus; [5] but when you say I do not give thanks, you are wrong. I give as much as I can. But I can give only praise, since I have no money. And just how enthusiastically I give it, when someone seems to me to speak well, you will know as soon as you have answered, since I think you will speak well.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Listen, then. I say justice is nothing other than what is advantageous for the stronger. Well, why don’t you praise me? No, you are [c] unwilling.

 

SOCRATES: First, I must understand what you mean. For, as things stand, I do not. What is advantageous for the stronger, you say, is just. What on [5] earth do you mean, Thrasymachus? Surely you do not mean something like this: Polydamas, the pancratist,16 is stronger than we are. Beef is advantageous for his body. So, this food is also both advantageous and just for us who are weaker than he? [d]

 

THRASYMACHUS: You disgust me, Socrates. You interpret my account in the way that does it the most evil.

 

SOCRATES: That’s not it at all, my very good man; I only want you to make your meaning clearer. [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Don’t you know, then, that some cities are ruled by a tyranny, some by a democracy, and some by an aristocracy?

 

SOCRATES: Of course I do.

 

THRASYMACHUS: And that what is stronger in each city is the ruling element? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Certainly.

 

THRASYMACHUS: And each type of rule makes laws that are advantageous for itself: democracy makes democratic ones, tyranny tyrannical ones, and [e] so on with the others. And by so legislating, each declares that what is just for its subjects is what is advantageous for itself—the ruler—and it punishes anyone who deviates from this as lawless and unjust. That, Socrates, is what [5] I say justice is, the same in all cities: what is advantageous for the established rule. Since the established rule is surely stronger, anyone who does the [339a] rational calculation correctly will conclude that the just is the same everywhere—what is advantageous for the stronger.

 

SOCRATES: Now I see what you mean. Whether it is true or not, I will try [5] to find out. But you yourself have answered that what is just is what is advantageous, Thrasymachus, whereas you forbade me to answer that. True, you have added for the stronger to it.

 

THRASYMACHUS: And I suppose you think that is an insignificant addition. [b]

 

SOCRATES: It isn’t clear yet whether it is significant. What is clear is that we must investigate whether or not it is true. I agree that what is just is something advantageous. But you add for the stronger. I do not know about [5] that. We will have to look into it.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Go ahead and look.

 

SOCRATES: That is just what I am going to do. Tell me, then, you also claim, don’t you, that it is just to obey the rulers?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I do.

 

[c] SOCRATES: And are the rulers in each city infallible, or are they liable to error?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No doubt, they are liable to error.

 

SOCRATES: So, when they attempt to make laws, they make some correctly, [5] others incorrectly?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: And a law is correct if it prescribes what is advantageous for the rulers themselves, and incorrect if it prescribes what is disadvantageous for them? Is that what you mean?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES : And whatever laws the rulers make must be obeyed by their [10] subjects, and that is what is just?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: According to your account, then, it isn’t only just to do what [d] is advantageous for the stronger, but also the opposite: what is not advantageous.

 

THRASYMACHUS: What is that you are saying?

 

[5] SOCRATES : The same as you, I think. But let’s examine it more closely. Haven’t we agreed that the rulers are sometimes in error as to what is best for themselves when they give orders to their subjects, and yet that it is just for their subjects to do whatever their rulers order? Wasn’t that agreed?

 

[10] THRASYMACHUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: You will also have to suppose, then, that you have agreed that [e] it is just to do what is disadvantageous for the rulers and those who are stronger, whenever they unintentionally order what is bad for themselves. But you say, too, that it is just for the others to obey the orders the rulers [5] gave. You are very wise, Thrasymachus, but doesn’t it necessarily follow that it is just to do the opposite of what you said, since the weaker are then ordered to do what is disadvantageous for the stronger?

 

[340a] POLEMARCHUS: By Zeus, Socrates, that’s absolutely clear.

 

And Clitophon interrupted:

 

Of course it is, if you are to be his witness, at any rate.

 

POLEMARCHUS: Who needs a witness? Thrasymachus himself agrees that the rulers sometimes issue orders that are bad for them, and that it is just for [5] the others to obey them.

 

CLITOPHON: That, Polemarchus, is because Thrasymachus maintained that it is just to obey the orders of the rulers.

 

POLEMARCHUS : Yes, Clitophon, and he also maintained that what is advantageous for the stronger is just. And having maintained both principles, [b] he went on to agree that the stronger sometimes order the weaker, who are subject to them, to do things that are disadvantageous for the stronger themselves. From these agreements it follows that what is advantageous for the stronger is no more just than what is not advantageous. [5]

 

CLITOPHON: But what he meant by what is advantageous for the stronger is what the stronger believes to be advantageous for him. That is what he maintained the weaker must do, and that is what he maintained is what is just.

 

POLEMARCHUS: But it is not what he said.

 

SOCRATES: It makes no difference, Polemarchus. If Thrasymachus wants to put it that way now, let’s accept it. But tell me, Thrasymachus, is that [c] what you intended to say, that what is just is what the stronger believes to be advantageous for him, whether it is in fact advantageous for him or not? Is that what we are to say you mean? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Not at all. Do you think I would call someone who is in error stronger at the very moment he errs?

 

SOCRATES: I did think you meant that, when you agreed that the rulers are not infallible but sometimes make errors.

 

THRASYMACHUS: That is because you are a quibbler in arguments, Socrates. I mean, when someone makes an error in the treatment of [d] patients, do you call him a doctor in virtue of the fact that he made that very error? Or, when someone makes an error in calculating, do you call him an accountant in virtue of the fact that he made that very error in calculation? I think we express ourselves in words that, taken literally, do say [5] that a doctor is in error, or an accountant, or a grammarian. But each of these, to the extent that he is what we call him, never makes errors, so that, [e] according to the precise account (and you are a stickler for precise accounts), no craftsman ever makes errors. It is when his knowledge fails him that he makes an error, and, in virtue of the fact that he made that error, he is no craftsman. No craftsman, wise man, or ruler makes an error at the moment when he is ruling, even though everyone will say that a [5] physician or a ruler makes errors. It is in this loose way that you must also take the answer I gave just now. But the most precise answer is this: a ruler, [341a] to the extent that he is a ruler, never makes errors and unerringly decrees what is best for himself, and that is what his subject must do. Thus, as I said from the first, it is just to do what is advantageous for the stronger.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Well, Thrasymachus, so you think I quibble, do you?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, I do.

 

SOCRATES: And you think that I asked the questions I did in a premeditated attempt to do you evil in the argument?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I am certain of it. But it won’t do you any good. You [b] will never be able to do me evil by covert means, and without them, you will never be able to overpower me by argument.

 

SOCRATES: Bless you, Thrasymachus; I would not so much as try! But to prevent this sort of confusion from happening to us again, would you define whether you mean the ruler and stronger in the ordinary sense or in [5] what you were just now calling the precise sense, when you say that it is just for the weaker to do what is advantageous for him, since he is the stronger?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I mean the ruler in the most precise sense. Now do that evil, if you can, and practice your quibbling on it—I ask no favors. But you [10] will find there is nothing you can do.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think that I am crazy enough to try to shave a lion17 [c] and quibble with Thrasymachus?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Well, you certainly tried just now, although you were a good-for-nothing at it, too!

 

SOCRATES: That’s enough of that! Tell me: is a doctor—in the precise [5] sense, the one you mentioned before—a moneymaker or someone who treats the sick? Tell me about the one who is really a doctor.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Someone who treats the sick.

 

SOCRATES: What about a ship’s captain? Is the true captain a ruler of sailors, [10] or a sailor?

 

THRASYMACHUS: A ruler of sailors.

 

SOCRATES: In other words, we should not take any account of the fact [d] that he sails in a ship, and he should not be called a sailor for that reason. For it is not because he is sailing that he is called a ship’s captain, but because of the craft he practices and his rule over sailors?

 

THRASYMACHUS: True.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And is there something that is advantageous for each of these?18

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t it also the case that the natural aim of the craft is to consider and provide what is advantageous for each?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, that is its aim.

 

SOCRATES: And is anything advantageous for each of the crafts themselves besides being as perfect as possible? [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: How do you mean? [e]

 

SOCRATES: It is like this: suppose you asked me whether it is satisfactory for a body to be a body, or whether it needs something else. I would answer, “Of course it needs something. In fact, that is why the craft of medicine has been discovered—because a body is deficient and it is not satisfactory for it to be like that.19 To provide what is advantageous, that is [5] what the craft was developed for.” Do you think I am speaking correctly in saying this, or not?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Correctly.

 

SOCRATES: What about medicine itself? Is it deficient? Does a craft need some further virtue, as the eyes are in need of sight and the ears of hearing, [342a] so that another craft is needed to consider and provide what is advantageous for them?20 Does a craft have some similar deficiency itself, so that each craft needs another to consider what is advantageous for it? And does the [5] craft that does the considering need still another, and so on without end? Or does each consider by itself what is advantageous for it? Does it need neither itself nor another craft to consider what—in light of its own deficiency—[b] is advantageous for it? Indeed, is there no deficiency or error in any craft? And is it inappropriate for any craft to consider what is advantageous for anything besides that with which it deals? And since it is itself correct, is it without fault or impurity so long as it is wholly and precisely [5] the craft it is? Consider this with that precision of language you mentioned. Is it so or not?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It appears to be so.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t it follow that medicine does not consider what is advantageous for medicine, but for the body? [c]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And horse breeding does not consider what is advantageous for horse breeding, but for horses? Indeed, no other craft considers what is advantageous for itself—since it has no further needs—but what is advantageous [5] for that with which it deals?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Apparently so.

 

SOCRATES: Now surely, Thrasymachus, the various crafts rule over and are stronger than that with which they deal?

 

[10] He gave in at this point as well, very reluctantly.

 

SOCRATES: So no kind of knowledge considers or enjoins what is advantageous for itself, but what is advantageous for the weaker, which is subject [d] to it.

 

He finally agreed to this too, although he tried to fight it. When he had agreed, however, I said:

 

Surely then, no doctor, to the extent that he is a doctor, considers or enjoins what is advantageous for himself, but what is advantageous for his [5] patient? For we agreed that a doctor, in the precise sense, is a ruler of bodies, not a moneymaker. Isn’t that what we agreed?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So a ship’s captain, in the precise sense, is a ruler of sailors, not a sailor?

 

[e] THRASYMACHUS: That is what we agreed.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t it follow that a ship’s captain and ruler won’t consider and enjoin what is advantageous for a captain, but what is advantageous for a sailor and his subject?

 

[5] He reluctantly agreed.

 

SOCRATES: So then, Thrasymachus, no one in any position of rule, to the extent that he is a ruler, considers or enjoins what is advantageous for himself, but what is advantageous for his subject—that on which he practices his craft. It is to his subject and what is advantageous and proper for it that [10] he looks, and everything he says and does, he says and does for it.

 

[343a] When we reached this point in the argument and it was clear to all that his account of justice had turned into its opposite, instead of answering, Thrasymachus said:

 

Tell me, Socrates, do you still have a wet nurse?

 

[5] SOCRATES: What is that? Shouldn’t you be giving answers rather than asking such things?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Because she is letting you run around sniveling and doesn’t wipe your nose when you need it, since it is her fault that you do not know the difference between sheep and shepherds.

 

SOCRATES: What exactly is it I do not know? [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: You think that shepherds and cowherds consider what is [b] good for their sheep and cattle, and fatten them and take care of them with some aim in mind other than what is good for their master and themselves. Moreover, you believe that rulers in cities—true rulers, that is—think about their subjects in a different way than one does about sheep, and that [5] what they consider night and day is something other than what is advantageous for themselves. You are so far from understanding justice and what is [c] just, and injustice and what is unjust, that you do not realize that justice is really the good of another, what is advantageous for the stronger and the ruler, and harmful to the one who obeys and serves. Injustice is the opposite, [5] it rules those simpleminded—for that is what they really are—just people, and the ones it rules do what is advantageous for the other who is stronger; and they make the one they serve happy, but they do not make themselves the least bit happy.

 

You must consider it as follows, Socrates, or you will be the most naïve [d] of all: a just man must always get less than does an unjust one. First, in their contracts with one another, when a just man is partner to an unjust, you will never find, when the partnership ends, that the just one gets [5] more than the unjust, but less. Second, in matters relating to the city, when taxes are to be paid, a just man pays more on an equal amount of property, an unjust one less; but when the city is giving out refunds, a just man gets nothing while an unjust one makes a large profit. Finally, when each of them holds political office, a just person—even if he is not penalized [e] in other ways—finds that his private affairs deteriorate more because he has to neglect them, that he gains no advantage from the public purse because of his justice, and that he is hated by his relatives and acquaintances because he is unwilling to do them an unjust favor. The opposite is [5] true of an unjust man in every respect. I mean, of course, the person I described before: the man of great power who does better21 than everyone else. He is the one you should consider if you want to figure out how [344a] much more advantageous it is for the individual to be unjust than just. You will understand this most easily if you turn your thoughts to injustice of the most complete sort, the sort that makes those who do injustice happiest, and those who suffer it—those who are unwilling to do injustice—[5] most wretched. The sort I mean is tyranny, because it uses both covert means and force to appropriate the property of others—whether it is sacred or secular, public or private—not little by little, but all at once. If [b] someone commits a part of this sort of injustice and gets caught, he is punished and greatly reproached—temple robbers,22 kidnappers, housebreakers, robbers, and thieves are what these partly unjust people are called when they commit those harms. When someone appropriates the [5] possessions of the citizens, on the other hand, and then kidnaps and enslaves the possessors as well, instead of these shameful names he is called [c] happy and blessed: not only by the citizens themselves, but even by all who learn that he has committed the whole of injustice. For it is not the fear of doing injustice, but of suffering it, that elicits the reproaches of those who revile injustice.

 

[5] So you see, Socrates, injustice, if it is on a large enough scale, is stronger, freer, and more masterful than justice. And, as I said from the beginning, justice is what is advantageous for the stronger, while injustice is profitable and advantageous for oneself.

 

[d] Having, like a bath attendant, emptied this great flood of words into our ears all at once, Thrasymachus was thinking of leaving. But those present wouldn’t let him. They made him stay and give an account of what he had said. And I [5] myself was particularly insistent:

 

You are marvelous, Thrasymachus; after hurling such a speech at us, you surely cannot be thinking of leaving before you have adequately instructed us—or learned yourself—whether you are right or not. Or do you think it [e] is a trivial matter you are trying to determine, and not rather a way of life—the one that would make living life that way most profitable for each of us?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Do you mean that I do not think it is a serious matter?

 

[5] SOCRATES: Either that, or you care nothing for us and so are not worried about whether we will live better or worse lives because of our ignorance of what you claim to know. No, be a good fellow and show some willingness to teach us—you won’t do badly for yourself if you help a group as [345a] large as ours. For my own part, I will tell you that I am not persuaded. I do not believe that injustice is more profitable than justice, not even if you should give it full scope to do what it wants. Suppose, my good fellow, that [5] there is an unjust person, and suppose he does have the power to do injustice, whether by covert means or open warfare; nonetheless, he does not persuade me that injustice is more profitable than justice. Perhaps someone [b] here besides myself feels the same as I do. So, blessed though you are, you are going to have to fully persuade us that we are wrong to value justice more highly than injustice in deliberating.

 

THRASYMACHUS: And how am I to persuade you? If you are not persuaded by what I said just now, what more can I do? Am I to take my argument and pour it into your very soul?[5]

 

SOCRATES: No, by Zeus, do not do that! But first, stick to what you have said, or, if you change your position, do it openly and do not try to deceive us. You see, Thrasymachus, having defined the true doctor—to continue examining the things you said before—you did not consider it necessary to [c] maintain the same level of exactness when you later turned to the true shepherd. You do not think a shepherd—to the extent that he is a shepherd—fattens sheep with the aim of doing what is best for them. But you think that, like a guest about to be entertained at a feast, his aim is to eat [5] well or to make a future sale—as if he were a moneymaker rather than a shepherd. But of course, the only concern of the craft of shepherding is to [d] provide what is best for that with which it deals, since it itself is adequately provided with all it needs to be at its best, as we know, when it does not fall short in any way of being the craft of shepherding. That is why I, at any rate, thought it necessary for us to agree before23 that every kind of rule—[5] to the extent that it is a kind of rule—does not seek anything other than what is best for the thing it rules and cares for, and this is true both in political and in private rule. But do you think that those who rule cities—the [e] ones who are truly rulers—rule willingly?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I do not think it, by Zeus, I know it.

 

SOCRATES: But, Thrasymachus, don’t you realize that in other kinds of rule there is no willing ruler? On the contrary, they demand to be paid on [5] the assumption that their ruling will benefit not themselves, but their subjects. For tell me, don’t we say that each craft differs from every other in [346a] the power it has? Blessed though you are, please don’t answer contrary to your belief, so that we can come to some definite conclusion.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, that is what differentiates them. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t each craft provide us with a particular benefit, different from the others? For example, medicine provides us with health, captaincy with safety at sea, and so on with the others?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t wage-earning provide us with wages, since that is what it is capable of doing? Or would you call medicine the same craft as [b] captaincy? Indeed, if you want to define matters precisely, as you proposed, even if someone who is a ship’s captain becomes healthy because what is advantageous for him is sailing on the sea, you would not for that reason call what he does medicine, would you? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Nor would you call wage-earning medicine, even if someone becomes healthy while earning wages?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Nor would you call medicine wage-earning, even if someone [10] earns pay while healing?

 

[c] THRASYMACHUS: No.

 

SOCRATES: We are agreed then, aren’t we, that each craft brings its own special benefit?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, we are.

 

[5] SOCRATES: So whatever benefit all craftsmen jointly receive must clearly derive from their joint practice of some additional craft that is the same for each of them.

 

THRASYMACHUS: It seems so.

 

SOCRATES: And we say that the additional craft in question, which benefits [10] the craftsmen by earning them wages, is the craft of wage-earning?

 

He reluctantly agreed.

 

SOCRATES: Then this very benefit, receiving wages, is not provided to [d] each of them by his own craft. On the contrary, if we are to examine the matter precisely, medicine provides health and wage-earning provides a wage; house-building provides a house, and wage-earning, which accompanies it, provides a wage; and so on with the other crafts. Each of them [5] does its own work and benefits that with which it deals. So, wages aside, is there any benefit that craftsmen get from their craft?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Apparently not.

 

SOCRATES: But he still provides a benefit, even when he works for [e] nothing?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, I think he does.

 

SOCRATES: Then, it is clear now, Thrasymachus, that no type of craft or rule provides what is beneficial for itself; but, as we have been saying for [5] some time, it provides and enjoins what is beneficial for its subject, and aims at what is advantageous for it—the weaker, not the stronger. That is why I said just now, my dear Thrasymachus, that no one chooses to rule voluntarily and take other people’s troubles in hand and straighten them out, but each asks for wages. You see, anyone who is going to practice his [347a] type of craft well never does or enjoins what is best for himself—at least not when he is acting as his craft prescribes—but what is best for his subject. It [5] is because of this, it seems, that wages must be provided to a person if he is going to be willing to rule, whether they are in the form of money or honor or a penalty if he refuses.[5]

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean, Socrates? I am familiar with the first two kinds of wages, but I do not understand what penalty you mean, or how you can call it a wage.

 

SOCRATES: Then you do not understand the sort of wages for which the best people rule, when they are willing to rule. Don’t you know that those [10] who love honor and those who love money are despised, and rightly so? [b]

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is why good people won’t be willing to rule [5] for the sake of money or honor. You see, if they are paid wages openly for ruling, they will be called hirelings, and if they take them covertly as the fruits of their rule, they will be called thieves. On the other hand, they won’t rule for the sake of honor either, since they are not ambitious honor-lovers. So, if they are going to be willing to rule, some compulsion or punishment [c]must be brought to bear on them—that is probably why wanting to rule when one does not have to is thought to be shameful. Now, the greatest punishment for being unwilling to rule is being ruled by someone worse than oneself. And I think it is fear of that that makes good people rule when they do rule. They approach ruling, not as though they were [5] going to do something good or as though they were going to enjoy themselves in it, but as something necessary, since it cannot be entrusted to anyone better than—or even as good as—themselves. In a city of good men, if [d] it came into being, the citizens would fight in order not to rule, just as they now do in order to rule. There it would be quite clear that anyone who is really and truly a ruler does not naturally seek what is advantageous for himself, but what is so for his subject. As a result, anyone with any sense [5] would prefer to be benefited by another than to go to the trouble of benefiting him. So I cannot at all agree with Thrasymachus that justice is what is advantageous for the stronger. But we will look further into that another [e] time. What Thrasymachus is now saying—that the life of an unjust person is better than that of a just one—seems to be of far greater importance. Which life would you choose, Glaucon? And which of our views do you [5] think is closer to the truth?

 

GLAUCON: I think the life of a just person is more profitable.

 

SOCRATES: Did you hear all the good things Thrasymachus attributed a moment ago to the unjust man? [348a]

 

GLAUCON: I did, but I am not persuaded.

 

SOCRATES: Then do you want us to persuade him, if we can find a way, that what he says is not true? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course I do.

 

SOCRATES: Well, if we oppose him with a speech parallel to his speech enumerating in turn the many good things that come from being just, and he replies, and then we do, we will have to count and measure the good things mentioned on each side, and we will need a jury to decide the case. [b] But if, on the other hand, we investigate the question, as we have been doing, by seeking agreement with each other, we ourselves can be both jury and advocates at once.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then which approach do you prefer?

 

GLAUCON: The second.

 

SOCRATES: Come on then, Thrasymachus, answer us from the beginning. You say, don’t you, that complete injustice is more profitable than complete [10] justice?

 

[c] THRASYMACHUS: I certainly have said that. And I have told you why.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, what do you say about this? Do you call one of the two a virtue and the other a vice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

[5] SOCRATES: That is to say, you call justice a virtue and injustice a vice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Is that likely, sweetest one, when I say that injustice is profitable and justice is not?

 

SOCRATES: Then what exactly do you say?

 

[10] THRASYMACHUS: The opposite.

 

SOCRATES: That justice is a vice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No, just very noble naiveté.24

 

[d] SOCRATES: So you call injustice deviousness?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No, I call it being prudent.

 

SOCRATES: Do you also consider unjust people to be wise and good, Thrasymachus?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, if they do complete injustice and can bring cities [5] and whole nations under their power. Perhaps, you thought I meant pickpockets? Not that such crimes aren’t also profitable, if they are not found out. But they are not worth discussing by comparison to what I described.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, I am not unaware of what you mean. But this did surprise [e] me: that you include injustice with virtue and wisdom, and justice with their opposites.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Nevertheless, that is where I put them.

 

SOCRATES: That is now a harder problem, comrade, and it is not easy to [5] know what to say in response. If you had declared that injustice is more profitable, but agreed that it is a vice or shameful, as some others do, we could be discussing the matter on the basis of conventional norms. But now, obviously, you will say that injustice is fine and strong and apply to it all the attributes we [10] used to apply to justice, since you dare to include it with virtue and wisdom. [349a]

 

THRASYMACHUS: You have guessed my views exactly.

 

SOCRATES: All the same, we must not shrink from pursuing the argument and looking into this, just as long as I take you to be saying what you really [5] think. You see, I believe that you really are not joking now, Thrasymachus, but saying what you believe to be the truth.

 

THRASYMACHUS: What difference does it make to you, whether I believe it or not? Isn’t it my account you are supposed to be refuting? [10]

 

SOCRATES: It makes no difference. But here is a further question I would like you to try to answer: do you think that a just person wants to do better25 [b] than another just person?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Not at all. Otherwise, he would not be the civilized and naïve person he actually is. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What about than the just action?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No, not than that, either.

 

SOCRATES: And does he claim that he deserves to do better than an unjust person and believe that it is just for him to do so, or doesn’t he believe that?

 

THRASYMACHUS: He would want to do better than him, and he would claim to deserve to do so, but he would not be able. [10]

 

SOCRATES: That is not what I am asking, but whether a just person wants, and claims to deserve, to do better than an unjust person, but not than a [c] just one?

 

THRASYMACHUS: He does.

 

SOCRATES: What about an unjust person? Does he claim that he deserves to do better than a just person or a just action? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course he does; he thinks he deserves to do better than everyone.

 

SOCRATES: Then will an unjust person also do better than an unjust person or an unjust action, and will he strive to get the most he can for himself from everyone?

 

[10] THRASYMACHUS: He will.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s put it this way: a just person does not do better than someone like himself, but someone unlike himself, whereas an unjust person [d] does better than those who are like and those who are unlike him.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Very well put.

 

SOCRATES: Now, an unjust person is wise and good, and a just one is neither?

 

[5] THRASYMACHUS: That is well put, too.

 

SOCRATES: So isn’t an unjust person also like a wise and good person, while the just person is not?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course. How could he fail to be like people who have such qualities, when he has them himself? But the unjust person is not like them.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Fine.Then each of them has the qualities of the people he is like?

 

THRASYMACHUS: What else could he have?

 

SOCRATES: All right, Thrasymachus. Do you call one person musical and [e] another non-musical?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Which of them is wise in music and which is not?

 

THRASYMACHUS: The musical one is wise, presumably, and the other not [5] wise.

 

SOCRATES: And in the things in which he is wise, he is good; and in the things in which he is not wise, he is bad?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t the same true of a doctor?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think, then, Thrasymachus, that a man who is a musician, [10] when he is tuning his lyre and tightening and loosening the strings, wants to do better than another musician, and does he claim that that is what he deserves?26

 

THRASYMACHUS: I do not.

 

SOCRATES: But he does want to do better than a non-musician? [15]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: What about a doctor? When he is prescribing food and drink, [350a]does he want to do better than another doctor or than medical practice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: But he does want to do better than a non-doctor?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.[5]

 

SOCRATES: In any branch of knowledge or ignorance, do you think that a knowledgeable person would intentionally try to take more for himself than another knowledgeable person, or to do or say more, and not rather exactly what the one like himself would do in the same situation?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No, I imagine it must be as you say. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And what about an ignorant person? Doesn’t he want to do better than both a knowledgeable person and an ignorant one? [b]

 

THRASYMACHUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: A knowledgeable person is wise?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: And a wise one is good? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: So, a good and wise person does not want to do better than someone like himself, but someone both unlike and opposite to him.

 

THRASYMACHUS: So it seems.

 

SOCRATES: But a bad and ignorant person wants to do better than both his like and his opposite. [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: Well, Thrasymachus, we found that an unjust person tries to do better than those like him and those unlike him. Didn’t you say that?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I did.[15]

 

SOCRATES: And that a just person won’t do better than those like him, but [c] those unlike him?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then a just person is like a wise and good person, and an unjust person is like an ignorant and bad one. [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: It looks that way.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we agreed that each has the qualities of the one he resembles.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, we did.

 

[10] SOCRATES: A just person has turned out to be good and wise, then, and an unjust one ignorant and bad.

 

[d] Thrasymachus agreed to all this, not easily as I am telling it, but reluctantly, with toil, trouble, and—since it was summer—a quantity of sweat that was amazing to behold. And then I saw something I had never seen before—Thrasymachus blushing. But in any case, after we had agreed that justice is [5] virtue and wisdom and that injustice is vice and ignorance, I said:

 

All right, let’s take that as established. But we also said that injustice is a strong thing, or don’t you remember that, Thrasymachus?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I remember. But I am not satisfied with what you are [10] now saying. I could make a speech about it, but if I did, I know that you would say I was engaging in demagoguery. So, either allow me to say as [e] much as I want to say or, if you want to keep on asking questions, go ahead and ask them, and I shall say to you—as one does to old women telling stories—“All right,” and nod or shake my head.

 

[5] SOCRATES: No, don’t do that; not contrary to your own belief.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Then I will answer to please you, since you won’t let me make a speech. What else do you want?

 

SOCRATES: Nothing, by Zeus. But if that is what you are going to do, do it, and I will ask the questions.

 

[10] THRASYMACHUS: Ask them, then.

 

SOCRATES: All right, I will ask precisely what I asked before, so that we may proceed in an orderly fashion with our argument about what sort of [351a] thing justice is, as opposed to injustice. For it was claimed, I believe, that injustice is stronger and more powerful than justice. But now, if justice is indeed wisdom and virtue, it will be easy to show, I suppose, that it is stronger [5] than injustice, since injustice is ignorance—no one could now be ignorant of that. However, I, at any rate, do not want to consider the matter in such simple terms, Thrasymachus, but to look into it in some such way as this: would you say that a city may be unjust and try to enslave other cities [b] unjustly, and succeed at enslaving them,27 and hold them in subjection which it enslaved in the past?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course. And that is what the best city will especially [5] do, the one that is most completely unjust.

 

SOCRATES: I understand that that is your argument, but the point I want to examine is this: will the city that becomes stronger than another achieve this power without justice, or will it need the help of justice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: If what you said a moment ago stands, and justice is [c] wisdom, it will need the help of justice; but if things are as I stated, it will need the help of injustice.

 

SOCRATES: I am impressed, Thrasymachus, that you are not merely nodding or shaking your head, but giving these fine answers. [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: That is because I am trying to please you.

 

SOCRATES: You are doing well at it, too. So please me some more by answering this question: do you think that a city, an army, a band of robbers or thieves, or any other group with a common unjust purpose would be able to achieve it if its members were unjust to each other? [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course not. [d]

 

SOCRATES: What if they were not unjust to one another? Would they achieve more?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Because, Thrasymachus, injustice causes factions, hatreds, and quarrels among them, while justice brings friendship and a sense of common purpose. Isn’t that so? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: I will say it is, in order not to disagree with you.

 

SOCRATES: You are still doing well on that front, which is very good of you. So tell me this: if the function of injustice is to produce hatred wherever it occurs, then whenever it arises, whether among free men or slaves, won’t it make them hate one another, form factions, and be unable to [10] achieve any common purpose? [e]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: What if it arises between two people? Won’t they be at odds, hate each other, and be enemies both to one another and to just people?

 

THRASYMACHUS: They will. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, my amazing fellow, if injustice arises within a single individual, will it lose its power or will it retain it undiminished?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Let’s say that it retains it undiminished.

 

SOCRATES: Apparently, then, its power is such that whenever it comes to exist in something—whether in a city, a family, an army, or anything else [10] whatsoever—it makes that thing, first of all, incapable of acting in concert with itself, because of the faction and difference it creates; and, second of [352a] all, an enemy to itself, and to what is in every way its opposite: namely, justice. Isn’t that so?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And in a single individual, too, I presume, it will produce the [5] very same effects that it is in its nature to produce. First, it will make him incapable of acting because of inner faction and not being of one mind with himself; second, it will make him his own enemy as well as the enemy of just people. Isn’t that right?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

[10] SOCRATES: But, my dear fellow, aren’t the gods also just?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Let’s say they are.

 

SOCRATES: Then an unjust person will also be an enemy of the gods, [b] Thrasymachus, while a just person will be their friend?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Feast yourself confidently on the argument! Don’t worry, I won’t oppose you, so as not to arouse the enmity of our friends here.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Come on, then, complete the banquet for me by continuing to answer as you have been doing now. We have shown that just people are wiser and better and more capable of acting, while unjust ones are not even [c] able to act together. For whenever we speak of men who are unjust acting together to effectively achieve a common goal, what we say is not altogether true. They would never have been able to keep their hands off each other if they were completely unjust. But clearly there must have been some sort of justice in them that at least prevented them from doing injustice [5] among themselves at the same time as they were doing it to others. And it was this that enabled them to achieve what they did. When they started doing unjust things, they were only halfway corrupted by their injustice. For those who are wholly bad and completely unjust are also completely incapable of acting. All this I now see to be the truth, and not [d] what you first maintained. However, we must now examine the question, as we proposed to do before,28 of whether just people also live better and are happier than unjust ones. I think it is clear even now from what we [5] have said that this is so, but we must consider it further. After all, the argument concerns no ordinary topic, but the way we ought to live.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Go ahead and consider.

 

SOCRATES: I will. Tell me, do you think there is such a thing as the function of a horse?

 

[e] THRASYMACHUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: And would you take the function of a horse or of anything else to be that which one can do only with it, or best with it?

 

THRASYMACHUS: I don’t understand.

 

SOCRATES: Let me put it this way: is it possible for you to see with anything except eyes? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: Or for you to hear with anything except ears?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No.

 

SOCRATES: Would it be right, then, for us to say that these things are their functions?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Again, couldn’t you use a dagger, a carving knife, or lots of other things in pruning a vine? [353a]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: But nothing would do a better job than a pruning knife designed for the purpose? [5]

 

THRASYMACHUS: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we take pruning to be its function, then?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Now I think you will understand better what I was asking earlier when I asked whether the function of each thing is what it alone can do or what it can do better than anything else. [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: I do understand, and I think that that is the function of anything. b

 

SOCRATES: All right. Does there seem to you also to be a virtue29 for each thing to which some function is assigned? Let’s go over the same ground again. We say that eyes have some function?

 

THRASYMACHUS: They do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So eyes also have a virtue?

 

THRASYMACHUS: They do.

 

SOCRATES: And ears have a function?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So they also have a virtue? [10]

 

THRASYMACHUS: They have a virtue too.

 

SOCRATES: What about everything else? Doesn’t the same hold?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It does.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then. Could eyes perform their function well if they [c] lacked their proper virtue but had the vice instead?

 

THRASYMACHUS: How could they? For don’t you mean if they had blindness instead of sight?

 

[5] SOCRATES: Whatever their virtue is. You see, I am not now asking about that, but about whether it is by means of their own proper virtue that their function performs the things it performs well, and by means of vice badly?

 

THRASYMACHUS: What you say is true.

 

SOCRATES : So, if ears are deprived of their own virtue, they too perform their function badly?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

[d] SOCRATES: And the same argument applies to everything else?

 

THRASYMACHUS: So it seems to me, at least.

 

SOCRATES : Come on, then, and let’s next consider this: does the soul have some function that you could not perform with anything else—for example, [5] taking care of things, ruling, deliberating, and all other such things? Is there anything else besides a soul to which you could rightly assign these and say that they special to it?

 

THRASYMACHUS: No, there is nothing else.

 

SOCRATES: Then what about living? Don’t we say that it is a function of a soul?

 

[10] THRASYMACHUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t we also say that a soul has a virtue?

 

THRASYMACHUS: We do.

 

SOCRATES: Will a soul ever perform its functions well, then, Thrasymachus, [e] if it is deprived of its own proper virtue, or is that impossible?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It is impossible.

 

SOCRATES: It is necessary, then, that a bad soul rules and takes care of [5] things badly, and that a good soul does all these things well?

 

THRASYMACHUS: It is necessary.

 

SOCRATES: Now, didn’t we agree that justice is a soul’s virtue and injustice its vice?

 

THRASYMACHUS: Yes, we did agree.

 

[10] SOCRATES: So a just soul and a just man will live well and an unjust one badly.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Apparently so, according to your argument.

 

SOCRATES: And surely anyone who lives well is blessed and happy, and anyone who does not is the opposite. [354a]

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, a just person is happy and an unjust one wretched.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Let’s say so. [5]

 

SOCRATES: But surely it is profitable, not to be wretched, but to be happy.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So then, blessed Thrasymachus, injustice is never more profitable than justice.

 

THRASYMACHUS: Let that be your banquet, Socrates, at the feast of Bendis. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Given by you, Thrasymachus, after you became gentle with me and ceased to be difficult. Yet I have not had a good banquet. But that is my fault, not yours. I seem to have behaved like those gluttons who snatch [b] at every dish that passes and taste it before having properly savored the preceding one. Before finding the first thing we inquired about—namely, what justice is—I let that go, and turned to investigate whether it is a kind [5] of vice and ignorance or a kind of wisdom and virtue. Then an argument came up about injustice being more profitable than justice, and I could not refrain from abandoning the previous one and following up on it. Hence the result of the discussion, so far as I am concerned, is that I know nothing. For when I do not know what justice is, I will hardly know whether it [c] is a kind of virtue or not, or whether a person who has it is happy or unhappy.

 

1 Hê theos: Most probably—as 354a10–11 implies—the Thracian goddess Bendis, whose cult had recently been introduced in Piraeus. However, for Athenians, Athena is hê theos.

2 See Glossary of Terms s.v. city.

3 See Glossary of Terms s.v. cloak.

4 See 485d6–e1.

5 Namely, death.

6 “God ever draws together like to like.”

7 See Glossary of Terms s.v. masses.

8 A slightly different version of the story appears in Herodotus 8.125.

9 See Glossary of Terms s.v. justice.

10 See Glossary of Terms s.v. craft.

11 See Glossary of Terms s.v. captain.

12 Odyssey 19.392–8.

13 See Glossary of Terms s.v. virtue.

14 In Greek superstition, anyone seen by a wolf before he sees it is struck dumb.

15 See Glossary of Terms s.v. irony.

16 See Glossary of Terms s.v. pancration.

17 Proverbial characterization of an almost impossible task.

18 I.e., for sailors and bodies.

19 See 608d13–610d3.

20 Sight is the virtue or excellence of the eyes. Without it, the eyes cannot achieve what is advantageous to them: namely, sight. But Socrates assumes throughout Book 1 that virtues are types of craft (see 332d). Hence he can conclude that the eyes need a further craft in order to achieve what is advantageous to them.

21 See Glossary of Terms s.v. do better.

22 The temples served as public treasuries, so that a temple robber is the equivalent of a present-day bank robber.

23 See 341e–342e above.

24 Euêtheia, kakoêtheia: Thrasymachus uses euêtheia in the bad sense, to mean stupidity.

Socrates takes him to mean it in the good sense of being straightforward, and so contrasts it with kakoêtheia—deviousness. See 400e1.

25 See Glossary of Terms s.v. do better.

26 What Socrates has in mind is explained at 350a. All expert musicians try to get the same result, perfect harmony, so they tighten and loosen their strings to exactly the same degree: namely, the one that will produce the right pitch. In the same way, all doctors who are masters of medicine prescribe the same diet for people with the same diseases: namely, the one that will best restore them to health.

27 Reading 123.

28 347e.

29 See Glossary of Terms s.v. virtue.

Book 2

 

SOCRATESNARRATION CONTINUES: When I had said this, I [357a] thought I had done with the discussion. But it all turned out to be only a prelude,as it were. You see, Glaucon, who is always very courageous in everything, refused on this occasion, too, to accept Thrasymachus’ capitulation. Instead, he said:

 

Do you want to seem to have persuaded us, Socrates, that it is better in [5] every way to be just rather than unjust, or do you want to really persuade us [b] of this?

 

SOCRATES: I want to really persuade you, if I can.

 

GLAUCON: Well, then, you certainly are not doing what you want. Tell [5] me, do you think there is a sort of good we welcome, not because we desire its consequences, but because we would choose to have it for its own sake—enjoying, for example, and all the harmless pleasures from which nothing results afterward beyond enjoying having them?

 

SOCRATES: Certainly, I think there is such a thing.

 

[10] GLAUCON: And is there a sort of good we love for its own sake, and also [c] for the sake of its consequences—knowing, for example, and seeing, and being healthy? For we welcome such things, I imagine, on both counts.

 

SOCRATES: Yes.

 

GLAUCON: And do you also recognize a third kind of good, which includes physical [5] training, medical treatment when sick, and both medicine itself, and ways of making money? We would say that these are burdensome but beneficial to us, and we would not choose to have them for their own sake, but for [d] the sake of their rewards and other consequences.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, certainly, there is also this third kind. But what of it?

 

GLAUCON: In which of them do you place justice?

 

[358a] SOCRATES: I myself put it in the finest one—the one that anyone who is going to be blessed with happiness must love both because of itself and because of its consequences.

 

GLAUCON: That is not what the masses think. On the contrary, they think it is of the burdensome kind: the one that must be practiced for the sake of the rewards and the popularity that are the consequences of a good reputation, [5] but that is to be avoided as intrinsically burdensome.

 

SOCRATES: I know that is the general view. Thrasymachus has been faulting justice and praising injustice on these grounds for some time. But it seems that I am a slow learner.

 

GLAUCON: Come on, then, listen to what I have to say as well, and see whether you still have that problem. You see, I think Thrasymachus gave up [b] before he had to, as if he were a snake you had charmed. Yet, to my way of thinking, there was still no demonstration on either side. For I want to hear what justice and injustice are, and what power each has when it is just by itself in the soul. I want to leave out of account the rewards and the consequences [5] of each of them.

 

So, if you agree, I will renew the argument of Thrasymachus. First, I will state what sort of thing people consider justice to be, and what its origins [c] are. Second, I will argue that all who practice it do so unwillingly, as something necessary, not as something good. Third, I will argue that they have good reason to act as they do. For the life of the unjust person is, they say, much better than that of the just one. [5]

It isn’t, Socrates, that I believe any of that myself. I am perplexed, indeed, and my ears are deafened listening to Thrasymachus and countless others. But I have yet to hear anyone defend justice in the way I want, as being better than injustice. I want to hear it praised on its own, and I think [d] that I am most likely to learn this from you. That is why I am going to speak at length in praise of the unjust life: by doing so, I will be showing you the way I want to hear you denouncing injustice and praising justice.[5] But see whether you want me to do what I am saying or not.

SOCRATES: I want it most of all. Indeed, what subject could a person with any sense enjoy talking and hearing about more often?

 

GLAUCON: Excellent sentiments. Now, listen to what I said I was going to discuss first—what justice is like and what its origins are. People say, you [e] see, that to do injustice is naturally good and to suffer injustice bad. But the badness of suffering it far exceeds the goodness of doing it. Hence, those who have done and suffered injustice and who have tasted both—the ones [5] who lack the power to do it and avoid suffering it—decide that it is profitable to come to an agreement with each other neither to do injustice nor [359a] to suffer it. As a result, they begin to make laws and covenants; and what the law commands, they call lawful and just. That, they say, is the origin and very being1 of justice. It is in between the best and the worst. The best [5] is to do injustice without paying the penalty; the worst is to suffer it without being able to take revenge. Justice is in the middle between these two extremes. People love it, not because it is a good thing, but because they are too weak to do injustice with impunity. Someone who has the power to do [b] it, however—someone who is a real man—would not make an agreement with anyone, neither to do injustice nor to suffer it. For him, that would be insanity. That is the nature of justice, according to the argument, Socrates, [5] and those are its natural origins.

 

We can see most clearly that those who practice it do so unwillingly, because they lack the power to do injustice, if we imagine the following [c] thought-experiment. Suppose we grant to the just and the unjust person the freedom to do whatever they like. We can then follow both of them and see where their appetites would lead. And we will catch the just person red-handed, traveling the same road as the unjust one. The reason for this is the desire to do better2 than others. This is what every natural being naturally [5] pursues as good. But by law and force, it is made to deviate from this path and honor equality.

They would especially have the freedom I am talking about if they had [d] the power that the ancestor of Gyges of Lydia is said to have possessed.3 The story goes that he was a shepherd in the service of the ruler of Lydia. There was a violent thunderstorm, and an earthquake broke open the ground and created a chasm at the place where he was tending his sheep. Seeing this, he [5] was filled with amazement and went down into it. And there, in addition to many other amazing things of which we are told stories, he saw a hollow, bronze horse. There were windowlike openings in it and, peeping in, he saw a corpse, which seemed to be of more than human size, wearing nothing [e] but a gold ring on its finger. He took off the ring and came out of the chasm. He wore the ring at the usual monthly meeting of shepherds that reported to the king on the state of the flocks. And as he was sitting among [5] the others, he happened to turn the setting of the ring toward himself, toward the inside of his hand. When he did this, he became invisible to [360a] those sitting near him, and they went on talking as if he had gone. He was amazed at this and, fingering the ring, he turned the setting outward again and became visible. So, he experimented with the ring to test whether it [5] indeed had this power—and it did. If he turned the setting inward, he became invisible; if he turned it outward, he became visible again. As soon as he realized this, he arranged to become one of the messengers sent to [b] report to the king. On arriving there, he seduced the king’s wife, attacked the king with her help, killed him, and in this way took over the kingdom.

Let’s suppose, then, that there were two such rings, one worn by the just person, the other by the unjust. Now no one, it seems, would be so [5] incorruptible that he would stay on the path of justice, or bring himself to keep away from other people’s possessions and not touch them, when he could take whatever he wanted from the marketplace with impunity, go into people’s houses and have sex with anyone he wished, kill or release from prison anyone he wished, and do all the other things that would [c] make him like a god among humans. And in so behaving, he would do no differently than the unjust person, but both would pursue the same course.

This, some would say, is strong evidence that no one is just willingly, but [5] only when compelled. No one believes justice to be a good thing when it is kept private, since whenever either person thinks he can do injustice with impunity, he does it. Indeed, all men believe that injustice is far more profitable to themselves than is justice. And what they believe is true, so the [d] exponent of this argument will say. For someone who did not want to do injustice, given this sort of opportunity, and who did not touch other people’s property, would be thought most wretched and most foolish by everyone aware of the situation. Though, of course, they would praise him in [5] public, deceiving each other for fear of suffering injustice. So much for my second topic.

As for decision itself about the life of the two we are discussing, if we [e] contrast the extremes of justice and injustice, we shall be able to make the decision correctly; but if we don’t, we won’t. What, then, is the contrast I have in mind? It is this: we will subtract nothing from the injustice of the unjust person, and nothing from the justice of the just one. On the contrary, we will take each to be perfect in his own pursuit. First, then, let the [5] unjust person act like a clever craftsman. An eminent ship’s captain or doctor, for example, knows the difference between what his craft can and cannot do. He attempts the first but lets the second go by. And if he happens to [361a] slip, he can put things right. In the same way, if he is to be completely unjust, let the unjust person correctly attempt unjust acts and remain undetected. The one who is caught should be thought inept. For the extreme of injustice is to be believed to be just without actually being so. And our [5] completely unjust person must be given complete injustice—nothing must be subtracted from it. We must allow that, while doing the greatest injustice, he has nonetheless provided himself with the greatest reputation for justice. If he does happen to slip up, he must be able to put it right, either [b] through his ability to speak persuasively if any of his unjust activities are discovered, or to use force if force is needed, because he is courageous and strong and has provided himself with wealth and friends. [5]

Having hypothesized such a person, let’s now put the just man next to him in our argument—someone who is simple and noble and who, as Aeschylus says, does not want to be believed to be good, but to be so.4 We must take away his reputation. For a reputation for justice would bring him honor and rewards, so that it would not be clear whether he is being just [c]for the sake of justice, or for the sake of those honors and rewards. We must strip him of everything except justice, and make his situation the opposite of the unjust person’s. Though he does no injustice, he must have the greatest [5] reputation for it, so that he may be tested with regard to justice by seeing whether or not he can withstand a bad reputation and its consequences. Let him stay like that, unchanged, until he is dead—just, but all his life [d] believed to be unjust. In this way, both will reach the extremes, the one of justice and the other of injustice, and we will be able to judge which of them is happier.

[5] SOCRATES: Whew! My dear Glaucon, how vigorously you have scoured each of the men in our competition, just as you would a pair of statues for an art competition.

 

GLAUCON: I am doing the best I can. Since the two are as I have described, in any case, it should not be difficult to complete the account of the sort of life that awaits each of them, but it must be done. And if what I [e] say sounds crude, Socrates, remember that it is not I who speak, but those who praise injustice at the expense of justice. They will say that the just person in such circumstances will be whipped, stretched on a rack, chained, blinded with a red-hot iron, and, at the end, when he has suffered every [362a] sort of bad thing, he will be impaled, and will realize then that one should not want to be just, but to be believed to be just. Indeed, Aeschylus’ words are far more correctly applied to the unjust man. For people will say that it is really the unjust person who does not want to be believed to be unjust, [5] but actually to be so, because he bases his practice on the truth about things and does not allow reputation to regulate his life. He is the one who “harvests [b] a deep furrow in his mind, where wise counsels propagate.” First, he rules his city because of his reputation for justice. Next, he marries into any family he wishes, gives his children in marriage to anyone he wishes, has contracts and partnerships with anyone he wants, and, besides benefiting himself in all these ways, he profits because he has no scruples about doing [5] injustice. In any contest, public or private, he is the winner and does better than his enemies. And by doing better than them, he becomes wealthy, [c] benefits his friends, and harms his enemies. He makes adequate sacrifices to the gods and sets up magnificent offerings to them, and takes much better care of the gods—and, indeed, of the human beings he favors—than the just person. So he may reasonably expect that the gods, in turn, will love [5] him more than the just person. That is why they say, Socrates, that gods and humans provide a better life for the unjust person than for the just one.

 

[d] When Glaucon had said this, I had it in mind to respond, but his brother Adeimantus intervened:

 

You surely do not think that the argument has been adequately stated?

 

SOCRATES: Why shouldn’t I?

 

ADEIMANTUS: The most important point has not been mentioned. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, as the saying goes, a man’s brother must stand by him.5 So if Glaucon has omitted something, you must help him. Though, for my part at any rate, what he has already said is quite enough to throw me to the canvas and make me incapable of coming to the aid of justice.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Nonsense. But listen to what more I have to say, as well. [e] You see, in order to clarify what Glaucon has in mind, we should also fully explore the arguments that are opposed to the ones he gave—those that praise justice and disparage injustice.

 

As you know, when fathers speak to their sons to give them advice, they say that one must be just, as do all those who have others in their charge. [5] But they do not praise justice itself, only the good reputation it brings: the [363a] inducement they offer is that if we are reputed to be just, then, as a result of our reputation, we will get political offices, good marriages, and all the things that Glaucon recently said that the just man would get as a result of having a good reputation.

But these people have even more to say about the consequences of reputation. For by throwing in being well thought of by the gods, they have [5] plenty of good things to talk about—all the ones the gods are said to give to those who are pious. For example, the noble Hesiod and Homer say such things. For Hesiod says that the gods make the oak trees “bear acorns at the [b] top, bees in the middle, and fleecy sheep heavy laden with wool” for those who are just, and tells of many other good things akin to these.6 And Homer says pretty much the same: [5]

 

When a good king, in his piety,

Upholds justice, the black earth bears

Wheat and barley for him, and his trees are heavy with fruit, [c]

His sheep bear lambs unfailingly and the sea yields up its fish.7

 

Musaeus and his son claim that the gods give just people even more exciting goods than these. In their account, they lead the just to Hades, seat them on couches, provide them with a symposium of pious people, crown [5]them with wreaths, and make them spend all their time drinking—as if they thought eternal drunkenness was the finest wage of virtue. Others [d] stretch even further the wages that virtue receives from the gods. For they say that someone who is pious and keeps his promises leaves his children’s children and a whole race behind him.

 

[5] In these and other similar ways, they praise justice. But the impious and unjust they bury in mud in Hades, and they force them to carry water in a sieve. They bring them into bad repute while they are still alive. And all those penalties that Glaucon gave to just people who are thought to be [e] unjust, they give to the unjust ones. But they have nothing else to say.

That, then, is the praise and blame given to each. But in addition, [5] Socrates, there is another kind of argument about justice and injustice for you to consider—one that is used both by private individuals and by poets. [364a] With one voice they all chant the hymn that justice and temperance are fine things, but difficult and onerous, while intemperance and injustice are sweet and easy to acquire and are only shameful by repute and convention. They also say that unjust deeds are, for the most part, more profitable than [5] just ones; and whereas they are perfectly willing to bestow public and private honors on bad people—provided they have wealth and other types of power—and to declare them to be happy, they dishonor and disregard those who happen to be in any way weak or poor, even though they admit that [b] they are better than the others.

But most amazing of all are the accounts they give of the gods and virtue, and how it is that the gods, too, assign misfortune and a bad life to many good people, and the opposite fate to their opposites. Begging priests and [5] prophets go to the doors of rich people and persuade them that, through sacrifices and incantations, they have acquired a god-given power: if the rich [5] person or any of his ancestors has committed an injustice, they can fix it with pleasant rituals. And if he wishes to injure an enemy, he will be able to harm a just one or an unjust one alike at little cost, since by means of spells and enchantments they can persuade the gods to do their bidding.

[5] And the poets are brought forward as witnesses to all these accounts. Some harp on the ease of vice, on the grounds that

 

Vice in abundance is easy to get,

[d] The road is smooth and begins beside you,

But the gods have put sweat between us and virtue

 

and a road that is long, rough, and steep.8 Others quote Homer to bear witness [5] that the gods can be influenced by humans, since he too said:

 

Even the gods themselves can be swayed by prayer.

And with sacrifices and soothing promises,

Incense and libation-drinking, human beings turn them from [e] their purpose,

When someone has transgressed and sinned.9

 

And they present a noisy throng of books by Musaeus and Orpheus—who are the offspring, they claim, of Selene and the Muses—on which they base their rituals. And they persuade not only private individuals, but whole cities, that there are in fact absolutions and purifications for unjust deeds. For [5] the living, these consist of ritual sacrifices and pleasant games. But there are also special rites for the dead. These initiations, as they call them, free people [365a] from evils hereafter, while terrible things await those who have not performed the rituals.

 

With so many things of this sort, my dear Socrates, being said about virtue and vice, and about how human beings and gods honor them, what [5] effect do we suppose they have on the souls of young people? I mean those who are naturally gifted and able to flit, so to speak, from one of these sayings to another and gather from them an impression of what sort of people they should be, and of how best to travel the road of life. He [b] would surely ask himself Pindar’s question: “Is it by justice or by crooked tricks that I will scale the higher wall,” and so live out my life surrounded by secure defenses? And he will answer: “As for what people say, they say that there is no advantage in my being just if I am not also thought just, [5] whereas the troubles and penalties of being just are apparent; but the unjust person, who has secured for himself a reputation for justice, lives the life of a god. Since, then, ‘opinion forcibly overcomes truth,’ and ‘controls happiness,’ as the wise men say, I must surely turn entirely to it.10 I [c] should create an illusionist painting11 of virtue around me to deceive those who come near, but keep behind it the wise Archilochus’ greedy and cunning fox.” [5]

“But surely,” someone will object, “it is not easy for evil to remain always hidden.” We will reply that nothing great is easy. And, in any case, if we are to be happy, we must go where the tracks of the arguments lead. To [d] remain undiscovered we will form secret societies and political clubs. And there are teachers of persuasion to make us clever in dealing with assemblies and law courts. Therefore, partly by persuasion, partly by force, we will [5] contrive to do better than other people, without paying the penalty.

“But surely we cannot hide from the gods or overpower them by force!” Well, if the gods do not exist, or do not concern themselves with human affairs, why should we worry at all about hiding from them? On the other hand, if they do exist, and do care about us, we know nothing about them [e] except what we have learned from the laws and from the poets who give their genealogies. But these are the very people who tell us that the gods can be persuaded and influenced by sacrifices, gentle prayers, and offerings. Hence, we should believe them on both matters, or on neither. If we [5] believe them, we should be unjust and offer sacrifices from the fruits of our [366a] injustice. For if we are just, our only gain is not to be punished by the gods, but we will lose the profits of our injustice. But if we are unjust, we will get those profits, and afterward we will entreat the gods and, persuading them, escape with our crimes and transgressions unpunished.

[5] “But in Hades, won’t we pay the penalty for crimes committed here, either ourselves or through our children’s children?” “My friend,” the young man will say as he does his rational calculation, “mystery rites and the gods of absolution have great power. The greatest cities tell us this, as do [b] those children of the gods who have become the gods’ poets and prophets and reveal it to be so.”

On the basis of what further argument, then, should we choose justice over the greatest injustice? For if we possess such injustice with a false [5] façade, we will do as we have a mind to among gods and humans, both while we are living and when we are dead, as both the masses and the eminent claim. So given all that has been said, Socrates, what device could get [c] someone with any power—whether of mind, wealth, body, or family—to be willing to honor justice, and not laugh aloud when he hears it praised?

Indeed, if anyone can show that what we have said is false, and has adequate [5] knowledge that justice is best, what he feels for unjust people won’t be anger, but a large measure of forgiveness. After all, he knows that apart from someone of godlike character who is disgusted by doing injustice, or someone who has gained knowledge and avoids injustice for that reason, no [d] one is just willingly. Through cowardice or old age or some other weakness, people do indeed object to injustice. But it is obvious that they do so only because they lack the power to do injustice. For the first of them to gain that power is the first to do as much injustice as he can.

[5] And all this has no other cause than the one that led to the whole of Glaucon’s and my argument with you, Socrates. “Socrates, you amazing [e] man,” we said, “of all of you who claim to praise justice, beginning from the earliest heroes of old whose accounts survive up to the men of the present day, not one has ever blamed injustice or praised justice except by mentioning the reputations, honors, and rewards that are their consequences. No one has ever adequately described what each does itself, [5] through its own power, by its presence in the soul of the person who possesses it, even if it remains hidden from gods and humans. No one, whether in poetry or in private discussions, has adequately argued that injustice is the greatest evil a soul can have in it, and justice the greatest good. If all of you had spoken in this way and had tried to persuade us [367a] from our earliest youth, we would not now be guarding against one another’s injustice, but each would be his own best guardian, afraid that by doing injustice he would be living on intimate terms with the worst thing possible.”

That, Socrates, and probably other things in addition, are what Thrasymachus[5] (or possibly someone else) might say in discussing justice and injustice—crudely inverting their power, in my view. But I—for I have no reason to hide anything from you—want to hear the opposite from you, [b] and that is why I am speaking with all the force I can muster. So do not merely demonstrate to us by argument that justice is stronger than injustice, but tell us what each one itself does, because of itself, to someone who possesses it, that makes the one bad and the other good. Follow [5] Glaucon’s advice and do not take reputations into account.12 For if you do not deprive justice and injustice of their true reputations and attach false ones to them, we will say that it is not justice you are praising, but its reputation; nor injustice you are condemning, but its reputation; and that you are encouraging us to be unjust but keep it secret. In that case, we will say [c] that you agree with Thrasymachus that justice is the good of another, the advantage of the stronger, while injustice is one’s own advantage and profit, though not the advantage of the weaker.

You agree that justice is one of the greatest goods, the ones that are [5] worth having for the sake of their consequences, but much more so for their own sake—such as seeing, hearing, knowing, being healthy, of course, and all the others that are genuine goods by nature and not simply by [d] repute. This is what I want you to praise about justice. How does it—because of its very self—benefit its possessor, and how does injustice harm him? Leave wages and reputations for others to praise.

I can put up with other people praising justice and blaming injustice in [5] that way—extolling the reputations and wages of the one and denigrating those of the other. But I won’t put up with that from you (unless you insist on it). For you have spent your whole life investigating this and nothing else. So do not merely demonstrate to us by argument that justice is stronger [e] than injustice, but show what effect each one itself has, because of itself, on the person who has it—the one for good, the other for bad—whether it remains hidden from gods and human beings or not. [5]

 

Now, I had always admired the natural characters of Glaucon and Adeimantus, but I was especially pleased when I heard what they had to say on this occasion, and I replied:

 

Sons of that man,13 Glaucon’s lover was not wrong to begin the elegy he [368a] wrote, when you distinguished yourselves at the battle of Megara, by addressing you as “Sons of Ariston, godlike family of a famous man.”14 That, my dear friends, was well said, in my view. For something altogether godlike [5] must have affected you if you are not convinced that injustice is better than justice and yet can speak like that on its behalf. And I do believe that [b] you really are unconvinced by your own words. I infer this from your general character, since if I had only your arguments to go on, I would not trust you. The more I trust you, however, the more I am at a loss as to what to do. I do not see how I can be of help. Indeed, I believe I am incapable of it.[5] And here is my evidence: I thought that what I said to Thrasymachus showed that justice is better than injustice, but you won’t accept that from me as a proof. On the other hand, I do not see how I can refuse my help. For I fear that it may even be impious to have breath in one’s body and the ability to speak, and yet stand idly by and not defend justice when it is being [c] prosecuted. The best thing, then, is to give justice any assistance I can.

 

Glaucon and the others begged me not to abandon the argument but to help in [5] every way to track down what justice and injustice each is, and the truth about their respective benefits. So I told them what I had in mind:

 

The investigation we are undertaking is not an easy one, in my view, but requires keen eyesight. So, since we are not clever people, I think we [d] should adopt the method of investigation that we would use if, lacking keen eyesight, we were told to identify small letters from a distance, and then noticed that the same letters existed elsewhere in a larger size and on a [5] larger surface. We would consider it a godsend, I think, to be allowed to identify the larger ones first, and then to examine the smaller ones to see whether they are really the same.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course we would. But how is this case similar to our [e] investigation of justice in your view?

 

SOCRATES: I will tell you. We say, don’t we, that there is a justice that belongs to a single man, and also one that belongs to a whole city?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And a city is larger than a single man?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is larger.

 

SOCRATES: Perhaps, then, there will be more justice in the larger thing, and it will be easier to discern. So, if you are willing, let’s first find out what [369a] sort of thing justice is in cities, and afterward look for it in the individual, to see if the larger entity is similar in form to the smaller one.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think that is a fine idea.

 

SOCRATES: If, in our discussion, we could look at a city coming to be, [5] wouldn’t we also see its justice coming to be, and its injustice as well?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We probably would.

 

SOCRATES: And once that process is completed, could we expect to find what we are looking for more easily? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, much more easily. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Do you think we should try to carry it out then? It is no small task, in my view. So, think it over.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It has been thought over. Don’t do anything besides try.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, a city comes to exist, I believe, because none of us [5] is individually self-sufficient, but each has many needs he cannot satisfy. Or do you think that a city is founded on some other principle?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, none.

 

SOCRATES: Then because we have many needs, and because one of us calls on another out of one need, and on a third out of a different need, we [5] gather many into a single settlement as partners and helpers. And we call such a shared settlement a city. Isn’t that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And if they share things with one another—if they give something to one another, or take something from one another—don’t they do so because each believes that this is better for himself?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, let’s, in our discussion, create a city from the beginning. But its real creator, it seems, will be our need. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Now, the first and greatest of our needs is to provide food in [d] order to sustain existence and life.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: The second is for shelter, and the third is for clothes and things of that sort.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Tell me, then, how will a city be able to provide all this? Won’t one person have to be a farmer, another a builder, and another a weaver? And shouldn’t we add a shoemaker to them, or someone else to take care of our bodily needs?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course. [10]

 

SOCRATES: A city with the barest necessities, then, would consist of four or five men?

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, should each of them contribute his own work for the common use of all? I mean, should a farmer, although he is only one person, provide food for four people, and spend quadruple the time and [5] labor to provide food to be shared by them all? Or should he not be concerned about everyone else? Should he produce one quarter the food in one quarter the time for himself alone? Should he spend the other three [370a] quarters providing a house, a cloak, and shoes? Should he save himself the bother of sharing with other people and mind his own business on his own?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: The first alternative, Socrates, is perhaps easier.

 

SOCRATES: There is nothing strange in that, by Zeus. You see, it occurred to me while you were speaking that, in the first place, we are not all born alike. On the contrary, each of us differs somewhat in nature from the others, [b] one being suited to one job, another to another. Or don’t you think so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, would one person do better work if he practiced [5] many crafts or if he practiced one?

 

ADEIMANTUS: If he practiced one.

 

SOCRATES: And it is also clear, I take it, that if one misses the opportune moment in any job, the work is spoiled.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is clear.

 

[10] SOCRATES: That, I take it, is because the thing that has to be done won’t wait until the doer has the leisure to do it. No, instead the doer must, of necessity, pay close attention to what has to be done and not leave it for his [c] idle moments.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, he must.

 

SOCRATES: The result, then, is that more plentiful and better-quality goods are more easily produced, if each person does one thing for which he is naturally suited and does it at the opportune moment, because his time is [5] freed from all the others.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then, Adeimantus, we are going to need more than four citizens to provide the things we have mentioned. For a farmer won’t make his own plow, it seems, if it is going to be a good one, nor his hoe, nor any of [d] his other farm implements. Nor will a carpenter—and he, too, needs lots of tools. And the same is true of a weaver and a shoemaker, isn’t it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: So carpenters, metalworkers, and many other craftsmen of that [5] sort will share our little city and make it bigger.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Yet it still would not be a great settlement, even if we added cowherds, shepherds, and other herdsmen, so that the farmers would [10] have cows to do their plowing, the builders oxen to share with the farmers [e] in hauling their materials, and the weavers and shoemakers hides and fleeces to use.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It would not be a small city either, if it had to hold all that.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, it is almost impossible, at any rate, to establish the [5] city itself in the sort of place where it will need no imports.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is impossible.

 

SOCRATES: Then we will need still other people who will import whatever is needed from another city. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: We will.

 

SOCRATES: And if our servant goes empty-handed to another city, without any of the things needed by those from whom he is trying to get what his own people need, he will come away empty-handed, won’t he? [371a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I should think so.

 

SOCRATES: Our citizens, then, must produce not only enough for themselves at home, but also goods of the right quality and quantity to satisfy the needs of others. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, they must.

 

SOCRATES: So we will need more farmers and other craftsmen in our city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And also other servants, I imagine, who are to take care of [10] imports and exports. These are merchants, aren’t they?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: We will need merchants too, then.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course. [15]

 

SOCRATES: And if the trade is carried on by sea, we will need a great many others who have expert knowledge of the business of the sea. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: A great many, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Again, within the city itself, how will people share with one another the things they each produce? It was in order to share, after all, that [5] we associated with one another and founded a city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly, they must do it by buying and selling.

 

SOCRATES: Then we will need a marketplace and a currency for such exchange.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: So if a farmer or any other craftsman brings some of his products [c] to the marketplace, and he does not arrive at the same time as those who want to exchange things with him, is he to sit idly in the marketplace, neglecting his own craft?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all. On the contrary, there will be people who notice [5] this situation and provide the requisite service—in well-organized cities, they are generally those whose bodies are weakest and who are not fit to do any other sort of work. Their job is to wait there in the marketplace and [d] exchange money for the goods of those who have something to sell, and then to exchange goods for the money of those who want to buy them.

 

[5] SOCRATES: This need, then, causes retailers to be present in our city.

 

Those who wait in the marketplace, and provide this service of buying and selling, are called retailers, aren’t they, whereas those who travel between cities are merchants?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s right.

 

SOCRATES: There are also other servants, I think, whose minds would not [e] altogether qualify them for membership in our community, but whose bodies are strong enough for hard labor. So they sell the use of their strength for a price called a wage, and that is why they are called wage-earners. [5] Isn’t that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So the wage-earners too, it seems, serve to complete our city?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think so.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, Adeimantus, has our city now grown to completeness? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Maybe it has.

 

SOCRATES: Then where are justice and injustice to be found in it? With which of the people we considered did they come in?

 

[372a] ADEIMANTUS: I have no idea, Socrates, unless it is somewhere in some need that these people have of one another.

 

SOCRATES: Perhaps what you say is right. We must look into it and not back off. First, then, let’s see what sort of life people will lead who have [5] been provided for in this way. They will make food, wine, clothes, and shoes, won’t they? And they will build themselves houses. In the summer, they will mostly work naked and barefoot, but in the winter they will wear adequate clothing and shoes. For nourishment, they will provide themselves [b] with barley meal and wheat flour, which they will knead and bake into noble cakes and loaves and serve up on a reed or on clean leaves. They will recline on couches strewn with yew and myrtles and feast with their children, [5] drink their wine, and, crowned with wreaths, hymn the gods. They will enjoy having sex with one another, but they will produce no more children than their resources allow, lest they fall into either poverty or war. [5]

 

At this point Glaucon interrupted and said:

 

It seems that you make your people feast without any relishes.15

 

SOCRATES: True enough, I was forgetting that they will also have relishes—salt, of course, and olives and cheese, and they will boil roots and [5] vegetables the way they boil them in the country. We will give them desserts too, I imagine, consisting of figs, chickpeas, and beans. And they will roast myrtles and acorns before the fire and drink in moderation. And so they will live in peace and good health, it seems, and when they die at a [d] ripe old age, they will pass on a similar sort of life to their children.

 

GLAUCON: If you were founding a city of pigs, Socrates, isn’t that just what you would provide to fatten them? [5]

 

SOCRATES: What, then, would you have me do, Glaucon?

 

GLAUCON: Just what is conventional. If they are not to suffer hardship, they should recline on proper couches, I suppose, dine at tables, and have the relishes and desserts that people have nowadays. [e]

 

SOCRATES: All right, I understand. It isn’t merely the origins of a city that we are considering, it seems, but those of a city that is luxurious, too. And that may not be a bad idea. For by examining such a city, we might perhaps see how justice and injustice grow up in cities.Yet the true city, in my view, [5] is the one we have described: the healthy one, as it were. But if you also want to look at a feverish city, so be it. There is nothing to stop us. You see, the things I mentioned earlier, and the way of life I described, won’t satisfy [373a] some people, it seems; but couches, tables, and other furniture will have to be added to it, and relishes, of course, and incense, perfumes, prostitutes, pastries—and the multifariousness of each of them. In particular, we cannot just provide them with the necessities16 we mentioned at first, such as houses, clothes, and shoes; no, instead we will have to get painting and [5] embroidery going, and procure gold and ivory and all sorts of everything of that sort. Isn’t that so?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then we will have to enlarge our city again: the healthy one is no longer adequate. On the contrary, we must now increase it in size and population and fill it with a multitude of things that go beyond what is necessary for a city—hunters, for example, and all those imitators. Many of the [5] latter work with shapes and colors; many with music—poets and their assistants, rhapsodes,17 actors, choral dancers, theatrical producers. And there will have to be craftsmen of multifarious devices, including, among other things, those needed for the adornment of women. In particular, then, we [c] will need more servants—don’t you think—such as tutors, wet nurses, nannies, beauticians, barbers, and relish cooks and meat cooks, too? Moreover, we will also need people to farm pigs. This animal did not exist in our earlier [5] city, since there was no need for it, but we will need it in this one. And we will also need large numbers of other meat-producing animals, won’t we, if someone is going to eat them?

 

GLAUCON: We certainly will.

 

SOCRATES: And if we live like that, won’t we have a far greater need for [d] doctors than we did before?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, far greater.

 

SOCRATES: And the land, I take it, that used to be adequate to feed the population we had then will now be small and inadequate. Or don’t you [5] agree?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t we have to seize some of our neighbors’ land, then, if we are to have enough for pasture and plowing? And won’t our neighbors want to seize part of ours in turn, if they too have abandoned themselves to the endless acquisition of money and overstepped the limit of their necessary [10] desires?

 

[e] GLAUCON: Yes, that is quite inevitable, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: And the next step will be war, Glaucon, don’t you agree?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Now, let’s not say yet whether the effects of war are good or [5] bad, but only that we have now found the origin of war: it comes from those same factors, the occurrence of which is the source of the greatest evils for cities and the individuals in them.

 

GLAUCON: Indeed, it does.

 

SOCRATES : The city must be further enlarged, then, my dear Glaucon, and not just a little, but by the size of a whole army. It will do battle with the invaders in defense of the city’s wealth, and of all the other things we [374a] just described.

 

GLAUCON: Why so? Aren’t the inhabitants themselves adequate for that purpose?

 

SOCRATES: No, not, at any rate, if the agreement that you and the rest of us made when we were founding the city was a good one. I think we agreed, if you remember, that it is impossible for a single person to practice [5] many crafts well.

 

GLAUCON: True, we did say that.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, don’t you think that warfare is a craft? [b]

 

GLAUCON: It is, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: So, should we be more concerned about the craft of shoemaking than the craft of warfare?

 

GLAUCON: Not at all. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, now, we prevented a shoemaker from trying to be a farmer, weaver, or builder at the same time, instead of just a shoemaker, in order to ensure that the shoemaker’s job was done well. Similarly, we also assigned just the one job for which he had a natural aptitude to each of the other people, and said that he was to work at it his whole life, free from having to do any of the other jobs, so as not to miss the opportune [5] moments for performing it well. But isn’t it of the greatest importance that warfare be carried out well? Or is fighting a war so easy that a farmer, a shoemaker, or any other artisan can be a soldier at the same time, even [5] though no one can become so much as a good checkers player or dice player if he considers it only as a sideline and does not practice it from childhood? Can someone just pick up a shield, or any other weapon or instrument of war and immediately become a competent fighter in an [d] infantry battle or whatever other sort of battle it may be, even though no other tool makes someone who picks it up a craftsman or an athlete, or is even of any service to him unless he has acquired knowledge of it and has [5] had sufficient practice?

 

GLAUCON: If tools could do that, they would be valuable indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then to the degree that the guardians’ job is of greatest importance, [e] it requires the most freedom from other things, as well as the greatest craft and practice.

 

GLAUCON: I should think so.

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t it also require a person whose nature is suited to that very practice?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then our task, it seems, is to select, if we can, which natures, which sorts of natures, suit people to guard the city.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that is our task.

 

[10] SOCRATES: By Zeus, it is no trivial task that we have taken on, then. All the same, we must not shrink from it, but do the best we can.

 

[375a] GLAUCON: No, we must not.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think that there is any difference, when it comes to the job of guarding, between the nature of a noble hound and that of a well-bred youth?

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

[5] SOCRATES: I mean that both of them have to be sharp-eyed, quick to catch what they see, and strong, too, in case they have to fight what they capture.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they need all these things.

 

SOCRATES: And they must be courageous, surely, if indeed they are to fight well.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Now, will a horse, a dog, or any other animal be courageous if it is not spirited? Or haven’t you noticed just how invincible and unbeatable [b] spirit is, so that its presence makes the whole soul fearless and unconquerable in any situation?

 

GLAUCON: I have noticed that.

 

SOCRATES: Then it is clear what physical qualities the guardians should [5] have.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And as far as their souls are concerned, they must, at any rate, be spirited.

 

GLAUCON: That too.

 

SOCRATES: But with natures like that, Glaucon, how will they avoid [10] behaving like savages to one another and to the other citizens?

 

GLAUCON: By Zeus, it won’t be easy for them.

 

[c] SOCRATES: But surely they must be gentle to their own people and harsh to their enemies. Otherwise, they will not wait around for others to destroy them, but will do it themselves first.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: What are we to do, then? Where are we to find a character that is both gentle and high-spirited at the same time? For, of course, a gentle nature is the opposite of the spirited kind.

 

GLAUCON: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: But surely if someone lacks either of these qualities, he cannot [10] be a good guardian. Yet the combination of them seems to be impossible. And so it follows, then, that a good guardian is impossible. [d]

 

GLAUCON: I am afraid so.

 

I could not see a way out, and on reexamining what had gone before, I said:

 

We deserve to be stuck, my dear Glaucon. For we have lost track of the analogy we put forward. [5]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: We have overlooked the fact that there are natures of the sort we thought impossible, ones that include these opposite qualities.

 

GLAUCON: Where?

 

SOCRATES: You can see the combination in other animals, too, but especially [10] in the one to which we compared the guardian. For you know, of course, that noble hounds naturally have a character of that sort. They are as [5] gentle as can be to those they are familiar with and know, but the opposite to those they do not know.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I do know that. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So the combination we want is possible, after all, and what we are seeking in a good guardian is not contrary to nature.

 

GLAUCON: No, I suppose not.

 

SOCRATES: Now, don’t you think that our future guardian, besides being spirited, must also be, by nature, philosophical?18 [10]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean? I don’t understand. [376a]

 

SOCRATES: It too is something you see in dogs, and it should make us wonder at the merit of the beast.

 

GLAUCON: In what way?

 

SOCRATES: In that when a dog sees someone it does not know, it gets angry even before anything bad happens to it. But when it knows someone, [5] it welcomes him, even if it has never received anything good from him. Have you never wondered at that?

 

GLAUCON: I have never paid it any mind until now. But it is clear that a dog does do that sort of thing. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Well, that seems to be a naturally refined quality, and one that is truly philosophical. [b]

 

GLAUCON: In what way?

 

SOCRATES: In that it judges anything it sees to be either a friend or an enemy on no other basis than that it knows the one and does not know the other. And how could it be anything besides a lover of learning19 if it [5] defines what is its own and what is alien to it in terms of knowledge and ignorance?

 

GLAUCON: It surely could not be anything but.

 

SOCRATES: But surely the love of learning and philosophy are the same, aren’t they?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, they are the same.

 

SOCRATES: Then can’t we confidently assume that the same holds for a human being too—that if he is going to be gentle to his own and those he [c] knows, he must be, by nature, a lover of learning and a philosopher?

 

GLAUCON: We can.

 

SOCRATES: Philosophy, then, and spirit, speed, and strength as well, must all be combined in the nature of anyone who is going to be a really fine and [5] good guardian of our city.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then that is what he would have to be like at the outset. But how are we to bring these people up and educate them? Will inquiring into that topic bring us any closer to the goal of our inquiry, which is to discover [d] the origins of justice and injustice in a city? We want our account to be adequate, but we do not want it to be any longer than necessary.

 

And Glaucon’s brother replied:

 

[5] I for one certainly expect that this inquiry will help us.

 

SOCRATES: By Zeus, in that case, my dear Adeimantus, we must not abandon it, even if it turns out to be a somewhat lengthy affair.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, we must not.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, and like people in a fable telling stories at [10] their leisure, let’s in our discussion educate these men.

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, let’s.

 

SOCRATES: What, then, will the education be? Or is it difficult to find a better one than the one that has been discovered over a long period of time—physical training for bodies and musical training for the soul?20

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Now, won’t we start musical training before physical training?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And you include stories under musical training, don’t you?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do. [10]

 

SOCRATES: But aren’t there two kinds of stories, one true and the other false?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And education must make use of both, but first of the false ones? [377a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do not understand what you mean.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you understand that we first begin by telling stories to children? And surely they are false on the whole, though they have some [5] truth in them. And we use stories on children before physical training.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is what I meant by saying that musical training should be taken up before physical training. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: And you were right.

 

SOCRATES: Now, you know, don’t you, that the beginning of any job is of greatest importance, especially when we are dealing with anything young and tender? For that is when it is especially malleable and best takes [b] on whatever pattern one wishes to impress on it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Precisely so.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we carelessly allow our children to hear any old stories [5] made up by just anyone, then, and to take beliefs into their souls that are, for the most part, the opposite of the ones we think they should hold when they are grown up?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We certainly won’t allow that at all.

 

SOCRATES: So our first task, it seems, is to supervise the storytellers: if they make up a good story, we must accept it; if not, we must reject it. We will persuade nurses and mothers to tell the acceptable ones to their children, [c] and to spend far more time shaping their souls with these stories than they do shaping their bodies by handling them. Many of the stories they tell now, however, must be thrown out. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which sorts?

 

SOCRATES: In the more significant stories, we will see the less significant ones as well. For surely the more significant ones and the less significant ones both follow the same pattern and have the same effects. Don’t you [d] think so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, I do. But I do not understand at all what more significant ones you mean.

 

SOCRATES: The ones Homer, Hesiod, and other poets tell us. After all, they [5] surely composed false stories, which they told and are still telling to people.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which stories do you mean? And what is the fault you find in them?

 

SOCRATES: The first and greatest fault that one ought to find, especially if the falsehood has no good features.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, but what is it?

 

[e] SOCRATES: Using a story to create a bad image of what the gods and heroes are like, just as a painter might paint a picture that is not at all like the things he is trying to paint.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, you are right to find fault with that. But what cases in [5] particular, what sorts of cases, do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: First, the greatest falsehood about the greatest things has no good features—I mean Hesiod telling us about how Uranus behaved, how Cronus punished him for it, and how he was in turn punished [378a] by his own son.21 But even if these stories were true, they should be passed over in silence, I would think, and not told so casually to the foolish and the young. And if, for some reason, they must be told, only a very few people should hear them—people who are pledged to secrecy and have had [5] to sacrifice not just a pig, but something so great and scarce that the number of people who hear them is kept as small as possible.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, those stories are certainly troubling.

 

[b] SOCRATES: And they should not be told in our city, Adeimantus. No young person should hear it said that if he were to commit the worst crimes, he would be doing nothing amazing, or that if he were to inflict every sort of punishment on an unjust father, he would only be doing the [5] same as the first and greatest of the gods.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, I do not think myself that these stories are fit to be told.

 

SOCRATES: Indeed, we must not allow any stories about gods warring, fighting, or plotting against one another if we want the guardians of our city to think that it is shameful to be easily provoked into mutual hatred. After all, those stories are not true either. Still less should battles between [c] gods and giants, or the many other multifarious hostilities of gods and heroes toward their families and friends, occur in the stories the guardians hear or in the embroidered pictures they see. On the contrary, if we are [5] somehow going to persuade our people that no citizen has ever hated another, and that it is impious to do so, then those are the things their male and female elders should tell them from childhood on. And the poets they [d] listen to as they grow older should be compelled to tell them the same sort of thing. Stories about Hera being chained by her son, on the other hand, or about Hephaestus being hurled from heaven by his father when he tried to save his mother from a beating, or about the battle of the gods in Homer, should not be admitted into our city, either as allegories or non-allegories. [5] For the young cannot distinguish what is allegorical from what is not. And the beliefs they absorb at that age are difficult to erase and tend to become unalterable. For these reasons, then, we should probably take the [e] utmost care to ensure that the first stories they hear about virtue are the best ones for them to hear.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that makes sense. But if, at this point too,22 someone were once again to ask us what stories these are, how should we reply? [5]

 

SOCRATES: You and I are not poets at present, Adeimantus, but we are founding a city. And it is appropriate for the founders to know the patterns [379a] on which the poets must base their stories, and from which they must not deviate. But they should not themselves make up any poems.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right. But what precisely are the patterns that stories [5] about the gods must follow?23

 

SOCRATES: Something like this: whether in epic, lyric, or tragedy, a god must always be represented as he is.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, he must. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Now, gods,24 of course, are really good, aren’t they, and must be described as such? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And surely nothing good is harmful, is it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I suppose not.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Well, can what is not harmful do any harm?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, never.

 

SOCRATES: And can what does no harm do anything bad?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, it can’t do that either.

 

SOCRATES: But what does nothing bad could not be the cause of anything bad, could it?

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: No, it could not.

 

SOCRATES: What about what is good? Is it beneficial?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, it is the cause of doing well?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: What is good is not the cause of all things, then. Instead, it is [15] the cause of things that are good, while of bad ones it is not the cause.

 

[c] ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: So, since gods are good, they are not—as the masses claim—the cause of everything. Instead, they are a cause of only a few things that happen to human beings, while of most they are not the cause. For good things are fewer than bad ones in our lives. Of the good things, they alone are the [5] cause, but we must find some other cause for the bad ones, not the gods.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true in my view.

 

SOCRATES: Then we won’t accept from Homer—or from anyone else—[d] the foolish mistake he makes about the gods when he says: “There are two urns at the threshold of Zeus, one filled with good fates, the other with bad [5] ones,” and the person to whom Zeus gives a mixture of these “sometimes meets with a bad fate, sometimes with a good one.” But the one who receives his fate entirely from the second urn, “evil famine drives over the [e] divine earth.” Nor will we tolerate the saying that “Zeus is the dispenser of both good and bad to mortals.” As for the breaking of the oaths and the truce by Pandarus, if anyone tells us that it was brought about by Athena and Zeus, or that Themis and Zeus were responsible for strife and contention [5] among the gods, we won’t praise him. Nor will we allow the young to [380a] hear the words of Aeschylus: “A god makes mortals guilty, when he wants to destroy a house utterly.”25 And if anyone composes a poem, such as the [5] one those lines are from, about the sufferings of Niobe, or about the house of Pelops, or the tale of Troy, or anything else of that sort, he should be required to say that these things are not the works of a god. Or, if they are the works of a god, then the poet must look for roughly the sort of account of them we are now seeking: he must say that the actions of the gods are good and just, and that the people they punish are benefited by them. We [b] won’t allow him to say that those who are punished are made wretched, and that it was a god who made them so; but we will allow him to say that bad people are wretched because they are in need of punishment, and that in paying the penalty they are benefited by that god. But as for saying that a [5] god, who is himself good, is the cause of evils, we will fight that in every way. We won’t allow anyone to say it in his own city, if it is to be well governed, or anyone to hear it either—whether young or old, whether with meter or without meter. For these stories are impious, disadvantageous to [c] us, and not in concord with one another.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I like your law, and I will vote with you for it. [5]

 

SOCRATES: This, then, will be one of the laws or patterns relating to gods that speakers and poets will have to follow: that gods are not the cause of all things, but only of good ones.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And an entirely satisfactory one it is. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Now, what about this second law? Do you think that gods are sorcerers who deliberately take different forms at different times, sometimes [d] by changing on their own and altering their own form into a large number of shapes, sometimes by deceiving us into thinking they have done so? Or are they simple beings, and least of all likely to abandon their own form? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I can’t say offhand.

 

SOCRATES: Well, if something abandons its own form, mustn’t it either cause the change itself or be changed by something else? [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It must.

 

SOCRATES: Now, the best things are least liable to alteration or change, aren’t they? For example, a body is altered by food, drink, and labors, and all plants by sun, winds, and other similar affections—but the healthiest and [5] strongest is least altered, isn’t that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course. [381a]

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t a soul that is most courageous and most knowledgeable be least disturbed or altered by any outside influence?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And the same account surely also applies even to manufactured items, such as implements, houses, and clothes: those that are good and well made are least altered by time or any other influences.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: So whatever is in good condition—whether due to nature or [b] craft or both—is least subject to change by something else.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It seems so.

 

SOCRATES: But gods, of course, as well as the things belonging to them, are best in every way.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: They certainly are.

 

SOCRATES: So, on this view, gods would be least likely to have many forms.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Least likely, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then would they change or alter themselves?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly so, if indeed they are altered at all.

 

SOCRATES: Do they change themselves into something better and more [10] beautiful, or into something worse and uglier, than themselves?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It would have to be into something worse, if indeed they [c] are altered at all. For surely we won’t say that gods are deficient in either beauty or virtue.

 

SOCRATES: You are absolutely right. And do you think, Adeimantus, that anyone, whether god or human, would deliberately make himself worse in [5] any way?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, that is impossible.

 

SOCRATES: It is also impossible, then, for a god to want to alter himself.

 

On the contrary, since each god is, it seems, as beautiful and as good as possible, he must always unqualifiedly retain his own form.

 

ADEIMANTUS: In my view, at least, that is absolutely necessary.

 

[d] SOCRATES: None of our poets, then, my very good man, is to say that “The gods, like strangers from foreign lands, assume many disguises when [5] [5] they visit our cities.”26 Nor must they tell lies about Proteus and Thetis, or present Hera, in their tragedies or other poems, disguised as a priestess collecting alms for “the life-giving sons of the Argive river Inachus,”27 or tell us [e] any of the many other such lies. Nor should mothers, influenced by these stories, which terrify children, tell bad tales about gods who go wandering around at night in the guises of many strange and multifarious beings, lest [5] they blaspheme the gods and, at the same time, make their children too cowardly.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, they should not.

 

SOCRATES: But, though the gods themselves are the sorts of things that cannot change, do they make us think that they appear in multifarious guises, deceiving us and using sorcery on us? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Perhaps they do.

 

SOCRATES: What? Would a god be willing to lie by presenting in word or [382a] deed what is only an illusion?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I don’t know.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you know that all gods and humans hate a true lie, if one may call it that? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: I mean that no one intentionally wants to lie about the most important things to what is most important in himself. On the contrary, he fears to hold a lie there more than anything.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I still don’t understand. [10]

 

SOCRATES: That is because you think I am saying something deep. I simply mean that to lie and to have lied to the soul about the things that are,28 [b] and to be ignorant, and to have and hold a lie there, is what everyone would least of all accept; indeed, they especially hate it there. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: They certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: But surely, as I was saying just now, it would be most correct to say that it is truly speaking a lie—the ignorance in the soul of the one to whom the lie was told. For a lie in words is a sort of imitation of this affection in the soul, an image of it that comes into being after it, and not an altogether [10] pure lie. Isn’t that so? [c]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is.

 

SOCRATES: A real lie, then, is hated not only by the gods, but also by human beings.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think it is. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What about a lie in words? Aren’t there times when it is useful, and so does not merit hatred? What about when we are dealing with enemies, or with so-called friends who, because of insanity or ignorance, are attempting to do something bad? Isn’t it a useful drug for preventing them? [10] And consider the case of those stories we were talking about just now—those we tell because we do not know the truth about those ancient events: [d] by making the lies that they contain as much like the truth as possible, don’t we make them useful?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We most certainly do.

 

[5] SOCRATES : In which of these ways, then, could a lie be useful to a god? Would he lie by making likenesses of the truth about ancient events because of his ignorance of them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It would be ridiculous to think that.

 

SOCRATES: Then there is nothing of the lying poet in a god?

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Not in my view.

 

SOCRATES: Would he lie, then, through fear of his enemies?

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: Hardly.

 

SOCRATES: Because of the foolishness or insanity of his family or friends, then?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No one who is foolish or mad is a friend of the gods.

 

SOCRATES: So a god has no reason to lie?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: None.

 

SOCRATES: So both what is daimonic29 and what is divine are entirely free of lies.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: A god, then, is altogether simple, true in both word and deed. He does not change himself or deceive others by means of images, by [10] words, or by sending signs, whether they are awake or dreaming.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That is my view—at any rate, now that I have heard what [383a] you have to say.

 

SOCRATES: You agree, then, that this is the second pattern people must follow when speaking or composing poems about the gods: the gods are not sorcerers who change themselves, nor do they mislead us by telling lies [5] in word or deed.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: Even though we praise many things in Homer, then, we won’t approve of Zeus’ sending the dream to Agamemnon, nor of Aeschylus [b] when he makes Thetis say that Apollo sang, in prophecy at her wedding:

 

About the good luck my children would have,

Free of disease throughout their long lives,

And of all the blessings the friendship of the gods would bring me.

I hoped that Phoebus’ divine mouth would be free of lies,

Endowed as it is with the craft of prophecy.

But the very god who sang, the one at the feast,

The one who said all that, he himself it is

Who killed my son.30

 

Whenever anyone says such things about a god, we will be angry with him, refuse him a chorus,31 and not allow teachers to use what he says for the [c] education of the young—not if our guardians are going to be as god-fearing and godlike as human beings can be. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I agree completely about these patterns, and I would use them as laws.

 

1 See Glossary of Terms s.v. being.

2 See Glossary of Terms s.v. do better.

3 At 612b4, the ring is assigned to Gyges himself, not his ancestor.

4 In Seven against Thebes 592–4, it is said of Amphiaraus that “he did not wish to be believed to be the best but to be it.” The passage continues with the words Glaucon quotes below at 362a–b.

5 See Homer, Odyssey 16.97–8.

6 Hesiod, Works and Days 332–3.

7 Homer, Odyssey 19.109.

8 Works and Days 287–9, with minor alterations.

9 Iliad 9.497–501, with minor alterations.

10 The quotation is attributed to Simonides, who is cited by Polemarchus in Book 1.

11 See Glossary of Terms s.v. illusionistic painting.

12 At 361b–c.

13 Ekeinou tou andros: Sometimes taken to be a facetious, indexical reference to Thra-symachus,whose heirs (sons) in the argument Glaucon and Adeimantus self-confessedly are. It is more likely, however, that it is an honorific expression equivalent in meaning to “that well-known man.”

14 Homosexual relations between older men and late-adolescent boys were an acceptable part of Athenian social life, especially among the upper classes. See K. J.

Dover, Greek Homosexuality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978).

15 See Glossary of Terms s.v. relish.

16 See 558d8–559d2.

17 See Glossary of Terms s.v. rhapsode.

18 Philosophos: used here in its general sense to refer to intellectual curiosity or wanting knowledge for its own sake.

19Philomathês.

20 See Glossary of Terms s.v. physical training, musical training.

21 Uranus prevented his wife, Gaia, from giving birth to his children by blocking them up inside her. Gaia gave a sickle to one of these children, Cronus, which he used to castrate his father when the latter next had intercourse with her. Cronus ate the children he had by his wife, Rhea, until, by deceiving him with a stone, she was able to save Zeus from suffering this fate. Zeus then overthrew his father. See Hesiod, Theogony 154–210, 453–506.

22 As at 377d10.

23 Theologia: theology.

24 Ho theos: literally, “the god.” But the definite article is almost certainly functioning as a universal quantifier, as in “The swallow is a migratory bird,” which means (all) swallows migrate.

25 The first three quotations are from Iliad 24.527–32. The sources for the fourth, and for the quotation from Aeschylus, are unknown. The story of Athena urging Pandarus to break the truce is told at Iliad 4.73–126.

26 Odyssey 17. 485–6.

27 Inachus was the father of Io, who was persecuted by Hera because Zeus was in love with her. The source for the part of the story Plato quotes is unknown.

28 See Glossary of Terms s.v. thing that is.

29 See Glossary of Terms s.v. daimon.

30 At Iliad 2.1–34, Zeus sends a dream to Agamemnon to promise success if he attacks Troy immediately. The promise is false. The source for the quotation from Aeschylus is unknown.

31 I.e., deny him the funding necessary to hire a chorus of actors and produce his play.

Book 3

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION CONTINUES:

[386a] SOCRATES: Where the gods are concerned, then, it seems that those are the sorts of stories the future guardians should and should not hear from childhood on, if they are to honor the gods and their parents, and not treat lightly their friendship with one another.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: I am sure we are right about that.

 

SOCRATES: What about if they are to be courageous? Shouldn’t they be told stories that will make them least likely to fear death? Or do you think [b] that anyone ever becomes courageous if he has that fear in his heart?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: What about if someone believes that Hades exists and is full of [5] terrible things? Can anyone with that fear be unafraid of death and prefer it to defeat in battle and slavery?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Then we must also supervise those who try to tell such stories, it seems, and ask them not to disparage the life in Hades in this undiscriminating way, but to speak well of it, since what they now tell us is neither [c] true nor beneficial to future warriors.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, we must.

 

SOCRATES: We will start with the following lines, then, and expunge everything like them: “I would rather labor on earth in another man’s service, a man who is landless, with little to live on, than be king over all the dead”;1 and this: “He feared that his home should be revealed to mortals [d] and immortals as dreadful, dank, and hated even by the gods;”2 and: “Alas, there survives in the Halls of Hades a soul, a mere phantasm, with its wits completely gone”;3 and this: “He alone can think others to be flitting shadows”;4 and: “The soul, leaving his limbs, made its way to Hades, lamenting its fate, leaving manhood and youth behind”;5 and this: “His [387a] soul went below the earth like smoke, screeching as it went”;6 and:

 

As when bats in an awful cave

Fly around screeching if one of them falls

From the cluster on the ceiling, all clinging to one another,
so their souls went screeching.7

 

We will beg Homer and the rest of the poets not to be angry if we delete [b] these and all similar passages—not because they are not poetic and pleasing to the masses when they hear them, but because the more poetic they are, the more they should be kept away from the ears of children and men who are to be free and to fear slavery more than death. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then, in addition, we must also get rid of the terrible and frightening names that occur in such passages: Cocytus, Styx,8 “those [c] below,” “the sapless ones,” and all the other names of the same pattern that supposedly make everyone who hears them shudder. Perhaps they are useful for other purposes, but our fear is that all that shuddering will make our guardians more emotional and soft than they ought to be. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: And our fear is justified.

 

SOCRATES: Should we remove them, then?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And follow the opposite pattern in speech and poetry?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Shall we also remove the lamentations and pitiful speeches of famous men? [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: If what we did before was necessary, so is that.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, though, whether we will be right to remove them or not. What we claim is that a good man won’t think that death is a terrible thing for another good one to suffer—even if the latter happens to be his friend. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, we do claim that.

 

SOCRATES: So, he won’t mourn for him as if he had suffered a terrible fate.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: But we also claim this: a good person is most self-sufficient when it comes to living well, and is distinguished from other people by [e] having the least need of anyone or anything else.

 

ADEIMANTUS: True.

 

SOCRATES: So it is less terrible for him than for anyone else to be deprived of a son, brother, possessions, or the like.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, much less.

 

SOCRATES: So, he will lament it the least and bear it the most calmly when some such misfortune overtakes him.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: We would be right, then, to remove the lamentations of [10] famous men. We would leave them to women (provided they are not excellent [388a] women) and cowardly men, so that those we say we are training to guard our land will be ashamed to do such things.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: In addition, then, we will have to ask Homer and the other [5] poets not to represent Achilles, who was the son of a goddess, as:

 

Lying now on his side, now on his back, now again

On his belly; then standing up to wander distracted

This way and that on the shore of the unharvested sea;9

 

[b] or to make him pick up ashes with both hands and pour them over his head, weeping and lamenting to the extent and in the manner Homer describes;10 [5] or to represent Priam, a close descendant of the gods, as “begging and rolling around in dung, as he calls upon each of his men by name.”11 And yet more insistently than that, we will ask them at least not to make the gods lament and say: “Woe is me, unfortunate that I am, wretched mother of a [c] great son.”12 But, if they do make the gods do such things, at least they must not dare to represent the greatest of the gods in so unlikely a fashion as to make him say: “Alas, with my own eyes I see a man who is most dear to me being chased around the city, and my heart laments”;13 or “Woe is me, that Sarpedon, who is most dear to me, should be fated to be killed by Patroclus, the son of Menoetius.”14 You see, my dear Adeimantus, if our young people listen [d] seriously to these stories without ridiculing them as not worth hearing, none of them is going to consider such things to be unworthy of a mere human being like himself, or rebuke himself if it occurred to him to do or say any of them. On the contrary, without shame or perseverance, he would [5] chant many dirges and laments at the slightest sufferings.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true. [e]

 

SOCRATES: But that must not happen, as our argument has shown—and we must remain persuaded by it until someone shows us a better one.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, it must not.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, they must not be lovers of laughter either. For [5] whenever anyone gives in to violent laughter, a violent reaction pretty much always follows.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: So, if someone represents worthwhile people as overcome by laughter, we must not accept it, and we will accept it even less if they represent the gods in that way. [389a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Much less.

 

SOCRATES: Then we must not accept the following sorts of sayings about the gods from Homer: “And unquenchable laughter arose among the blessed gods as they saw Hephaestus limping through the hall.”15 According [5] to your argument, they must be rejected.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, if you want to attribute it to me, but they must be rejected in any case. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we have to be concerned about truth as well. For if what we said just now is correct and a lie is really useless to the gods, but useful to human beings as a form of drug, it is clear that it must be assigned to doctors, whereas private individuals must have nothing to do with it. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is clear.

 

SOCRATES: It is appropriate for the rulers, then, if anyone, to lie because of enemies or citizens for the good of the city. But no one else may have anything to do with it. On the contrary, we will say that for a private individual to lie to such rulers is as bad a mistake as for a sick person not to tell [c] his doctor or an athlete his trainer the truth about his physical condition, or for someone not to tell the captain the things that are true about the ship and the sailors, or about how he himself or one of his fellow sailors is faring—[5] indeed, it is a worse mistake.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

[d] SOCRATES: So, if anyone else is caught telling lies in the city—“any of the craftsmen, whether a prophet, a doctor who heals the sick, or a carpenter who works in wood”16—he will be punished for introducing a practice that [5] is as subversive and destructive of a city as of a ship.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed it is, at any rate, if what people do is influenced by what he says.

 

SOCRATES: What about temperance?17 Won’t our young people also need that?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t the greatest parts of temperance—at any rate for the majority of people—consist in obedience to the rulers and ruling over the pleasures [e] of drink, sex, and food for themselves?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That is my view, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: So we will claim, I imagine, that it is fine to say the sort of [5] thing that Diomedes says in Homer: “Sit down in silence, my friend, and be persuaded by my story”;18 and what follows it: “The Achaeans went in silently, breathing valor, afraid of their commanders”;19 and anything else of [10] that sort.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is fine.

 

SOCRATES: But what about things like, “You drunkard, with the eyes of a dog and the heart of a deer,” and what follows it?20 Are they, then, fine [390a] things to say? And what about all the other headstrong things that private individuals say to their rulers in works of prose or poetry?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, they are not fine.

 

SOCRATES: That, I imagine, is because they are not suitable for inculcating temperance in the young people who hear them. But it would not be surprising [5] if they were found pleasant in some other context. What do you think?

 

ADEIMANTUS: The same as you.

 

SOCRATES: What about making the wisest man say that the best thing of all, as it seems to him, is when “the tables are well laden with bread and meat, and the wine-bearer draws wine from the mixing bowl, brings it, and [b] pours it in the cups”?21 Do you think that hearing things like that is suitable for inculcating self-mastery in young people? Or that “death by starvation is the most pitiful fate”?22 Or about how Zeus stayed awake alone deliberating, [5] when all the other gods and mortals were asleep, and then easily forgot all his plans because of his sexual appetite, and was so overcome by the sight [c] of Hera that he did not even want to go to their bedroom, but to possess her there on the ground, saying that his appetite for her was even greater than it was when they first made love to one another “without their parents’ [5] knowledge”?23 Or what about the chaining together of Ares and Aphrodite by Hephaestus24 for similar reasons?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, that does not seem suitable to me.

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, if there are any words or deeds of famous men that express perseverance in the face of everything, surely they must be [d] seen and heard. For example, “He struck his chest and spoke to his heart: ‘Bear up, my heart, you have suffered more shameful things than this.’”25 [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And we must not, of course, allow our men to be bribable with gifts or to be money-lovers.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly not. [e]

 

SOCRATES: Then they must not sing: “Gifts persuade gods, and gifts persuade revered kings.”26 Nor must we praise Phoenix, the tutor of Achilles, for being moderate, when he advises Achilles to take the gifts and defend [5] the Achaeans, but not to lay aside his anger without gifts.27 Nor should we agree that Achilles himself was such a money-lover as to accept the gifts of Agamemnon, or to release a corpse when he got paid for it, but otherwise to refuse.28 [391a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, it certainly is not right to praise such things.

 

SOCRATES: It is only out of respect for Homer, indeed, that I hesitate to say that it is positively impious to accuse Achilles of such things, or to [5] believe them when others say them. Or to believe that he said to Apollo: “You have injured me, Farshooter, most deadly of the gods; And I would punish you, if only I had the power.”29 Or that he disobeyed the river—a [b] god—and was ready to fight it.30 Or that he consecrated hair to the dead Patroclus, which he had already consecrated to the other river, Sphercheius:

 

“To the hero, Patroclus, I give my hair to take with him.”31 We must not believe that he did that. Nor is it true that he dragged the dead Hector around the tomb of Patroclus32 or massacred the captives on his pyre.33 So we will deny these things. Nor will we allow our people to believe that [c] Achilles—the son of a goddess and of Peleus (who was himself the most temperate of men and the grandson of Zeus), and the pupil of the most wise Cheiron—was so full of inner disorder as to have two opposite diseases within him: illiberality accompanied by the love of money on the one [5] hand, and arrogance toward gods and humans on the other.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we will neither believe nor allow it to be said that Theseus, the son of Poseidon, and Peirithous, the son of Zeus, ever [d] attempted those terrible rapes,34 nor that any other child of a god and hero dared to do any of the terrible and impious deeds that are now falsely attributed to them. We will compel the poets either to deny that they did such things, or else to deny that they were children of the gods. But they [5] must not say both or attempt to persuade our young people that the gods produce evils, nor that heroes are no better than humans. After all, as we [e] were saying earlier, these things are neither pious nor true. For we demonstrated, I take it, that it is impossible for the gods to produce evils.35

 

ADEIMANTUS: We certainly did.

 

SOCRATES: And they are also positively harmful to those who hear them. You see, everyone will be ready to excuse himself when he is bad, [5] if he has been persuaded that similar things are done and were done by “close descendants of the gods, near kin of Zeus, whose ancestral altar is in the ether on Ida’s peak,” and “in whom the blood of daimons has not weakened.”36 That is why we must put a stop to such stories; if we do not, they will produce in our young people a very casual attitude to evil. [392a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: What kind of stories are still left, then, about which we must determine whether or not they may be told? I mean, we have discussed how gods, heroes, daimons, and things in Hades should be portrayed. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: We have.

 

SOCRATES: Then wouldn’t stories about human beings be left?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Obviously so.

 

SOCRATES: But it is not possible, my friend, to discuss them here. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Why not?

 

SOCRATES: Because what we are going say, I imagine, is that poets and prose writers get the greatest things concerning human beings wrong. They say that many unjust people are happy and many just ones wretched, [b] that doing injustice is profitable if it escapes detection, and that justice is another’s good but one’s own loss. We will forbid them to say such things, I imagine, and order them to sing and tell the opposite. Don’t you think so? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, I know so.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if you agree that what I said is correct, won’t I say to you that you have conceded the point we were investigating all along?

 

ADEIMANTUS: And your claim would be correct.

 

SOCRATES: Then we won’t come to an agreement about what stories should be told about human beings until we have discovered what sort of [c] thing justice is, and how, given its nature, it profits the one who has it, whether he is believed to be just or not.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely right. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Our discussion of the content of stories is complete, then. Our next task, I take it, is to investigate their style. And then we will have completely investigated both what they should say and how they should say it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I don’t understand what you mean. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Well, we must see that you do. Maybe this will help you to grasp it better: isn’t everything said by poets and storytellers a narration of [d] past, present, or future events?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t they proceed by narration alone, narration through imitation, or both? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I need a still clearer understanding of that, too.

 

SOCRATES: What a ridiculously unclear teacher I seem to be! So, I will do what incompetent speakers do: I won’t try to deal with the subject as a whole. Instead, I will take up a particular example and use that to explain [e] what I mean. Tell me, do you know the beginning of the Iliad where the poet tells us that Chryses begged Agamemnon to release his daughter, that Agamemnon got angry, and that Chryses, having failed to get what he [393a] wanted, prayed to his god37 to punish the Achaeans?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: You know, then, that up to the lines, “He begged all the Achaeans, but especially the commanders of the army, the two sons of [5] Atreus,”38 the poet himself is speaking and is not trying to make us think that the speaker is anyone but himself. After that, however, he speaks as if he himself were Chryses, and tries as hard as he can to make us think that [b] the speaker is not Homer, but the priest himself, who is an old man. And all the rest of his narration of the events in Ilium and Ithaca, and all of the Odyssey, are written in pretty much the same way.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, they are.

 

SOCRATES: Now, each of the speeches, as well as the material between them, is narration, isn’t it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But when he makes a speech as if he were someone else, won’t [c] we say that he makes his own style as much like that of the person he tells us is about to speak?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We certainly will.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Now, to make oneself like someone else in voice or appearance is to imitate the person one makes oneself like, isn’t it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then in a passage of that sort, it seems, he, and the rest of poets as well, produce their narration through imitation.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: But if the poet never disguised himself, his entire poem would [d] be narration without imitation. To prevent you from saying that you still do not understand, I will tell you what that would be like. If Homer said that Chryses came with a ransom for his daughter to supplicate the Achaeans, [5] especially the kings, and if after that Homer had gone on speaking, not as if he had become Chryses, but still as Homer, you know that it would not be imitation but narration pure and simple. It would have gone something like this—I will speak without meter since I am not a poet: the priest came and prayed that the gods would grant it to the Achaeans to capture Troy and have [e] a safe return home, and he entreated them to accept the ransom and free his daughter, out of reverence for the god.39 When he had said this, the others approved of it and consented. But Agamemnon was angry and ordered him to leave and never return, or else his priestly wand and the wreaths of the [5] god would not protect him. He said that the priest’s daughter would grow old in Argos by his side sooner than be freed. He ordered Chryses to leave and not make him angry if he wanted to get home safely. When the old man heard this, he was frightened and went off in silence. And once he had left [394a] the camp, he prayed at length to Apollo, invoking the cult names of the god, reminding him of his past gifts, and asking to be repaid for any that had found favor with him, whether they were temples he had built or victims he had sacrificed. He prayed that, in return for these things, the arrows of the [5] god would make the Achaeans pay for his tears. That, comrade, is how we get pure narration without any imitation. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I understand.

 

SOCRATES: Also understand, then, that the opposite occurs when one omits the words between the speeches and leaves the speeches on their own. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS : I understand that, too; it is what happens in tragedies, for example.

 

SOCRATES: You have got it absolutely right. And now I think I can make clear to you what I could not before. One sort of poetry and storytelling employs only imitation—tragedy, as you said, and comedy. Another sort, [c] which you find primarily in dithyrambs,40 employs only narration by the poet himself. A third sort, which uses both, is what we find in epic poetry and many other places. Do you follow me? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, now I understand what you meant.

 

SOCRATES: And before that, as you remember, we said that we had already dealt with content, but that we had yet to investigate style .

 

ADEMANTUS : Yes, I remember.

 

SOCRATES: What I meant, then, was just this: we need to come to an [d] agreement about whether to allow our poets to narrate as imitators, or as imitators of some things, but not others—and what sorts of things these are; or not to allow them to imitate at all.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I imagine that you are considering whether we will admit [5] tragedy and comedy into our city or not.

 

SOCRATES: Perhaps so, but it may be an even wider question than that. I really do not know yet. But wherever the wind of argument blows us, so to speak, that is where we must go.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, well put.

 

SOCRATES: What I want you to consider, then, Adeimantus, is whether [e] our guardians should be imitators or not. Or does the answer follow from what we have said already—namely, that whereas each individual can practice one pursuit well, he cannot practice many well, and if he tried to do this and dabbled in many things, he would surely fail to achieve distinction [5] in all of them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course. Why wouldn’t it?

 

SOCRATES: Then doesn’t the same principle also apply to imitation—namely, that a single individual cannot imitate many things as well as he can imitate one?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, he cannot.

 

SOCRATES: Then he will hardly be able to practice any pursuit worth talking [395a] about while at the same time imitating lots of things and being an imitator. For, as you know, even when two sorts of imitation are thought to be closely akin, the same people are not able to practice both of them well simultaneously. The writing of tragedy and comedy is an example. Didn’t [5] you just call both of these imitations?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I did, and you are quite right; the same people cannot do both.

 

SOCRATES: Nor can they be both rhapsodes and actors simultaneously.

 

ADEIMANTUS: True.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Indeed, the same men cannot be used as both tragic and comic [b] actors. And all these are imitations, aren’t they?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They are.

 

SOCRATES: And human nature, Adeimantus, seems to me to be minted in even smaller coins than this, so that an individual can neither imitate many [5] things well nor perform well the actions themselves of which those imitations are likenesses.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: So, if we are to preserve our first argument, that our guardians must be kept away from all other crafts so as to be the most exact craftsmen [c] of the city’s freedom, and practice nothing at all except what contributes to this, then they must neither do nor imitate anything else. But if they imitate anything, they must imitate right from childhood what is appropriate for them—that is to say, people who are courageous, temperate, pious, free, and everything of that sort. On the other hand, they must not be clever at [5] doing or imitating illiberal or shameful actions, so that they won’t acquire a taste for the real thing from imitating it. Or haven’t you noticed that imitations, if they are practiced much past youth, get established in the habits [d] and nature of body, tones of voice, and mind?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I have indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Since those we claim to care about are men, then, and men [5] who must become good, we won’t allow them to imitate a woman, young or old, as she abuses her husband, quarrels with the gods, brags because she thinks herself happy, or suffers misfortune and is possessed by sorrows and lamentations—and still less a woman who is ill, passionately in love, or in [e] labor.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely not.

 

SOCRATES: Nor must they imitate either male or female slaves doing servile actions. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, they must not.

 

SOCRATES: Nor cowardly, bad men, it seems, or those whose actions are the opposite of what we described just now—men who libel and ridicule each other, and use shameful language when drunk or even when sober, or who wrong themselves and others by word or deed in the other ways that are typical of such people. And they must not get into the habit, I take it, of [396a] acting or talking like madmen. They must know, of course, about mad and evil men and women, but they must not do or imitate anything they do. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: What about metalworkers or other craftsmen, or those who row in triremes, or their coxswains, or the like—should they imitate them? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, they should not, since they are not allowed even to pay any mind to those pursuits.

 

SOCRATES: And what about neighing horses, bellowing bulls, roaring rivers, [5] the crashing sea, thunder, or the like—will they imitate them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, they have already been forbidden to be mad or to imitate madmen.

 

SOCRATES: So you are saying, if I understand you, that there is one kind of [10] style and narration that a really good and fine person would use whenever he had to say something, and another kind, unlike that one, which his opposite by nature and education would always favor, and in which he [c] would narrate his story.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What kinds are they?

 

SOCRATES: In my view, when a moderate man comes upon the words or actions of a good man in the course of a narration, he will be willing to report them as if he were that man himself, and he won’t be ashamed of that sort of imitation. He will be most willing to imitate the good man when he is [d] acting in a faultless and intelligent manner, but less willing and more reluctant to do so when he is upset by disease, passion, drunkenness, or some other misfortune. When he comes upon a character who is beneath him, however, he will be unwilling to make himself resemble this inferior character in any serious way—except perhaps for a brief period in which he is doing something [5] good. On the contrary, he will be ashamed to do something like that, both because he is unpracticed in the imitation of such people, and also because he cannot stand to shape and mold himself on an inferior pattern. In [e] his mind he despises that, except when it is for the sake of amusement.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t he use the sorts of narration, then, that we described in dealing with the Homeric epics a moment ago? And though his style of [5] [5] speaking will involve both imitation and the other sort of narration, won’t imitation play a small part even in a long story? Or am I talking nonsense?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all. That must indeed be the pattern followed by that [10] sort of speaker.

 

SOCRATES: As for the other sort of speaker, the more inferior he is, the [397a] more willing he will be to narrate anything and to consider nothing beneath him. Hence he will undertake to imitate, before a large audience and in a serious way, all the things we just mentioned: thunder and the [5] sounds of winds, hail, axles, and pulleys; trumpets, flutes, pipes, and all the other instruments; and even the cries of dogs, sheep, and birds. And his [b] style will consist entirely of imitation in voice and gesture, won’t it, with possibly a small bit of plain narration thrown in?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that must be so, too.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is what I meant when I said that there are two kinds of style.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: And you were right; there are.

 

SOCRATES: Now, one of them involves little variation.41 Hence if an appropriate harmony and rhythm are provided for this style, won’t anyone who speaks in it correctly come close to speaking in a single harmony and, what is more, in a rhythm of pretty much the same sort, since the variations [c] involved in it are slight?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s precisely what he will do.

 

SOCRATES: What about the other kind of style? Won’t it need the opposite: namely, every harmony and every rhythm, if it, too, is going to be spoken in properly, since it is multifarious in the forms of its variations? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s very much what it is like.

 

SOCRATES: Now, doesn’t every poet and speaker adopt a style that fits one or the other of these patterns, or a mixture of both? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: What are we to do, then? Shall we admit all of these into our city, or one of the pure sorts, or the mixed one? [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: If my view prevails, we will admit only the pure imitator of the good person. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And yet, Adeimantus, the mixed style is pleasing. And the one that is most pleasing to children, their tutors, and the vast majority of people is the opposite of the one you chose.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is the most pleasing.

 

SOCRATES: But perhaps you would say that it does not harmonize with our constitution, because there is no twofold or manifold man among us, [e] since each does only one job.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, it does not harmonize with it.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t that the reason that it is only in a city like ours that we will find a shoemaker who is a shoemaker, not a ship’s captain who also [5] makes shoes; and a farmer who is a farmer, not a juror who also farms; and a soldier who is a soldier, not a moneymaker who also soldiers, and so on?

 

ADEIMANTUS: True, it is.

 

SOCRATES: Suppose, then, that a man whose wisdom enabled him to become multifarious and imitate everything were to arrive in person in our [398a] city and want to give a performance of his poems. It seems that we would bow down before him as someone holy, amazing, and pleasing. But we would tell him that there is no man like him in our city, and that it is not in [5] accord with divine law for there to be one. Then we would anoint his head with perfumes, crown him with a woolen wreath,42 and send him away to another city. But, for our own benefit, we would employ a more austere and less pleasant poet and storyteller ourselves—one who would imitate the [b] speech of a good person and make his stories fit the patterns we laid down at the beginning, when we undertook to educate our soldiers.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is certainly what we would do, if it were up to us. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And now, my friend, it looks to me as though we have completed our discussion of the branch of musical training that deals with speech and stories. After all, we have discussed both what is to be said and how it is to be said.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it seems that way to me, too.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t what is left for us to discuss next, then, be lyric odes [c] and songs?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And couldn’t anyone discover by now what to say about what they must be like, if indeed it is going to be concordant with what has [5] already been said?

 

And Glaucon laughed and said:

 

I am afraid, Socrates, that “anyone” does not include me. You see, it is not sufficiently clear to me at the moment what we are to say, though I have [10] my suspicions.

 

SOCRATES: Nonetheless, you are sufficiently clear about this: first, that a [d] song consists of three elements—speech, harmony, and rhythm.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I do know that, at least.

 

SOCRATES: Now, as far as speech is concerned, at any rate, it is no different, is it, from speech that is not part of a song, in that it must still be spoken [5] in conformity to the patterns we established just now?

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: Further, the harmony and rhythm must fit the speech.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But we said that there is no longer a need for dirges and lamentations in words.43

 

GLAUCON: No, there is not.

 

SOCRATES: What are the lamenting harmonies, then? You tell me; you are [e] musical.

 

GLAUCON: The mixo-Lydian, the syntono-Lydian, and some others of that sort.

 

SOCRATES: Shouldn’t we exclude them, then? After all, they are even useless for helping women to be as good as they should be, let alone men.

 

GLAUCON: We certainly should.

 

SOCRATES: Now, surely drunkenness is also entirely inappropriate for our guardians, and softness and idleness as well.

 

G LAUCON: Of course. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What, then, are the soft harmonies, and the ones suitable for drinking parties?

 

GLAUCON: There are some Ionian ones that are called “relaxed,” and also some Lydian ones. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Could you use any of them, my friend, on men who are warriors? [399a]

 

GLAUCON: No, never. So it looks as though you have got the Dorian and Phrygian left.

 

SOCRATES: I do not know the harmonies, so just leave me that harmony [5] that would appropriately imitate the vocal sounds and tones44 of a courageous person engaged in battle or in other work that he is forced to do, and who—even when he fails and faces wounds or death or some other misfortune—always grapples with what chances to occur, in a disciplined and resolute [b] way. And also leave me another harmony for when he is engaged in peaceful enterprises, or in those he is not forced to do but does willingly; or for when he is trying to persuade someone of something, or entreating a god though prayer, or a human being through instruction and advice; or for when he is doing the opposite—patiently listening to someone else, [5] who is entreating or instructing him, or trying to change his mind through persuasion. Leave me the harmony that will imitate him, when he does not behave arrogantly when these things turn out as he intends; but, on the contrary, is temperate and moderate in all these enterprises, and satisfied with their outcomes. Leave me these two harmonies, then—the forced and [c] the willing—that will best imitate the voices of temperate and courageous men in good fortune and in bad.

 

GLAUCON: You are asking to be left with the very ones I just mentioned. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, we will have no need for multi-stringed or polyharmonic instruments to accompany our odes and songs.

 

GLAUCON: No, it seems to me we won’t.

 

SOCRATES: Then we won’t maintain craftsmen who make triangular lutes, [10] harps, and all other such multi-stringed and polyharmonic instruments. [d]

 

GLAUCON: Apparently not.

 

SOCRATES: What about flute-makers and flute players? Will you allow them into the city? Or isn’t the flute the most multi-stringed of all?45 And [5] aren’t polyharmonic instruments all imitations of it?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly, they are.

 

SOCRATES: You have the lyre and the cithara left, then, as useful in our city; and in the countryside, by contrast, there would be a sort of pipe for the herdsman to play.

 

[10] GLAUCON: That is what our argument suggests, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: Well we are certainly not doing anything new, my friend, in [e] preferring Apollo and his instruments to Marsyas and his.46

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I suppose we aren’t.

 

SOCRATES: And, by the dog,47 we have certainly been unwittingly repurifying[5] the city we described as luxurious a while ago.

 

GLAUCON: That just shows how temperate we are.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s complete the purification. Now, the next topic after harmonies is the discussion of rhythms. We should not chase after complexity or multifariousness in the basic elements.48 On the contrary, we should [10] try to discover the rhythms of a life that is ordered and courageous, and then adapt the metrical foot and the melody to the speech characteristic of [400a] it, not the speech to them. What rhythms these would be is for you to say, just as you did in the case of the harmonies.

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I cannot tell you that. However, I can tell you from observation that there are three kinds of metrical feet49 out of which [5] the others are constructed, just as there are four, in the case of voices, from which come all the harmonies.50 But I cannot tell you which sort imitates which sort of life.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, we will also have to consult with Damon, on this [b] point, and ask him which metrical feet suit illiberality, arrogance, madness, and the other vices, and which their opposites. I think I have heard him using the unclear terms “warlike,” “complex,” “fingerlike,”51 and “heroic” [5] to describe one foot, which he arranged, I do not know how, to be equal up and down in the interchange of long and short.52 And I think he called one foot an iamb and another a trochee, and assigned long and short quantities to them. In the case of some of these, I think he approved or disapproved [c] of the tempo of the foot as much as of the rhythm itself, or of some combination of the two—I cannot tell you which. But, as I said, we will leave these things to Damon, since to decide them would take a long discussion. Or do you think we should try it? [5]

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: But you are able to decide this, at least, aren’t you: that grace goes along with good rhythm and lack of grace with bad rhythm?

 

GLAUCON: Of course. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, good rhythm goes along with fine speaking and [d] is similar to it, while bad rhythm goes along with the opposite sort, and the same goes for harmony and disharmony; since, as we said just now, rhythm and harmony must conform to speech, and not vice versa.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they certainly must conform to speech. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And what about the style of speaking and what is said? Don’t they go along with the character of the speaker’s soul?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t all the rest go along with the style of speaking?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Fine speech, then, as well as harmony, grace, and rhythm, go along with naiveté. I do not mean the stupidity for which naiveté53 is a [e] euphemism, but the quality a mind has when it is equipped with a truly good and fine character.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t our young people try to achieve these on every occasion, if they are going to do the job that is really theirs? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they must indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Now, surely painting and all the crafts similar to it are full of [401a] these qualities—weaving is full of them, as are embroidery, architecture, and likewise the manufacture of implements generally; and so, furthermore, is the nature of bodies and that of the other things that grow. For in all [5] these there is grace or the lack of it. And lack of grace, bad rhythm, and disharmony are akin to bad speech and bad character, while their opposites are akin to and imitate their opposite—a character that is temperate and good.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

[b] SOCRATES: Is it only poets we have to supervise, then, compelling them either to embody the image of a good character in their poems or else not to practice their craft among us? Or mustn’t we also supervise all the other craftsmen, and forbid them to represent a character that is bad, intemperate, [5] illiberal, and graceless, in their images of living beings, in their buildings, or in any of the other products of their craft? And mustn’t the one who finds this impossible be prevented from practicing in our city, so that our guardians [c] will not be brought up on images of evil as in a meadow of bad grass, where they crop and graze every day from all that surrounds them until, little by little, they unwittingly accumulate a great evil in their souls? Instead, mustn’t we look for craftsmen who are naturally capable of [5] pursuing what is fine and graceful in their work, so that our young people will live in a healthy place and be benefited on all sides as the influence exerted by those fine works affects their eyes and ears like a healthy breeze from wholesome regions, and imperceptibly guides them from earliest [d] childhood into being similar to, friendly toward, and concordant with the beauty of reason?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that would be by far the best education for them.

 

SOCRATES: Then aren’t these the reasons, Glaucon, that musical training is [5] most important? First, because rhythm and harmony permeate the innermost element of the soul, affect it more powerfully than anything else, and bring it grace, such education makes one graceful if one is properly trained, [e] and the opposite if one is not. Second, because anyone who has been properly trained will quickly notice if something has been omitted from a thing, or if that thing has not been well crafted or well grown. And so, since he feels distaste correctly, he will praise fine things, be pleased by them, take [5] them into his soul, and, through being nourished by them, become fine [402a] and good. What is ugly or shameful, on the other hand, he will correctly condemn and hate while he is still young, before he is able to grasp the reason. And, because he has been so trained, he will welcome the reason when it comes and recognize it easily because of its kinship with himself.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, it seems to me that these are the goals of musical training.

 

SOCRATES: It is like learning to read, then. We became adequately proficient only when the few letters that there are did not escape us in any of the different words in which they are scattered about; and when we did not disregard them, either in a small word or a great one, as if they were not worth noticing; but tried hard to distinguish them wherever they occur, knowing [b] that we would not be competent readers until we knew our letters.

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t it also true that if there are images of letters reflected in water or mirrors, we won’t know them until we know the letters themselves, [5] for both abilities are parts of the same craft and discipline?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then, by the gods, aren’t I right in saying that neither we nor the guardians we claim to be educating will be musically trained until [c] we know the different forms of temperance, courage, generosity, high-mindedness, and all their kindred, and their opposites, too, which are carried around everywhere; and see them in the things in which they are, [5] both themselves and their images; and do not disregard them, either in small things or in great, but accept that the knowledge of both belongs to the same craft and discipline?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that necessarily follows.

 

SOCRATES: Then, if the fine habits in someone’s soul and those in his [d] physical form agree and are in concord with one another, so that both share the same pattern, wouldn’t that be the most beautiful sight for anyone capable of seeing it?

 

GLAUCON: By far. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And surely the most beautiful is also the most loveable, isn’t it?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: A really musical person, then, would passionately love people who are most like that. But a disharmonious person, he would not passionately love.

 

GLAUCON: No, he would not—at least, not if the defect were in the soul. If it were only in the body, however, he would put up with it and still be [10] willing to embrace the boy who had it. [e]

 

SOCRATES: I understand that you love or have loved such a boy yourself, and I agree with you. But tell me this: does excessive pleasure share anything in common with temperance?

 

GLAUCON: How can it? It surely drives one no less mad than pain does. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What about with any other virtue?

 

[403a] GLAUCON: Never.

 

SOCRATES: Then, what about with arrogance and intemperance?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, with them most of all.

 

SOCRATES: Can you think of any pleasure that is greater or keener than [5] sexual pleasure?

 

GLAUCON: No, I cannot—or of a more insane one either.

 

SOCRATES: But isn’t the right sort of passion a naturally moderate and musically educated passion for order and beauty?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Then nothing insane and nothing akin to dissoluteness can be involved in the right love?

 

GLAUCON: No, they cannot.

 

[b] SOCRATES: Then sexual pleasure must not be involved, must it, and the lover and the boy who passionately love and are loved in the right way must have no share in it?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, Socrates, it must not be involved.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that you will lay it down as a law in the city we are founding that a lover—if he can persuade his boyfriend to let him—[5] may kiss him, be with him, and touch him, as a father would a son, for the sake of beautiful things. But in all other respects, his association with the [c] one he cares about must never seem to go any further than this. Otherwise, he will be reproached as untrained in music, and as lacking in appreciation for beautiful things.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Do you agree, then, that our account of musical training has [5] come to an end? At any rate, it ought to end where it has ended; for surely training in the musical crafts ought to end in a passion for beauty.

 

GLAUCON: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: Now, after musical training, our young people must be given physical training.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And in this, too, they must have a careful training, which starts in childhood and continues throughout life. It would, I believe, be something [d] like this—but you should consider what you think, too. You see, I, for my part, do not believe that a healthy body, by means of its own virtue, makes the soul good. On the contrary, I believe that the opposite is true: a good soul, by means of its own virtue, makes the body as good as possible. [5] What do you think?

 

GLAUCON: I think so, too.

 

SOCRATES: Then if we give adequate care to the mind, entrust it with the detailed supervision of the body, and content ourselves with indicating the general patterns to be followed rather than going on at great length, wouldn’t we be proceeding in the right way? [e]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Now, we said that our prospective guardians must avoid drunkenness.54 For surely a guardian is the last person who should get so drunk that he does not know where on earth he is. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it would be ridiculous for a guardian to need a guardian himself!

 

SOCRATES: What about food? These men are athletes in the greatest contest, aren’t they?

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Then would the regimen of ordinary, trained athletes be suitable for them? [404a]

 

GLAUCON: Maybe.

 

SOCRATES: But it seems to be a soporific sort of regimen and unreliable as regards health. Or haven’t you noticed that these athletes sleep their lives away, and that if they deviate even a little from their orderly regimen, they [5] become seriously and violently ill?

 

GLAUCON: I have noticed that.

 

SOCRATES: Then we need a more refined sort of training for our warrior-athletes, since they must be like sleepless hounds, as it were, who have the [10] keenest possible sight and hearing, and whose health is not so precarious that it cannot sustain the frequent changes of water and diet generally, and the heat waves and winter storms typical of war. [b]

 

GLAUCON: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t the best physical training, then, be akin to the simple musical training we described a moment ago? [5]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: I mean a simple and good physical training, and one that is especially adapted to the conditions of war.

 

GLAUCON: In what way?

 

SOCRATES: You could learn that even from Homer. For you know that when his heroes are at war, he does not portray them banqueting on [c] fish55—even though they are by the sea in the Hellespont—or boiled meat, but roasted meat only, which is the sort most easily available to soldiers. For it is pretty much always easier to use an open fire than to carry pots and pans around everywhere.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Quite right.

 

SOCRATES: Nor, I believe, does Homer mention rich sauces anywhere. In fact, isn’t everyone else who is in training also aware that if he is planning to stay in good physical condition, he must avoid such things altogether?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, and they are certainly right to be aware of it and to avoid them.

 

SOCRATES: If you think they are right to do that, my dear Glaucon, you [d] apparently do not approve of Syracusan cuisine or complex Sicilian relishes.

 

GLAUCON: I suppose not.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Then you also object to men having a Corinthian girlfriend, if they are planning to be in good physical condition.56

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And also to their enjoying the reputed delights of Attic pastries?

 

[10] GLAUCON: I would have to.

 

SOCRATES: And the reason for that, I take it, is that we would be right to compare this sort of diet, and this lifestyle, to the polyharmonic songs and [e] lyric odes that make use of every sort of rhythm.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: There complexity engendered intemperance, didn’t it, and here it engenders illness; whereas simplicity in musical training engenders [5] temperance in the soul, and in physical training health in the body?

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

[405a] SOCRATES: And as intemperance and disease breed in a city, aren’t many law courts and surgeries opened? And don’t the legal and medical professions give themselves airs when even free men in large numbers take them very seriously?

 

[5] GLAUCON: How could it be otherwise?

 

SOCRATES: Could you find better evidence that a city’s education is in a bad and shameful state than when eminent doctors and lawyers are needed, not only by inferior people and handicraftsmen, but by those who claim to have been brought up in the manner of free men? Indeed, don’t you think it is shameful and strong evidence of lack of education to be forced to make [b] use of a justice imposed by others, as if they were one’s masters and judges, because one lacks such qualities oneself?

 

GLAUCON: That is the most shameful thing of all. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Do you really think so? Isn’t it even more shameful not just to spend a good part of one’s life in court defending oneself and prosecuting someone else, but to be so vulgar that one is persuaded to take pride in this and regard oneself as amazingly clever at doing injustice, and as so accomplished at every trick and turn that one can wiggle through any loophole, [c] and avoid punishment—and to do all that for the sake of little worthless things, and because one is ignorant of how much better and finer it is to arrange one’s own life so that one won’t need to find a judge57 who is asleep? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that is even more shameful.

 

SOCRATES: What about needing the craft of medicine for something besides wounds or some seasonal illnesses? What about needing it because idleness and the regimen we described has filled one full of gasses and [d] phlegm, like a stagnant swamp, so that sophisticated Asclepiad doctors are forced to come up with names like “flatulence” and “catarrh” to describe one’s diseases? Don’t you think that is shameful?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is; and those truly are strange new names for diseases. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And of a sort that I do not imagine even existed in the time of Asclepius himself. My evidence for this is that his sons at Troy did not criticize [e] the woman who treated the wounded Eurypylus with Pramneian wine that had lots of barley meal and grated cheese sprinkled on it, even though such treatment is now thought to cause inflammation. Moreover, [406a] they did not criticize Patroclus, who prescribed the treatment.58

 

GLAUCON: Yet, surely it was a strange drink for someone in that condition.

 

SOCRATES: Not if you recall that the sort of modern medicine that coddles the disease was not used by the Asclepiads before the time of Herodicus. [5] Herodicus was a physical trainer who became ill and, through a combination of physical training and medicine, tormented first and foremost himself, and then lots of other people as well. b

 

GLAUCON: How did he do that?

 

SOCRATES: By making his death a lengthy process. You see, although he was always tending his illness, he was not able to cure it, since it was terminal. [5] And so he spent his life under medical treatment, with no free time for anything else whatsoever. He suffered torments if he departed even a little from his accustomed regimen; but, thanks to his wisdom, he struggled against death and reached old age.

 

GLAUCON: A fine reward for his craft that was!

 

SOCRATES: And appropriate for someone who did not know that it was [c] not because of ignorance or inexperience of this kind of medicine that Asclepius failed to teach it to his sons, but because he knew that everyone in a well-regulated city has his own work to do, and that no one has the [5] time to be ill and under treatment all his life. We see how ridiculous this would be in the case of craftsmen, but we do not see it in the case of those who are supposedly happy—the rich.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: When a carpenter is ill, he expects to get a drug from his doctor [d] that will make him throw up what is making him sick or evacuate it through his bowels; or to get rid of his disease through surgery or cautery. If anyone prescribes a lengthy regimen for him and tells him that he should rest with his head bandaged and so on, he quickly replies that he has no [5] time to be ill, and that it is not profitable for him to live like that, always [e] minding his illness and neglecting the work at hand. After that, he says goodbye to his doctor, resumes his usual regimen, lives doing his own job, and recovers his health; alternatively, if his body cannot withstand the illness, he dies and escapes his troubles.

 

GLAUCON: That does seem to be the correct way for someone like that to [5] use the craft of medicine.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t that because he had a job to do, and that if he could not [407a] do it, it would not profit him to go on living?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: But a rich person, it is said, has no job assigned to him of the [5] sort that would make his life not worth living if he had to keep away from it.

 

GLAUCON: So it is said, at least.

 

SOCRATES: What, have you not heard the saying of Phocylides that once one has the means of life, one must practice virtue?59

 

GLAUCON: And even earlier, in my view.

 

[10] SOCRATES : Let’s not quarrel with him about that. But let’s try to find out for ourselves whether this virtue is something a rich person must practice, and if his life is not worth living if he does not practice it; or whether nursing an illness, while an obstacle to putting your mind to carpentry and [b] other crafts, is no obstacle whatever to taking Phocylides’ advice.

 

GLAUCON: But, by Zeus, it is: excessive care of the body that goes beyond simple physical training is more of an obstacle than pretty much anything. For it’s a [5] nuisance in household management, in military service, and even in sedentary political office.

 

SOCRATES: And the greatest of all, surely, is that it makes any sort of learning, thought, or private meditation difficult, by forever causing imaginary [c] headaches or dizziness and accusing philosophy of causing them. Hence, wherever this sort of virtue is practiced and submitted to philosophical scrutiny, excessive care of the body hinders it. For it is constantly making you imagine that you are ill and never lets you stop agonizing about your body. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, probably so.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t we say that Asclepius knew this, too, and that he invented the craft of medicine for people whose bodies are healthy in nature and habit, but have some specific disease in them? That is the type of [d] person and condition for which he invented it. He rid them of their disease by means of drugs or surgery, and then prescribed their normal regimen, so that affairs of politics would not be harmed. However, he did not attempt to prescribe regimens for those whose bodies were riddled with disease, so [5] that by drawing off a little here and pouring in a little there, he could make their life a prolonged misery and enable them to produce offspring in all probability like themselves. He did not think that he should treat someone who could not live a normal life, since such a person would profit neither himself nor his city. [e]

 

GLAUCON: Asclepius was a true man of politics, in your view.

 

SOCRATES: Clearly so. And it was because he was like that, don’t you see, that his sons, too, turned out to be good men in the war at Troy, and practiced [408a] the craft of medicine as I say they did. Don’t you remember that they “sucked out the blood and applied gentle drugs” to the wound Pandarus inflicted on Menelaus? But they no more prescribed what he should eat or [5] drink after that than they did for Eurypylus?60 That was because they assumed that their drugs were sufficient to cure men who were healthy and living an orderly life before being wounded, even if they happened to drink wine mixed with barley and cheese right afterward. But they thought that [b] the lives of naturally sick and intemperate people were profitable neither to themselves nor to anyone else, that the craft of medicine shouldn’t be practiced on them, and that they should not be given treatment, not even if they were richer than Midas. [5]

 

GLAUCON: The sons of Asclepius were indeed very sophisticated, in your view.

 

SOCRATES: It is the right view to hold of them. And yet it is on just this point that Pindar and the tragedians are not persuaded by us. They say that Asclepius, even though he was the son of Apollo, was bribed with gold to heal a rich man who was already dying, and that that is why he was struck [c] by lightning. But, in view of what we said before, we won’t accept both claims from them. On the contrary, we will say that if Asclepius was the son of a god, he was not a money-grubber; and that if he was a moneygrubber, he was not the son of a god.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right. But what do you say about the following, [5] Socrates? Won’t we need to have good doctors in our city? And the best, I take it, will be those who have treated the greatest number of healthy [d] and diseased people. In the same way, the best judges 61 will be those who have associated with people with multifarious natures.

 

SOCRATES: I certainly agree that we need good ones. But do you know [5] which ones I regard as such?

 

GLAUCON: I will, if you will tell me.

 

SOCRATES: Well, I will try. However, you ask about things that are not alike in the same question.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: Doctors, it is true, would become cleverest if, in addition to learning the craft of medicine, they associated with the greatest possible [10] number of the most diseased bodies right from childhood,62 had themselves [e] experienced every illness, and were not, by nature, very healthy. After all, they do not treat a body with a body. If they did, we would not allow their bodies to be or become bad. But it is with a soul that a body is treated, and it [5] is not possible for a soul to treat anything well if it is or has become bad itself.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: But a judge, my friend, does rule a soul with a soul. And it is [409a] not possible for a soul to be nurtured among bad souls from childhood, to have associated with them, and to have itself indulged in every sort of injustice, so as to be able to draw exact inferences from itself about the injustices of others, as in the case of diseases of the body. On the contrary, it itself the craft of medicine, they associated withmust have no experience of, and be uncontaminated by, bad characters while it is young, if as a fine and good soul itself, it is going to make judgments about what is just in a healthy way. That is precisely the reason, indeed, that good people are thought to be naïve when they are young and easily deceived by unjust ones: they do not have models within themselves [b] of the behavior of bad ones.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed, that is precisely what happens to them.

 

SOCRATES: That is why a good judge must not be young, but old—a late learner of what sort of thing injustice is, who has become aware of it, not as [5] something at home in his own soul, but as an alien thing present in other people’s souls. He must have trained himself over many years to discern how naturally bad it is by using his theoretical knowledge, not his own intimate experience of it. [c]

 

GLAUCON: At any rate, it would seem that the noblest judge would be like that.

 

SOCRATES: And so is the good one you asked about, since the one who has a good soul is good. The clever and suspicious person, on the other hand, who has committed many injustices himself and thinks of himself to be unscrupulous and wise, appears clever when he associates with those like [5] himself, because he is on his guard and looks to the models within himself. But when he meets with good people who are older, he is seen to be stupid, distrustful at the wrong time, and ignorant of what a healthy character is, since he has no model of this within himself. But because he meets bad [d] people more often than good ones, he seems more wise than foolish, both to himself and to them as well.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true. [5]

 

SOCRATES : Then we must not look for a good judge among people like that, but among the sort we described earlier. For while a bad person could never come to know either vice or virtue, a naturally virtuous person, when educated, will in time acquire knowledge of both virtue and vice. And it is someone like that, and not a bad person, who becomes a wise judge in my view. [e]

 

GLAUCON: And I share your view.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t you establish by law in your city both the craft of medicine we mentioned and this craft of judging along with it? And these crafts will care for such of your citizens as have naturally good bodies and [5] souls; but those whose bodies are not like that they will allow to die, while [410a] those whose souls are naturally and incurably bad they will themselves put to death.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we have seen that that is best both for those who receive such treatment and for the city. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And so it is clear that your young people will be wary of coming to need a judge, since they employ that simple sort of musical training, which we said engenders temperance.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t a person who is musically trained hunt for a type of [b] physical training by following these same tracks, and catch it, if he chooses? And won’t the result be that he will have no need of the craft of medicine, except when absolutely necessary?

 

GLAUCON: That’s my view, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: And he will undertake even the regimens and exertions of [5] physical training with an eye less to strength than to arousing the spirited part of his nature, unlike all other athletes who use diets and exertions only to gain muscle power.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Then, doesn’t it follow, Glaucon, that those who established musical training and physical training did not establish them with the aim [c] that some people attribute to them: namely, to treat the body with the former and the soul with the latter?

 

GLAUCON: What was it then?

 

[5] SOCRATES: It looks as though they established both chiefly for the sake of the soul.

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: Have you never noticed the mind-set of those who have a lifelong association with physical training but stay away from musical training? [10] Or, again, that of those who do the opposite?

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

[d] SOCRATES: Savagery and toughness, in the one case; softness and over-cultivation, in the other.

 

GLAUCON: I have certainly noticed that people who devote themselves exclusively to physical training turn out to be more savage than they should, while those who devote themselves to musical training turn out to [5] be softer than is good for them.

 

SOCRATES: And surely the savageness derives from the spirited element of their nature, which, if rightly nurtured, becomes courageous, but, if overstrained, is likely to become hard and harsh.

 

[10] GLAUCON: So it seems.

 

SOCRATES: What about the cultivation? Wouldn’t it derive from the philosophic [e] element of their nature, which, if relaxed too much, becomes softer than it should, but, if well nurtured, is cultivated and orderly?

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Now, we said that our guardians must have both these [5] natures.63

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they must.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t the two be harmonized with one another?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t the soul of the person thus harmonized temperate [10] and courageous? [411a]

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And that of the inharmonious person, cowardly and savage?

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: So when someone gives himself over to musical training and lets the flute pour into his soul through his ears, as through a funnel, those [5] sweet, soft, and plaintive harmonies we mentioned; and when he spends his whole life humming, entranced by song, the first result is that whatever spirit he had, he softens the way he would iron and makes useful, rather than useless and brittle. But when he keeps at it unrelentingly and charms [b] his spirit, the next result is that he melts it and dissolves it completely until he has cut out, so to speak, the very sinews of his soul and makes himself “a feeble warrior.”64

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And if he has a spiritless nature to begin with, this happens quickly. But if he has a spirited one, his spirit becomes weak and unstable, quickly inflamed by trivial things and quickly extinguished. As a result, people like that become quick-tempered and prone to anger, instead of [c] spirited, and filled with peevishness.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, what about someone who works hard at physical training, eats very well, and never touches musical training or philosophy? At first, because his body is in good strong condition, isn’t he full [5] of pride and spirit, and more courageous than he was before?

 

GLAUCON: He certainly is.

 

SOCRATES: But what happens if he does nothing but this and never enters into partnership with a Muse? Even if there was some love of learning in his soul, because it never tastes any sort of instruction or investigation, and [d] never participates in any discussion or in any of the rest of musical training, doesn’t it become weak, deaf, and blind, because it never receives any stimulation [5] or nourishment, and its senses are never purified?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it does.

 

SOCRATES: Then a person like that, I take it, becomes an unmusical hater of argument65 who no longer uses argument to persuade people, but force [e] and savagery, behaves like a wild beast, and lives in awkward ignorance without rhythm or grace.

 

GLAUCON: That’s exactly how it is.

 

SOCRATES: So I, for one, would claim that it is to deal with these two things, so it seems, that a god has given two crafts to human beings—musical [5] training and physical training—to deal with the philosophical and spirited elements, and not, except as a byproduct, with the soul and the body; but with these two, so that they might be harmonized with one another by [412a] being stretched and relaxed to the appropriate degree.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it seems so.

 

SOCRATES: Then it is the person who makes the best blend of musical and physical training, and applies them in the most perfect proportion to his [5] soul, that we would be most correct to describe as completely trained in music and as most in harmony—far more so than the one who merely attunes his strings to one another.

 

GLAUCON: Probably so, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t we also need this sort of person in our city, Glaucon, [10] as a permanent overseer, if indeed its constitution is to be preserved?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Yes, we will need him most of all.

 

SOCRATES: Those, then, would be the patterns of their education and upbringing. For why should we enumerate their dances, hunts, chases with hounds, athletic contests, and horse races? After all, it is pretty much clear [5] that they should be consistent with these patterns, and so there should no longer be any difficulty in discovering them.

 

GLAUCON: No, presumably there should not.

 

SOCRATES: All right. Now, what is the next question we have to settle? Isn’t it which of these same people will rule and which be ruled?

 

[c] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Well, isn’t it clear that the older ones must rule, whereas the younger ones must be ruled?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is clear.

 

SOCRATES: And that the rulers must be the best among them? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s clear, too.

 

SOCRATES: And aren’t the best farmers the ones who are best at farming?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: In the present case, then, since the rulers must be the best of the guardians, mustn’t they be the ones who are best at guarding the city? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then mustn’t they be knowledgeable and capable in this matter, and, in addition, mustn’t they care for the city?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they must. [d]

 

SOCRATES: But a person would care most for what he loved.

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: And he would love something most if he thought that the same things were advantageous both for it and for himself, and if he thought that when it did well, he would do well, too; and that if it didn’t, [5] the opposite would happen.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Then we must choose from among our guardians the sort of men who seem on the basis of our observation to be most inclined, throughout their entire lives, to do what they believe to be advantageous for the city, and most unwilling to do the opposite. [e]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they would be suitable for the job.

 

SOCRATES: I think, then, that we will have to observe them at every stage of their lives to make sure that they are good guardians of this conviction, [5] and that neither compulsion nor sorcery will cause them to discard or forget their belief that they must do what is best for the city.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean by discarding?

 

SOCRATES: I will tell you. It seems to me that the departure of a belief from someone’s mind is either voluntary or involuntary—voluntary when [10] he learns that the belief is false; involuntary in the case of all true beliefs. [413a]

 

GLAUCON: I understand the voluntary sort, but I still need instruction about the involuntary.

 

SOCRATES: What? Don’t you know that people are involuntarily deprived of good things, but voluntarily deprived of bad ones? And isn’t being [5] deceived about the truth a bad thing, whereas possessing the truth is a good one? Or don’t you think that to believe things that are is to possess the truth?

 

GLAUCON: No, you are right. And I do think that people are involuntarily [10] deprived of true beliefs.

 

SOCRATES: Then isn’t it through theft, sorcery, and compulsion that this [b] happens?

 

GLAUCON: Now I do not understand again.

 

SOCRATES: I suppose I am making myself as clear as a tragic poet!66 By those who have their beliefs stolen from them, I mean those who are over-persuaded, [5] or those who forget; because argument, in the one case, and time, in the other, takes away their beliefs without their noticing. You understand now, don’t you?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Well then, by those who are compelled, I mean those who are [10] made to change their beliefs by some suffering or pain.

 

GLAUCON: I understand that, too, and you are right.

 

[c] SOCRATES: And the victims of sorcery, I think you would agree, are those who change their beliefs because they are charmed by pleasure or terrified by some fear.

 

GLAUCON: It seems to me that all deception is a form of sorcery.

 

SOCRATES: Well then, as I was just saying, we must discover which of [5] them are best at safeguarding within themselves the conviction that they must always do what they believe to be best for the city. We must watch them right from childhood, and set them tasks in which a person would be most likely to forget such a conviction or be deceived out of it. And we [d] must select the ones who remember and are difficult to deceive, and reject the others. Do you agree?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And we must also subject them to labors, pains, and contests, [5] and watch for the same things there.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Then we must also set up a third kind of competition for sorcery. Like those who lead colts into noise and tumult to see if they are afraid, we must subject our young people to fears and then plunge them [10] once again into pleasures, so as to test them much more thoroughly than [e] people test gold in a fire. And if any of them seems to be immune to sorcery, preserves his composure throughout, is a good guardian of himself and of the musical training he has received, and proves himself to be rhythmical and harmonious in all these trials—he is the sort of person who would be most useful, both to himself and to the city. And anyone who is tested as a [5] child, youth, and adult, and always emerges as being without impurities, should be established as a ruler of the city as well as a guardian, and should [414a] be honored in life and receive the most prized tombs and memorials after his death. But those who do not should be rejected. That is the sort of way, Glaucon, that I think rulers and guardians should be selected and established. [5] Though I have provided only a pattern, not the precise details.

 

GLAUCON: I also think much the same.

 

SOCRATES: Then wouldn’t it really be most correct to call these people [b] complete guardians—the ones who guard against external enemies and internal friends, so that the former will lack the power, and the latter the desire, to do any evil; but to call the young people to whom we were referring as guardians just now, auxiliaries and supporters of the guardians’ convictions? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I think it would.

 

SOCRATES: How, then, could we devise one of those useful lies we were talking about a while ago,67 a single noble lie that would, preferably, persuade [c] even the rulers themselves; but, failing that, the rest of the city?

 

GLAUCON: What sort of lie?

 

SOCRATES: Nothing new, but a sort of Phoenician story68 about something that happened in lots of places prior to this—at least, that is what the poets say and have persuaded people to believe. It has not happened in our [5] day, and I do not know if it could happen. It would take a lot of persuasion to get people to believe it.

 

GLAUCON: You seem hesitant to tell the story.

 

SOCRATES: You will realize that I have every reason to hesitate, when I do tell it.

 

GLAUCON: Out with it. Do not be afraid.

 

SOCRATES: All right, I will—though I do not know where I will get the audacity or the words to tell it. I will first be trying to persuade the rulers [d] and the soldiers, and then the rest of the city, that the upbringing and the education we gave them were like dreams; that they only imagined they were undergoing all the things that were happening to them, while in fact [5] they themselves were at that time down inside the earth being formed and nurtured, and that their weapons and the rest of their equipment were also [e] manufactured there. When they were entirely completed, the earth, their mother, sent them up, so that now, just as if the land in which they live were their mother and nurse, they must deliberate on its behalf, defend it if [5] anyone attacks it, and regard the other citizens as their earthborn brothers.

 

GLAUCON: It is not for nothing that you were ashamed to tell your lie earlier.

 

SOCRATES: No, it was only to be expected. But all the same, you should [415a] listen to the rest of the story. “Although all of you in the city are brothers,” we will say to them in telling our story, “when the god was forming you, he mixed gold into those of you who are capable of ruling, which is why [5] they are the most honorable; silver into the auxiliaries; and iron and bronze into the farmers and other craftsmen. For the most part, you will produce children like yourselves; but, because you are all related, a silver [b] child will occasionally be born to a golden parent, a golden child to a silver parent, and so on. Therefore, the first and most important command from the god to the rulers is that there is nothing they must guard better or [5] watch more carefully than the mixture of metals in the souls of their offspring. If an offspring of theirs is born with a mixture of iron or bronze, they must not pity him in any way, but assign him an honor appropriate to [c] his nature and drive him out to join the craftsmen or the farmers. On the other hand, if an offspring of the latter is found to have a mixture of gold or silver, they will honor him and take him up to join the guardians or the [5] auxiliaries. For there is an oracle that the city will be ruined if it ever has an iron or a bronze guardian.” So, have you a device that will make them believe this story?

 

GLAUCON: No, none that would make this group believe it themselves.[d] But I do have one for their sons, for later generations, and for all other people who come after them.

 

SOCRATES: Well, even that would have a good effect, by making them care more for the city and for each other. For I think I understand what [5] you mean—namely, that all this will go where tradition leads. What we can do, however, when we have armed our earthborn people, is lead them forth with their rulers at their head. They must go and look for the best place in the city for a military encampment, a site from which they can [e] most easily control anyone in the city who is unwilling to obey the laws, or repel any outside enemy who, like a wolf, attacks the fold. And when they have established their camp and sacrificed to the appropriate gods, they must make their sleeping quarters, mustn’t they?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t these provide adequate shelter against the storms of winter and the heat of summer?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, of course. After all, I assume you are talking about their living quarters.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, but ones for soldiers, not moneymakers.

 

GLAUCON: What difference do you think there is between the two, again? [416a]

 

SOCRATES: I will try to tell you. You see, it is surely the most terrible and most shameful thing in the world for shepherds to rear dogs as auxiliaries to help them with their flocks in such a way that those dogs themselves—because of intemperance, hunger, or some other bad condition—try to do [5] evil to the sheep, acting not like sheepdogs but like wolves.

 

GLAUCON: Of course, that is terrible.

 

SOCRATES: So, mustn’t we use every safeguard to prevent our auxiliaries [b] from treating the citizens like that—because they are stronger—and becoming savage masters rather than gentle allies?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we must.

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t they have been provided with the greatest safeguard possible if they have been really well educated? [5]

 

GLAUCON: But surely they have been.

 

SOCRATES: That is not something that deserves to be asserted so confidently, my dear Glaucon. But what does deserve it is what we were saying just now, that they must have the right education, whatever it is, if they are going to have what will do most to make them gentle to one another and [c] the ones they are guarding.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: But anyone with any sense will tell us that, besides this education, they must be provided with living quarters and other property of the [5] sort that will neither prevent them from being the best guardians nor encourage them to do evil to the other citizens. [d]

 

GLAUCON: And he would be right.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, then, whether or not they should live and be housed in some such way as this, if they are going to be the sort of men we described. First, none of them should possess any private property that is not wholly necessary. Second, none should have living quarters or storerooms [5] that are not open for all to enter at will. Such provisions as are required by temperate and courageous men, who are warrior-athletes, they should receive from the other citizens as a salary for their guardianship, the [e] amount being fixed so that there is neither a shortfall nor a surplus at the end of the year. They should have common messes to go to, and should live together like soldiers in a camp. We will tell them that they have gold and [5] silver of a divine sort in their souls as a permanent gift from the gods, and have no need of human gold in addition. And we will add that it is impious for them to defile this divine possession by possessing an admixture of mortal gold, because many impious deeds have been done for the sake of the [417a] currency of the masses, whereas their sort is pure. No, they alone among the city’s population are forbidden by divine law to handle or even touch gold and silver. They must not be under the same roof as these metals, wear them as jewelry, or drink from gold or silver goblets. And by behaving in [5] that way, they would save both themselves and the city. But if they acquire private land, houses, and money themselves, they will be household managers and farmers instead of guardians—hostile masters of the other citizens, [b] instead of their allies. They will spend their whole lives hating and being hated, plotting and being plotted against, much more afraid of internal than of external enemies—already rushing, in fact, to the brink of their [5] own destruction and that of the rest of the city as well. For all these reasons, let’s declare that that is how the guardians must be provided with housing and the rest, and establish it as a law. Or don’t you agree?

 

GLAUCON: Of course I do.

 

1 Odyssey 11.489–91. Odysseus is being addressed by Achilles in Hades.

2 Iliad 20.64–5. Hades is afraid that the earth will split open and reveal what his home is like.

3 Iliad 23.103–4. Achilles speaks these lines as the soul of the dead Patroclus leaves for Hades.

4 Odyssey 10.493–5. Circe speaking to Odysseus about the prophet Tiresias.

5 Iliad 16.856–7. The words refer to Patroclus, who has just been mortally wounded by Hector.

6 Iliad 23.100. The soul referred to is that of Patroclus.

7 Odyssey 14.6–9. The souls are those of Penelope’s suitors, whom Odysseus has killed.

8 “Cocytus” means river of wailing or lamenting; “Styx,” river of hatred.

9 Iliad 24.3–12.

10 Iliad 18.23–4.

11 Iliad 22.414–5.

12 Iliad 18.54. Thetis, the mother of Achilles, is mourning his fate among the Nereids.

13 Iliad 22.168–9. Zeus is watching Hector being pursued by Achilles.

14 Iliad 16.433–4.

15 Iliad 1.599–600.

16Odyssey 17.384.

17 Sôphrosunê.

18 Iliad 4.412. Agamemnon has unfairly rebuked Diomedes for cowardice.

Diomedes’ squire protests, but Diomedes quiets him with these words. By obeying, the squire exhibits the kind of moderation that most people can come to possess.

19 A mix of Iliad 3.8 and 4.431.

20 Iliad 1.225. Achilles is insulting his commander, Agamemnon.

21 Odyssey 9.8–10.

22 Odyssey 12.342. Eurylochus urges the men to slay the cattle of Helios in Odysseus’ absence.

23 Iliad 14.294–341.

24Odyssey 8.266ff.

25 Odyssey 20.17–8. The speaker is Odysseus.

26 The source of the passage is unknown. Cf. Euripides, Medea 964.

27 Iliad 9.602–3.

28 Iliad 19.278ff., 24.594.

29 Iliad 22.15, 20.

30 Iliad 21.232ff.

31 Iliad 23.151–2.

32Iliad 14.14–8.

33 Iliad 23.175.

34 According to some legends, Theseus and Peirithous abducted Helen and tried to abduct Persephone from Hades.

35 See 380b8–"d7e25682-109"383c7.

36 Thought to be from Aeschylus’ lost play Niobe.

37 Apollo.

38 Iliad 1.15ff.

39 Apollo as at 393a1 and 394a3.

40 See Glossary of Terms s.v. dithyramb.

41 Metabolê: variation in general, but also a technical term in music for the transition from one harmony to another.

42 As was traditionally done to statues of the gods.

43 387d–388e.

44 Phthongos, prosôdia: phthongos is a human voice, an animal cry, or more generally a sound of some sort; prosôdia is the tone or accent of a syllable, or a song accompanied by music.

45 See Glossary of Terms s.v. flute. It is characterized as multi-stringed because of the number of different notes it is capable of producing.

46 After Athena had invented the flute, she discarded it because playing it distorted her features. It was picked up by the satyr Marsyas, who was foolish enough to challenge Apollo (inventor of the lyre) to a musical contest. He was defeated, and Apollo flayed him alive. Satyrs were bestial in their behavior and desires—especially their sexual desires.

47 Nê ton kuna: probably the dog-headed Egyptian god Anubis, as at Gorgias 428b5.

48 Rhythm is poetic meter, and the elements are the metrical feet.

49 Probably those in which the foot is divided in the ratio of: (1) 2:2—e.g., the dactyl Il_9781603842761_0117_001or the spondee Il_9781603842761_0117_001 (2) 3:2—e.g., the paeon Il_9781603842761_0117_002(3) 1:2 or 2:1—e.g., the iamb Il_9781603842761_0117_002 or the trochee Il_9781603842761_0117_001.

50 The precise reference is unclear.

51 Reading 1234 with Jackson and Waterfield.

52 The foot being described is probably the dactyl Il_9781603842761_0117_001: it is warlike and heroic, because Greek heroic poetry was written in dactylic hexameter; complex, because it consists of a long syllable and two short ones; equal up and down in the interchange of long and short, because a long syllable is equal in length to two short ones; and fingerlike, because the first joint on a finger is roughly equal in length to the other two.

53 See 348c12 note.

54 398e6.

55 Fish was a luxury item in Plato’s Athens. See James Davidson, Courtesans and Fishcakes: The Consuming Passions of Classical Athens (New York: St. Martin’s, 1998).

56 Corinthian prostitutes enjoyed an international reputation in the Classical period.

57 See Glossary of Terms s.v. judge.

58 At Iliad 11.580ff. Eurypylus is wounded, but not treated in this way (see 11.828–36).

However, Machaon, the son of Asclepius, does receive this treatment at 11.624–50.

59 Phocylides of Miletus was a mid-sixth–century elegiac and hexameter poet best known for his epigrams.

60 Iliad 4.218–9. In the extant text, Machaon is acting alone.

61 See Glossary of Terms s.v. judge.

62 See 341e4–6.

63 375c6–8.

64 Iliad 17.588.

65Misologos: the opposite of a philosopher, who is a philologos, a lover of argument.

See Laches 188c4–189b7, Phaedo 89d1–91b7.

66 Tragikôs: The participles Socrates has used at 413b1–2—klapentes (theft), goê-teuthentes(sorcery), biasthentes (compulsion)—are, like much tragic poetry, both metaphorical and grand.

67 382a4–d3.

68 Apparently a reference, first, to the legend of the Phoenician hero, Cadmus, who sowed the earth with dragon’s teeth from which giants grew; and, second, to the Odyssey, and the tales Odysseus tells to the Phaeacians.

Book 4

 

SOCRATESNARRATION CONTINUES:   Adeimantus interrupted:

How will you defend yourself, Socrates, he said, if someone objects that [419a] you are not making these men very happy and, furthermore, that it is their own fault that they are not? I mean, the city really belongs to them, yet they derive no good from the city. Others own land, build fine, big houses, [5] acquire furnishings to go along with them, make their own private sacrifices to the gods, entertain guests, and also, of course, possess what you were talking about just now: gold and silver and all the things that those who are going to be blessedly happy are thought to require. Instead of that, he might say, they seem simply to be paid auxiliaries established in the city [10] as a garrison, and nothing else. [420a]

 

SOCRATES: Yes, and what is more, they do it just for upkeep and get no wages in addition to their upkeep, as other men do. So, they won’t even be able to take a personal trip out of town if they want to, or give presents to their girlfriends, or spend money in whatever other ways they might wish, [5] as people do who are considered happy. You have omitted these and a host of other similar facts from your list of charges.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well, let them too be added to the charges.

 

SOCRATES: How will we defend ourselves? Is that what you are asking? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: I think we will discover what to say if we follow the same path as before. You see, our reply will be this: it would not be at all surprising if these people were happiest just as they are. However, in establishing our [5] city, we are not looking to make any one group in it outstandingly happy, but to make the whole city so as far as possible. For we thought that we would be most likely to find justice in such a city, and injustice, by contrast, in the one that is governed worst. And we thought that by observing both cities, we would be able to decide the question we have been inquiring into for so long. At the moment, then, we take ourselves to be forming a happy [c] city—not separating off a few happy people and putting them in it, but making the city as a whole happy. (We will look at the opposite city soon.)1

 

Suppose, then, that we were painting a statue2 and someone came up to [5] us and started to criticize us, saying that we had not applied the most beautiful colors to the most beautiful parts of the statue; because the eyes, which are the most beautiful part, had been painted black rather than purple. We would think it reasonable to offer the following defense: “My amazing fellow, [d] you must not expect us to paint the eyes so beautifully that they no longer look like eyes at all, nor the other parts either. On the contrary, you must look to see whether, by dealing with each part appropriately, we are making the whole thing beautiful. Similarly, in the present case, you must not force us to give our guardians the sort of happiness that would make [e] them something other than guardians.You see, we know how to clothe the farmers in purple robes, festoon them with gold jewelry, and tell them to work the land whenever they please. We know we could have our potters recline on couches from right to left in front of the fire,3 drinking and [5] feasting with their wheel beside them for whenever they have a desire to make pots. And we can make all the others happy in the same way, so that the whole city is happy. But please do not urge us to do this. For if we are persuaded by you, a farmer won’t be a farmer, nor a potter a potter, nor [421a] will any of the others from which a city is constituted remain true to type. But for most of the others, it matters less: cobblers who become inferior and corrupt, and claim to be what they are not, do nothing terrible to the [5] city. But if the guardians of our laws and city are not really what they seem to be, you may be sure that they will destroy the city utterly and, on the other hand, that they alone have the opportunity to govern it well and make it happy.”

Now, if we are making genuine guardians, the sort least likely to do the [b] city evil, and if our critic is making pseudo-farmers—feasters happy at a festival, so to speak, not in a city—he is not talking about a city, but about something else. What we have to consider, then, is whether our aim in [5] establishing the guardians is the greatest possible happiness for them, or whether—since our aim is to see this happiness develop for the whole [c] city—we should compel or persuade the auxiliaries and guardians to ensure that they, and all the others as well, are the best possible craftsmen at their own work; and then, with the whole city developing and being governed [5] well, leave it to nature to provide each group with its share of happiness.

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, I think what you say is right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, will you also think me reasonable if I say something closely related?

 

ADEIMANTUS: What exactly? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Take the rest of the craftsmen again, and consider whether these things corrupt them to such an extent that they actually become bad. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: What things?

 

SOCRATES: Wealth and poverty.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What do you mean? [5]

 

SOCRATES: This: do you think that a potter who has become wealthy will still be willing to devote himself to his craft?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t he become idler and more careless than he was?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Much more. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t he become a worse potter?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, much worse.

 

SOCRATES: And surely if poverty prevents him from providing himself with tools, or any of the other things he needs for his craft, he will make poorer products himself and worse craftsmen of his sons or anyone else he teaches. [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So poverty and wealth make the products and the practitioners of the crafts worse. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that we have found other things that our guardians must prevent in every way from slipping into the city undetected.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What things?

 

SOCRATES: Wealth and poverty. For the former makes for luxury, idleness, [422a] and revolution; and the latter for illiberality, bad work, and revolution as well.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right. But consider this, Socrates: how will our city be able to fight a war if it has acquired no wealth—especially if it has to [5] fight a great and wealthy city?

 

SOCRATES: Obviously, it will be harder to fight one such city, but easier to fight two. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: First of all, if our city has to fight a city of the sort you mention, won’t it be a case of warrior-athletes fighting rich men?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it will. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, Adeimantus, don’t you think that a single boxer who has had the best possible training could easily fight two non-boxers who are rich and fat?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Maybe not at the same time.

 

SOCRATES: Not even if he could start to run away and then turn and hit [c] the one who caught up with him first, and could do this often, out in the stifling heat of the sun? Couldn’t a man like that overcome even more than two such enemies?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly would not be surprising if he could.

 

SOCRATES: Well, don’t you think that rich people have more knowledge [5] and experience of boxing than of how to fight a war?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: In all likelihood, then, our athletes will easily be able to fight two or three times their number.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I will have to grant you that, since I think what you say is [10] right.

 

[d] SOCRATES: Well, then, what if they sent an envoy to another city with the following true message: “We use no gold or silver. It is against divine law for us to do so, but not for you. So join us in this war and you can have the property of our enemy.” Do you think that anyone who heard this message [5] would choose to fight hard, lean hounds, rather than to join the hounds in fighting fat and tender sheep?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, I do not. But if the wealth of all other cities were [e] amassed by a single one, don’t you think that would endanger your non-wealthy city?

 

SOCRATES: You are happily innocent if you think that any city besides the [5] one we are constructing deserves to be called a city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What should we call them, then?

 

SOCRATES: We will have to find a “greater” title for the others because each of them is a great many cities, but not a city, as they say in the game.4 They contain two, at any rate, which are at war with one another: the city [423a] of the poor and that of the rich. And within each of these, there are a great many more. So if you treat them as one city, you will be making a big mistake. But if you treat them as many and offer one the money, power, and the very inhabitants of another, you will always find many allies and few enemies. And as long as your own city is temperately governed in the way [5] we just arranged, it will be the greatest one—not in reputation; I do not mean that; but the greatest in fact—even if it has only a thousand soldiers to defend it. For you won’t easily find one city so great among either Greeks or barbarians, though you will find many that are reputed to be many times greater. Or do you disagree? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: This, then, would also provide our rulers with the best limit for determining the proper size of the city, and how much land they should [5] mark off for a city that size, letting the rest go.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What limit is that?

 

SOCRATES: I think it is this: as long as it is willing to remain one city, it may continue to grow, but not beyond that point. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: And it is a good one. [c]

 

SOCRATES: Then we will also give our guardians this further order, that they are to guard in every possible way against the city’s being either small in size or great in reputation, rather than adequate in size and one in number.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No doubt, that will be a trivial instruction for them to follow! [5]

 

SOCRATES: Here is another that is even more trivial. We mentioned it earlier as well.5 We said that if an offspring of the guardians is inferior, he must be sent off to join the other citizens, and that if the others have an excellent offspring, he must join the guardians. This was meant to make clear that [d] every other citizen, too, must be assigned to what naturally suits him, with one person assigned to one job so that, practicing his own pursuit, each of them will become not many but one, and the entire city thereby naturally [5] grow to be one, not many.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Oh, yes, that is a more minor one!

 

SOCRATES: Really, my good Adeimantus, the orders we are giving them are neither as numerous nor as difficult as one would think. Indeed, they are all insignificant provided, as the saying goes, they safeguard the one great thing—or rather not great but adequate.6 [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: What’s that?

 

SOCRATES: Their education and upbringing. For if a good education makes them moderate men, they will easily discover all this for themselves—and everything else that we are now omitting, such as the possession [5] of women, marriages, and the procreation of children, and how all [424a] these must be governed as far as possible by the old proverb that friends share everything in common.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that would be best.

 

SOCRATES: And surely once our constitution is well started, it will, as it [5] were, go on growing in a circle. For good education and upbringing, if they are kept up, produce good natures; and sound natures, which in turn receive such an education, grow up even better than their predecessors in every respect—but particularly with respect to their offspring, as in the case [b] of all the other animals.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, probably so.

 

SOCRATES: To put it briefly, then, what the overseers of our city must cling to, not allow to become corrupted without their noticing it, and [5] guard against everything, is this: there must be no innovation in musical or physical training that goes against the established order. On the contrary, they must guard against that as much as they can. And they should dread to hear anyone say that “people think most of the song that floats newest from [10] the singer’s lips,”7 in case someone happens to suppose that the poet means [c] not new songs, but a new way of singing, and praises that. We should not praise such a claim, however, or take it to be what the poet meant. You see, a change to a new kind of musical training is something to beware of as wholly dangerous. For one can never change the ways of training people in [5] music without affecting the greatest political laws. That is what Damon says, and I am convinced he is right.

 

ADEIMANTUS: You can also count me among those who are convinced.

 

[d] SOCRATES: It seems, then, that it is in musical training that the guardhouse of our guardians must surely be built.

 

ADEIMANTUS: At any rate, this sort of lawlessness easily inserts itself undetected.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, because it is supposed to be only part of a game that, as [5] such, can do no harm.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And it does not do any—except, of course, that when it has established itself there, it slowly and silently flows over into people’s habits and practices. From these it travels forth with greater vigor into private [10] contracts, and then from private contracts it advances with the utmost insolence [e] into the laws and constitution, Socrates, until in the end it overthrows everything public and private.

 

SOCRATES: Well, is that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think it is.

 

SOCRATES: Then, as we were saying at the beginning, our children must [5] take part in games that are more law-abiding right from the start, since, if their games become lawless and the children follow suit, isn’t it impossible for them to grow up into excellent and law-abiding men? [425a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So whenever children play in a good way right from the start and absorb lawfulness from musical training, there is the opposite result: lawfulness follows them in everything and fosters their growth, correcting [5] anything in the city that may have been neglected before.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: And so such people rediscover the seemingly insignificant conventional norms their predecessors had destroyed.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which sort? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Those dealing with things like this: the silence appropriate for younger people in the presence of their elders; the giving up of seats for [b] them and standing up in their presence; the care of parents; hairstyles; clothing; shoes; the general appearance of the body; and everything else of that sort. Don’t you agree? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: To legislate about such things is naïve, in my view, since verbal or written decrees will never make them come about or last.

 

ADEIMANTUS: How could they?

 

SOCRATES: At any rate, Adeimantus, it looks as though the start of someone’s education determines what follows. Or doesn’t like always encourage [c] like?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It does.

 

SOCRATES: And the final outcome of education, I imagine we would say, is a single, complete, and fresh product that is either good or the opposite. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: That is why I, for my part, would not try to legislate about such things.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And with good reason.

 

SOCRATES: Then, by the gods, what about all that marketplace business, the contracts people make with one another in the marketplace, for example, [10] and contracts with handicraftsmen, and slanders, injuries, indictments, [d] establishing juries, paying or collecting whatever dues are necessary in marketplace and harbors, and, in a word, the entire regulation of marketplace, city, harbor, or what have you—dare we legislate about any of these? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, it would not be appropriate to dictate to men who are fine and good. For they will easily find out for themselves whatever needs [e] to be legislated about such things.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, my friend, provided that a god grants that the laws we have already described are preserved intact.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: If not, they will spend their lives continually enacting and amending such laws in the hope of finding what is best.

 

SOCRATES: You mean they will live like those sick people who, because [10] they are intemperate, are not willing to abandon their bad way of life.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

[426a] SOCRATES: Such people really do lead a charming life! Their medical treatment achieves nothing, except to make their illnesses worse and more complex, and they are always hoping that someone will recommend some new drug that will make them healthy.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s exactly what happens to invalids of this sort.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t it another charming feature of theirs that they think their worst enemy of all is the one who tells them the truth—that until they give up drunkenness, overeating, sexual indulgence, and idleness, then [b] no drug, cautery, or surgery, no charms, amulets, or anything else of that sort will do them any good?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is not charming at all. Being harsh to someone who tells the truth is not charming.

 

[5] SOCRATES: You do not approve of such men, apparently.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: Then nor will you approve of an entire city that behaves in the way we were just describing. Or don’t you think that such invalids behave in the very same way as cities where the following occurs? Because they are badly governed politically, the citizens are warned not to change the city’s [c] whole political system, and the one who does is threatened with the death penalty. But the one who serves these cities most pleasantly, while they remain politically governed in that way; who indulges them, flatters them, anticipates their wishes, and is clever at fulfilling them; isn’t he, on that [5] account, honored by them as a good man who is wise in the greatest matters?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, I think their behavior is the same and I do not approve of it at all.

 

SOCRATES: What about those who are willing and eager to provide treatment [d] for such cities? Don’t you approve of their courage and also their lighthearted irresponsibility?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do indeed—except for those who are actually deluded and suppose themselves to be true men of politics because they are praised by the masses. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What do you mean? Have you no sympathy for these men? Or do you think it is possible for a man who does not know how to measure anything not to believe that he is four cubits tall8 when many others, who are similarly ignorant, tell him that he is? [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, I do not think that.

 

SOCRATES: Then do not be too hard on them. You see, such people are surely the most charming of all. They pass and amend the sorts of laws we have just been describing, and are always expecting that they will find a [5] way to put a stop to cheating on contracts, and the other evildoings I mentioned just now, not realizing that they are really just cutting off a Hydra’s head.9

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yet that is all they are really doing. [427a]

 

SOCRATES: I would have thought, then, that a true lawgiver should not bother with laws or constitutions of this kind, whether in a politically badly governed or in a politically well-governed city—in the one because it is useless and accomplishes nothing; in the other because some of them are [5] discoverable by anyone, while the others follow automatically from the practices already described.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What remains for us to legislate, then? [b]

 

SOCRATES: For us, nothing; but for the Delphic Apollo, there remain the greatest, finest, and first of legislations.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What are they about? [5]

 

SOCRATES: The establishing of temples and sacrifices, and other forms of service to gods, daimons, and heroes; the burial of the dead, and the services that ensure the favor of those who have gone to the other world. For we, of course, have no knowledge of these things and so, when we are founding a city, we won’t take anyone else’s advice, if we have any sense, or employ any interpreter except our ancestral one. And in fact, this god—as [c] he delivers his interpretations from his seat at the navel of the earth10—is the ancestral guide on these matters for the whole human race.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well put. That is what we must do.

 

SOCRATES: So then, son of Ariston, your city would now seem to be [d] founded. As the next step, look inside it, having got hold of an adequate light somewhere. Look yourself and invite your brother and Polemarchus and the rest of us to help you, to see where justice and injustice might be in it, how they differ from one another, and which of the two must be possessed [5] by the person who is going to be happy, whether that fact is hidden from all gods and humans or not.

 

And Glaucon said:

 

That’s nonsense! You promised you would look for them yourself, because [e] you said it was impious for you not to defend justice in every way you could.11

 

SOCRATES: You are right to remind me, and I must do what I promised. But you will have to help.

 

[5] GLAUCON: We will.

 

SOCRATES: I expect, then, to find justice in the following way. I think our city, if indeed it has been correctly founded, is completely good.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it must be.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Clearly, then, it is wise, courageous, temperate, and just.

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Then if we find any of these in it, what remains will be what we have not found?

 

[428a] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, as in the case of any other four things, if we were looking for one of them in something and recognized it first, that would be enough to satisfy us. But if we recognized the other three first, that itself would enable us to recognize what we were looking for, since clearly it [5] could not be anything other than the one that remains.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: So, since there also happen to be four things we are interested in, mustn’t we look for them in the same way?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Now, the first thing I think I can see clearly in the city is wisdom. [b] And there seems to be something odd about it.

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: I think that the city we described is really wise. And that is because it is prudent,12 isn’t it?

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And surely it is clear that this very thing, prudence, is some sort of knowledge. I mean, it certainly is not through ignorance that people do the prudent thing, but through knowledge.

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: But there are, of course, many multifarious sorts of knowledge in the city. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: So, is it because of the knowledge possessed by the carpenters that the city deserves to be described as wise and prudent?

 

GLAUCON: Not at all. It is called skilled in carpentry because of that. [c]

 

SOCRATES: So a city shouldn’t be called wise because it has the knowledge that deliberates about how wooden things can be best.

 

GLAUCON: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: What about this, then? What about the knowledge of things made of bronze, or anything else of that sort? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Not anything of that sort either.

 

SOCRATES: And not the knowledge of how to produce crops from the soil. On the contrary, it is skilled in farming because of that.

 

GLAUCON: That’s my view. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Then is there some knowledge in the city we have just founded, which some of its citizens have, that does not deliberate about some particular thing in the city, but about the city as a whole, and about [d] how its internal relations and its relations with other cities will be the best possible.

 

GLAUCON: There is indeed.

 

SOCRATES: What is it and who has it? [5]

 

GLAUCON: It is the craft of guardianship. And the ones who possess it are those rulers we just now called complete guardians.13

 

SOCRATES: Because it has this knowledge, then, how do you describe the city?

 

GLAUCON: As prudent and really wise. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Now, do you think that there will be more metalworkers in [e] the city, or more of these true guardians?

 

GLAUCON: There will be far more metalworkers.

 

SOCRATES: Of all those who are called by a certain name because they have some sort of knowledge, wouldn’t the true guardians be the fewest in [5] number?

 

GLAUCON: By far.

 

SOCRATES: So, it is because of the smallest group or part of itself, and the knowledge that is in it—the part that governs and rules—that a city founded according to nature would be wise as a whole. And this class—which seems to be, by nature, the smallest—is the one that inherently possesses [429a] a share of the knowledge that alone among all the other sorts of knowledge should be called wisdom.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

[5] SOCRATES: So we have found—though I do not know how—this one of the four and its place in the city, too.

 

GLAUCON: It seems to me, at least, that it has been well and truly found.

 

SOCRATES: But surely courage and the part of the city it is in, and because of which the city is described as courageous, is not very difficult to spot.

 

GLAUCON: How so? [10]

 

[b] SOCRATES: Who would describe a city as cowardly or courageous by looking at anything other than that part which defends it and wages war on its behalf?

 

GLAUCON: No one would look at anything else.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Because, I take it, whether the others are courageous or cowardly doesn’t make it one or the other.

 

GLAUCON: No, it doesn’t.

 

SOCRATES: So courage, too, belongs to a city because of a part of itself—because it has in that part the power to preserve through everything its belief that the things, and the sorts of things, that should inspire terror are [c] the very things, and sorts of things, that the lawgiver declared to be such in the course of educating it. Or don’t you call that courage?

 

GLAUCON: I do not completely understand what you said. Would you mind repeating it?

 

[5] SOCRATES: I mean that courage is a sort of preservation.

 

GLAUCON: What sort of preservation?

 

SOCRATES: The preservation of the belief, inculcated by the law through education, about what things, and what sorts of things, inspire terror. And by its preservation “through everything,” I mean preserving it though pains, pleasures, appetites, and fears and not abandoning it. I will compare it to [d] something I think it resembles, if you like.

 

GLAUCON: I would like that.

 

SOCRATES: You know, then, that when dyers want to dye wool purple, they first select from wools of many different colors the ones that are naturally [5] white. Then they give them an elaborate preparatory treatment, so that they will accept the color as well as possible. And only at that point do they dip them in the purple dye. When something is dyed in this way, it holds the dye fast, and no amount of washing, whether with or without detergent, [e] can remove the color. But you also know what happens when things are not dyed in this way, when one dyes wools of other colors, or even these white ones, without preparatory treatment. [5]

 

GLAUCON: I know they look washed out and ridiculous.

 

SOCRATES: You should take it, then, that we too were trying as hard as we could to do something similar when we selected our soldiers and educated them in musical and physical training. It was contrived, you should suppose, for no purpose other than to ensure that—persuaded by us—they [430a] would absorb the laws in the best possible way, just like wool does a dye; that as a result, their beliefs about what things should inspire terror, and about everything else, would hold fast because they had the proper nature and rearing; so fast that the dye could not be washed out even by those [5] detergents that are so terribly effective at scouring—pleasure, which is much more terribly effective at this than any chalestrian14 or alkali, and pain and fear and appetite, which are worse than any detergent. This power, [b] then, to preserve through everything the correct and law-inculcated belief about what should inspire terror and what should not is what I, at any rate, call courage. And I will assume it is this, unless you object. [5]

 

GLAUCON: No, I have no objection. For I presume that the sort of correct belief about these same matters that you find in animals and slaves, which is not the result of education and has nothing at all to do with law, is called something other than courage.

 

SOCRATES: You are absolutely right. [c]

 

GLAUCON: Well, then, I accept your account of courage.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, do accept it, at any rate, as my account of political courage, and you will be right to accept it. If you like, we will discuss that more fully some other time.You see, at the moment, our inquiry is not about courage [5] but about justice. And for the purpose of that inquiry, I think that what we have said is sufficient.

 

GLAUCON: You are right.

 

SOCRATES: Two things, then, remain for us to find in the city: temperance15[d] and—the goal of our entire inquiry—justice.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: How could we find justice, then, so we won’t have to bother [5] with temperance any further?

 

GLAUCON: Well I, for my part, do not know of any, nor would I want justice to appear first if that means that we are not going to investigate temperance any further. So if you want to please me, look for it before the other.

 

[e] SOCRATES: Of course I want to. It would be wrong not to.16

 

GLAUCON: Go ahead and look, then.

 

SOCRATES: I will. And seen from here, it is more like a sort of concord and harmony than the previous ones.

 

[5] GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: Temperance is surely a sort of order, the mastery of certain sorts of pleasures and appetites. People indicate as much when they use the term “self-mastery”—though I do not know in what way. This and other similar things are like tracks that temperance has left. Isn’t that so?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t the term “self-mastery” ridiculous, though? For, of course, the one who is master of himself is also the one who is weaker, and the one who is weaker is also the one who masters. After all, the same person [431a] is referred to in all these descriptions.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: It seems to me, however, that what this term is trying to indicate is that within the same person’s soul, there is a better thing and a worse [5] one. Whenever the naturally better one masters the worse, this is called being master of oneself. At any rate, it is praised. But whenever, as a result of bad upbringing or associating with bad people, the smaller and better one is mastered by the inferior majority, this is blamed as a disgraceful thing [b] and is called being weaker than oneself, or being intemperate.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that seems plausible.

 

SOCRATES: Now, then, take a look at our new city and you will find one of these conditions present in it. For you will say that it is rightly described [5] as master of itself, if indeed anything in which the better rules the worse is to be described as temperate and master of itself.

 

GLAUCON: I am looking, and what you say is true.

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, pleasures, pains, and appetites that are numerous and multifarious are things one would especially find in children, women, [c] household slaves, and in the so-called free members of the masses—that is, the inferior people.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: But the pleasures, pains, and appetites that are simple and moderate, the ones that are led by rational calculation with the aid of [5] understanding and correct belief, you would find in those few people who are born with the best natures and receive the best education.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you see, then, that this too is present in your city, and that the appetites of the masses—the inferior people—are mastered there by the wisdom and appetites of the few—the best people? [d]

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: So, if any city is said to be master of its pleasures and appetites and of itself, it is this one. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: So isn’t it also temperate because of all this?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And moreover, if there is any city in which rulers and subjects share the same belief about who should rule, it is this one. Or don’t you [e] agree?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: And in which of them do you say temperance is located when they are in this condition? In the rulers or the subjects? [5]

 

GLAUCON: In both, I suppose.

 

SOCRATES: Do you see, then, that the hunch we had just now—that temperance is like a sort of harmony—was quite plausible?

 

GLAUCON: Why is that?

 

SOCRATES: Because its operation is unlike that of courage and wisdom, [10] each of which resides in one part and makes the city either courageous or wise. Temperance does not work like that, but has literally been stretched [432a] throughout the whole, making the weakest, the strongest, and those in between all sing the same song in unison—whether in wisdom, if you like, [5] or in physical strength, if you prefer; or, for that matter, in numbers, wealth, or anything else. Hence we would be absolutely right to say that this unanimity is temperance—this concord between the naturally worse and the naturally better, about which of the two should rule both in the city and in each individual.

 

[b] GLAUCON: I agree completely.

 

SOCRATES: All right. We have now spotted three kinds of virtue in our city. What kind remains, then, that would give the city yet another share of [5] virtue? For it is clear that what remains is justice.

 

GLAUCON: It is clear.

 

SOCRATES: So then, Glaucon, we must now station ourselves like hunters surrounding a wood and concentrate our minds, so that justice does not escape us and vanish into obscurity. For it is clear that it is around here [c] somewhere. Keep your eyes peeled and do your best to catch sight of it, and if you happen to see it before I do, show it to me.

 

GLAUCON: I wish I could help. But it is rather the case that if you use me as a follower who can see only what you point out to him, you will be using me in a more reasonable way.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Pray for success, then, and follow me.

 

GLAUCON: I will.You have only to lead.

 

SOCRATES: And it truly seems to be an impenetrable place and full of shadows. It is dark, at any rate, and difficult to search through. But all the same, we must go on.

 

[d] GLAUCON: Yes, we must.

 

And then I caught sight of something and shouted:

 

SOCRATES: Ah ha!17 Glaucon, it looks as though there is a track here, and I do not think our quarry will altogether escape us.

 

GLAUCON: That’s good news.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Oh dear, what a stupid condition in which to find ourselves!

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: It seems, blessed though you are, that the thing has been rolling around at our feet from the very beginning, and yet, like ridiculous fools, we could not see it. For just as people who are holding something in their hands sometimes search for the very thing they are holding, we did not look in the right direction but gazed off into the distance, and perhaps [e] that is the very reason we did not notice it.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: This: I think we have been talking and hearing about it all this [5] time without understanding ourselves, or realizing that we were, in a way, talking about it.

 

GLAUCON: That was a long prelude! Now I want to hear what you mean!

 

SOCRATES: Listen, then, and see whether there is anything in what I say. You see, what we laid down at the beginning when we were founding our [433a] city, about what should be done throughout it—that, I think, or some form of that, is justice. And surely what we laid down and often repeated, if you remember, is that each person must practice one of the pursuits in the city, the one for which he is naturally best suited. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we did say that.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we have heard many people say, and have often said ourselves, that justice is doing one’s own work and not meddling with what is not one’s own. [b]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we have.

 

SOCRATES: This, then, my friend, provided it is taken in a certain way, would seem to be justice—this doing one’s own work. And do you know what I take as evidence of that?

 

GLAUCON: No, tell me. [5]

 

SOCRATES: After our consideration of temperance, courage, and wisdom, I think that what remains in the city is the power that makes it possible for all of these to arise in it, and that preserves them when they have arisen for as long as it remains there itself. And we did say that justice would be what [c] remained when we had found the other three.18

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that must be so.

 

SOCRATES: Yet, surely, if we had to decide which of these will most contribute to making our city good by being present in it, it would be difficult [5] to decide. Is it the agreement in belief between the rulers and the subjects? The preservation among the soldiers of the law-inculcated belief about what should inspire terror and what should not? The wisdom and guardianship of the rulers? Or is what most contributes to making it good the fact [d] that every child, woman, slave, free person, craftsman, ruler, and subject each does his own work and does not meddle with what is not? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course it’s a difficult decision.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that this power—which consists in everyone’s doing his own work—rivals wisdom, temperance, and courage in its contribution to the city’s virtue.

 

[10] GLAUCON: It certainly does.

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t you say that justice is certainly what rivals them [e] in contributing to the city’s virtue?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Look at it this way, too, if you want to be convinced. Won’t you assign to the rulers the job of judging lawsuits in the city?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And will they have any aim in judging other than this: that no citizen should have what is another’s or be deprived of what is his own?

 

GLAUCON: No, they will have none but that.

 

SOCRATES: Because that is just? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So from that point of view, too, having and doing of one’s [434a] own, of what belongs to one, would be agreed to be justice.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Now, see whether you agree with me about this: if a carpenter attempts to do the work of a shoemaker, or a shoemaker that of a carpenter, or they exchange their tools or honors with one another, or if the same [5] person tries to do both jobs, and all other such exchanges are made, do you think that does any great harm to the city?

 

GLAUCON: Not really.

 

SOCRATES: But I imagine that when someone who is, by nature, a craftsman or some other sort of moneymaker is puffed up by wealth, or by having [b] a majority of votes, or by his own strength, or by some other such thing, and attempts to enter the class of soldiers; or when one of the soldiers who is unworthy to do so tries to enter that of judge and guardian, and these exchange their tools and honors; or when the same person tries [5] to do all these things at once, then I imagine you will agree that these exchanges and this meddling destroy the city.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: So, meddling and exchange among these three classes is the [c] greatest harm that can happen to the city and would rightly be called the worst evil one could do to it.

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t you say that the worst evil one could do to one’s own city is injustice? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is what injustice is. But let’s put it in reverse: the opposite of this—when the moneymaking, auxiliary, and guardian class each do their own work in the city—is justice, isn’t it, and makes the city just? [10]

 

GLAUCON: That’s exactly what I think too. [d]

 

SOCRATES: Let’s not state it as fixedly established just yet. But if this kind of thing is agreed by us to be justice in the case of individual human beings as well, then we can assent to it. For what else will there be for us to say? But if it is not, we will have to look for something else. For the moment, [5] however, let’s complete the inquiry in which we supposed that if we first tried to observe justice in some larger thing that possessed it, that would make it easier to see what it is like in an individual human being.19 We agreed that this larger thing is a city, and so we founded the best city we [e] could, knowing well that justice would of course be present in one that was good. So, let’s apply what has come to light for us there to an individual, and if it is confirmed, all will be well. But if something different is found in the case of the individual, we will go back to the city and test it there. And [5] perhaps by examining them side by side and rubbing them together like fire-sticks, we can make justice blaze forth and, once it has come to light, [435a] confirm it in our own case.

 

GLAUCON: Well, the road you describe is the right one, and we should follow it.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if you call a larger thing and a smaller thing by the same name, are they unalike in the respect in which they are called the [5] same, or alike?

 

GLAUCON: Alike.

 

SOCRATES: So a just man won’t differ at all from a just city with respect to the form of justice but will be like it. [b]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, he will be like it.

 

SOCRATES: But now, the city, at any rate, was thought to be just because each of the three natural classes within it did its own job; and to be temperate, [5] courageous, and wise, in addition, because of certain other conditions or states of these same classes.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Then, my friend, we would expect an individual to have these same kinds of things in his soul, and to be correctly called by the same [c] names as the city because the same conditions are present in them both.

 

GLAUCON: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: Well, you amazing fellow, here is another trivial investigation20[5] we have stumbled into: does the soul have these three kinds of things in it or not?

 

GLAUCON: It does not look at all trivial to me. Perhaps, Socrates, there is some truth in the old saying that everything beautiful is difficult.

 

SOCRATES: Apparently so. In fact, you should be well aware, Glaucon, that it is my belief we will never ever grasp this matter precisely by methods [d] of the sort we are now using in our discussions. However, there is in fact another longer and more time-consuming road that does lead there.21 But perhaps we can manage to come up to the standard of our previous statements [5] and inquiries.

 

GLAUCON: Shouldn’t we be content with that? It would be enough for me, at least for now.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, it will be quite satisfactory for me, too.

 

GLAUCON: Then do not weary, but go on with the inquiry.

 

[e] SOCRATES: Well, isn’t it absolutely necessary for us to agree to this much: that the very same kinds of things and conditions exist in each one of us as exist in the city? After all, where else would they come from? You see, it would be ridiculous for anyone to think that spiritedness did not come to be in cities from the private individuals who are reputed to have this quality, [5] such as the Thracians, Scythians, and others who live to the north of us; or that the same is not true of the love of learning, which is mostly associated [436a] with our part of the world; or of the love of money, which is said to be found not least among the Phoenicians and Egyptians.

 

GLAUCON: It certainly would.

 

SOCRATES: We may take that as being so, then, and it was not at all difficult [5] to discover.

 

GLAUCON: No, it certainly was not.

 

SOCRATES: But this, now, is difficult. Do we do each of them with the same thing or, since there are three, do we do one with one and another with another: that is to say, do we learn with one, feel anger with another, [10] and with yet a third have an appetite for the pleasures of food, sex, and those closely akin to them? Or do we do each of them with the whole of our soul, once we feel the impulse? That is what is difficult to determine in [b] a way that is up to the standards of our argument.

 

GLAUCON: I think so, too.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, let’s try in this way to determine whether they are the same as one another or different. [5]

 

GLAUCON: What way?

 

SOCRATES: It is clear that the same thing cannot do or undergo opposite things; not, at any rate, in the same respect, in relation to the same thing, at the same time. So, if we ever find that happening here, we will know that [10] we are not dealing with one and the same thing, but with many. [c]

 

GLAUCON: All right.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, then, what I am about to say.

 

GLAUCON: Say it.

 

SOCRATES: Is it possible for the same thing, at the same time, and in the same respect, to be standing still and moving? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s come to a more precise agreement, in order to avoid disputes later on. You see, if anyone said of a person who is standing still but moving his hands and head, that the same thing is moving and standing still [10] at the same time, we would not consider, I imagine, that he should say that; but rather that in one respect the person is standing still, while in another he is moving. Isn’t that so? [d]

 

GLAUCON: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Then, if the one who said this became still more charming and made the sophisticated point that spinning tops, at any rate, stand still as a whole at the same time as they are also in motion, when, with the peg [5] fixed in the same place, they revolve, or that the same holds of anything else that moves in a circle on the same spot—we would not agree, on the grounds that in such situations it is not in the same respects that these objects are both moving and standing still. On the contrary, we would say that these objects have both a straight axis and a circumference in them, and [e] that with respect to the straight axis they stand still—since they do not wobble to either side—whereas with respect to the circumference they move in a circle. But if their straight axis wobbles to the left or right or front or back at the same time as they are spinning, we will say that they are [5] not standing still in any way.

 

GLAUCON: And we would be right.

 

SOCRATES: No such objection will disturb us, then, or make us any more likely to believe that the same thing can—at the same time, in the same respect, and in relation to the same thing—undergo, be, or do opposite [437a] things.

 

GLAUCON: They won’t have that effect on me at least.

 

SOCRATES: All the same, in order to avoid going through all these objections [5] one by one and taking a long time to prove them all untrue, let’s hypothesize that what we have said is correct and carry on—with the understanding that if it should ever be shown to be incorrect, all the consequences we have drawn from it will be invalidated.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, that’s what we should do.

 

[b] SOCRATES: Now, wouldn’t you consider assent and dissent, wanting to have something and rejecting it, taking something and pushing it way, as all being pairs of mutual opposites—whether of opposite doings or of opposite [5] undergoings does not matter?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they are pairs of opposites.

 

SOCRATES: What about thirst, hunger, and the appetites as a whole, and also wishing and willing? Would you include all of them somewhere among [c] the kinds of things we just mentioned? For example, wouldn’t you say that the soul of someone who has an appetite wants the thing for which it has an appetite, and draws toward itself what it wishes to have; and, in addition, that insofar as his soul wishes something to be given to it, it nods assent to [5] itself as if in answer to a question, and strives toward its attainment?

 

GLAUCON: I would.

 

SOCRATES: What about not-willing, not-wishing, and not-having an appetite? Wouldn’t we include them among the very opposites, cases in which the soul pushes and drives things away from itself?

 

[d] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Since that is so, won’t we say that there is a kind consisting of appetites, and that the most conspicuous examples of them are what we call hunger and thirst?

 

[5] GLAUCON: We will.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t the one for food, the other for drink?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Now, insofar as it is thirst, is it an appetite in the soul for more than what we say it is for? I mean, is thirst a thirst for hot drink or cold, or [10] much drink or little, or—in a word—for drink of a certain sort? Or isn’t it rather that if heat is present in addition to thirst, it causes the appetite to be [e] for something cold as well, whereas the addition of cold makes it an appetite for something hot? And if there is much thirst, because of the presence of muchness, won’t it cause the desire to be for much drink, and where little for little? But thirst itself will never be for anything other than the very thing that it is in its nature to be an appetite for: namely, drink itself; and, [5] similarly, hunger is for food.

 

GLAUCON: That’s the way it is. By itself, at any rate, each appetite is for its natural object only, while an appetite for an object of this or that sort depends on additions.

 

SOCRATES: No one should catch us unprepared, then, or disturb us by claiming that no one has an appetite for drink but rather for good drink, [438a] nor for food but rather for good food, since everyone’s appetite is for good things. And so, if thirst is an appetite, it will be an appetite for good drink or good whatever, and similarly for the other appetites. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, there might seem to be something in that objection.

 

SOCRATES: But surely, whenever things are related to something, those that are of a particular sort are related to a particular sort of thing, as it seems to me, whereas those that are just themselves are related only to a [b] thing that is just itself.

 

GLAUCON: I do not understand.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you understand that the greater is such as to be greater than something? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Than the less?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And the much greater than the much less. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And the once greater than the once less? And the going-to-be greater than the going-to-be less?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t the same hold of the more in relation to the fewer, the double to the half, and everything of that sort; and also of [5] heavier to lighter and faster to slower; and, in addition, of hot to cold, and all other similar things?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What about the various kinds of knowledge? Aren’t they the same way? Knowledge itself is of what can be learned itself (or of whatever we should take the object of knowledge to be), whereas a particular knowledge of a particular sort is of a particular thing of a particular sort. I mean something like this: when knowledge of building houses was developed, it [d] differed from the other kinds of knowledge, and so was called knowledge of building. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And wasn’t that because it was a different sort of knowledge [5] from all the others?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And wasn’t it because it was of a particular sort of thing that it itself became a particular sort of knowledge? And isn’t this true of all the crafts and sciences?

 

[10] GLAUCON: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, you should think of that as what I wanted to get across before—if you understand it now—when I said that whenever things are related to something, those that are just themselves are related to things that are just themselves, whereas those of a particular sort are related to things of a particular sort. And I do not at all mean that the sorts in question [e] have to be the same for them both—that the knowledge of health and disease is healthy and diseased, or that that of good and bad things is good and bad. On the contrary, I mean that when knowledge occurred that was not just knowledge of the thing itself that knowledge is of, but of something of [5] a particular sort, which in this case was health and disease, the result was that it itself became a particular sort of knowledge; and this caused it to be no longer called simply knowledge but, with the addition of the particular sort, medical knowledge.

 

GLAUCON: I understand and I think you are right.

 

SOCRATES: Returning to thirst, then, wouldn’t you include it among the [439a] things that are related to something just by being what they are? Surely thirst is related to. . . .

 

GLAUCON: I would. It is related to drink.

 

SOCRATES: So a particular sort of thirst is for a particular sort of drink. [5] Thirst itself, however, is not for much or little, good or bad, or, in a word, for drink of a particular sort; rather, thirst itself is, by nature, just for drink itself. Right?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Hence the soul of the thirsty person, insofar as it is simply thirsty, does not want anything else except to drink, and this is what it [b] longs for and is impelled to do.

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Then if anything in it draws it back when it is thirsty, wouldn’t it be something different from what thirsts and, like a beast, drives it to drink? For surely, we say, the same thing, in the same respect of itself, in relation to the same thing, and at the same time, cannot do opposite [5] things.

 

GLAUCON: No, it cannot.

 

SOCRATES: In the same way, I imagine, it is not right to say of the archer that his hands at the same time push the bow away and draw it toward him. On the contrary, we should say that one hand pushes it away, while the other draws it toward him. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely. [c]

 

SOCRATES: Now, we would say, wouldn’t we, that some people are thirsty sometimes, yet unwilling to drink?

 

GLAUCON: Many people often are.

 

SOCRATES: What, then, should one say about them? Isn’t it that there is an [5] element in their soul urging them to drink, and also one stopping them—something different that masters the one doing the urging?

 

GLAUCON: I certainly think so.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t the element doing the stopping in such cases arise—when it does arise—from rational calculation, while the things that drive and drag are present because of feelings and diseases? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Apparently so.

 

SOCRATES: It would not be unreasonable for us to claim, then, that there are two elements, different from one another; and to call the element in the soul with which it calculates, the rationally calculating element; and the [5] one with which it feels passion, hungers, thirsts, and is stirred by other appetites, the irrational and appetitive element, friend to certain ways of being filled and certain pleasures.

 

GLAUCON: No, it would not. Indeed, it would be a very natural thing for us to do. [e]

 

SOCRATES: Let’s assume, then, that we have distinguished these two kinds of elements in the soul. Now, is the spirited element—the one with which we feel anger—a third kind of thing, or is it the same in nature as one of these others?

 

GLAUCON: As the appetitive element, perhaps. [5]

 

SOCRATES: But I once heard a story and I believe it. Leontius, the son of Aglaeon, was going up from the Piraeus along the outside of the North Wall when he saw some corpses with the public executioner nearby. He had an appetitive desire to look at them, but at the same time he was disgusted and [10] turned himself away. For a while he struggled and put his hand over his eyes, [440a] but finally, mastered by his appetite, he opened his eyes wide and rushed toward the corpses, saying: “Look for yourselves, you evil wretches; take your fill of the beautiful sight.”22

 

GLAUCON: I have also heard that story myself.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Yet, surely, the story suggests that anger sometimes makes war against the appetites as one thing against another.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it does suggest that.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t we often notice on other occasions that when [b] appetite forces someone contrary to his rational calculation, he reproaches himself and feels anger at the thing in him that is doing the forcing; and just as if there were two warring factions, such a person’s spirit becomes the ally of his reason? But spirit partnering the appetites to do what reason has [5] decided should not be done—I do not imagine you would say that you had ever seen that, either in yourself or in anyone else.

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I would not.

 

SOCRATES: And what about when a person thinks he is doing some injustice? [c] Isn’t it true that the nobler he is, the less capable he is of feeling angry if he suffers hunger, cold, or the like at the hands of someone whom he believes to be inflicting this on him justly; and won’t his spirit, as I say, [5] refuse to be aroused?

 

GLAUCON: It is true.

 

SOCRATES: But what about when a person believes he is being unjustly treated? Doesn’t his spirit boil then, and grow harsh and fight as an ally of what he holds to be just? And even if it suffers hunger, cold, and every imposition of that sort, doesn’t it stand firm and win out over them, not [d] ceasing its noble efforts until it achieves its purpose, or dies, or, like a dog being called to heel by a shepherd, is called back by the reason alongside it and becomes gentle?

 

GLAUCON: Your simile is perfect. And, in fact, we did put the auxiliaries [5] in our city to be like obedient sheepdogs for the city’s shepherdlike rulers.

 

SOCRATES: You have understood what I was trying to say very well. But have you also noticed something else about it?

 

[e] GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: That it is the opposite of what we recently thought about the kind of thing spirit is. You see, then we thought of it as something appetitive.23 But now, far from saying that, we say that in the faction that takes place in the soul, it is far more likely to take arms on the side of the rationally [5] calculating element.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Is it also different from this, then, or is it some kind of rationally calculating element, so that there are not three kinds of things in the soul, but two—the rationally calculating element and the appetitive one? Or rather, just as there were three classes in the city that held it together—[10] the moneymaking, the auxiliary, and the deliberative—is there also this [441a] third element in the soul, the spirited kind, which is the natural auxiliary of the rationally calculating element, if it has not been corrupted by bad upbringing?

 

GLAUCON: There must be a third.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, provided, at any rate, that it can be shown to be as distinct from the rationally calculating element as it was shown to be from the [5] appetitive one.

 

GLAUCON: But it is not difficult to show that. After all, one can see it even in small children: they are full of spirit right from birth, but as for rational calculation, some of them seem to me never to possess it, while the masses do so quite late. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Yes, by Zeus, you put that really well. Besides, one can see in animals that what you say is true. But, in addition to that, our earlier quotation from Homer also bears it out: “He struck his chest and spoke to his heart.”24 You see, in it Homer clearly presents what has calculated about better and worse, rebuking what is irrationally angry as though it were [c] something different.

 

GLAUCON: That’s exactly right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, we have had a difficult swim through all that, and we are pretty much agreed that the same classes as are in the city are in the soul of [5] each individual, and an equal number of them too.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Then doesn’t it already necessarily follow that the private individual is wise in the same way and because of the same element as is the city? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And that the city is courageous in the same way and because [d] of the same element as is the private individual? And that in everything else that pertains to virtue, both are alike?

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And so, Glaucon, I take it we will also say that a man is just in exactly the same way as is a city.

 

GLAUCON: That too follows with absolute necessity.

 

SOCRATES: But we surely have not forgotten that the city was just because [10] each of the three classes in it does its own work.

 

GLAUCON: I do not think we have.

 

SOCRATES: We should also bear in mind, then, that in the case of each one of us as well, the one in whom each of the elements does its own job will [e] be just and do his own job.

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then isn’t it appropriate for the rationally calculating element to rule, since it is really wise and exercises foresight on behalf of the whole [5] soul; and for the spirited kind to obey it and be its ally?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Now, as we were saying, isn’t it a mixture of musical and physical training that makes these elements concordant, tightening and nurturing [442a] the first with fine words and learning, while relaxing, soothing, and making gentle the second by means of harmony and rhythm?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, exactly.

 

SOCRATES: And these two elements, having been trained in this way and having truly learned their own jobs and been educated, will be put in [5] charge of the appetitive element—the largest one in each person’s soul and, by nature, the most insatiable for money. They will watch over it to see that it does not get so filled with the so-called pleasures of the body that it becomes big and strong, and no longer does its own job but attempts to [b] enslave and rule over the classes it is not fitted to rule, thereby overturning the whole life of anyone in whom it occurs.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And wouldn’t these two elements also do the finest job of guarding the whole soul and body against external enemies—the one by deliberating, the other by fighting, following the ruler, and using its courage to carry out the things on which the former had decided?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, they would.

 

SOCRATES: I imagine, then, that we call each individual courageous because of the latter part—that is, when the part of him that is spirited in kind preserves through pains and pleasures the pronouncements of reason25 [c] about what should inspire terror and what should not.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: But we call him wise, surely, because of the small part that rules in him, makes those pronouncements, and has within it the knowledge [5] of what is advantageous—both for each part and for the whole, the community composed of all three.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: What about temperance? Isn’t he temperate because of the friendly and concordant relations between these same things: namely, when [10] both the ruler and its two subjects share the belief that the rationally calculating element should rule, and do not engage in faction against it? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Temperance in a city and in a private individual is certainly nothing other than that.

 

SOCRATES: But surely, now, a person will be just because of what we have so often described and in the way we have so often described. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, has our justice become in any way blurred? Does it look like anything other than the very thing we found in the city?

 

GLAUCON: It doesn’t seem so to me, at least.

 

SOCRATES: We could make perfectly sure, if there is still anything in our [10] souls that disputes this, by applying everyday tests to it. [e]

 

GLAUCON: Which ones?

 

SOCRATES: For example, if we had to come to an agreement about whether a man similar in nature and training to this city of ours would embezzle [5] gold or silver he had accepted for deposit, who do you think would consider him more likely to do so than men of a different sort? [443a]

 

GLAUCON: No one.

 

SOCRATES: And would he have anything to do with temple robberies,26 thefts, or betrayals of friends in private life or of cities in public life?

 

GLAUCON: No, nothing. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And he would be in no way untrustworthy when it came to promises or other agreements.

 

GLAUCON: How could he be?

 

SOCRATES: And surely adultery, disrespect for parents, and neglect of the gods would be more characteristic of any other sort of person than of this [10] one.

 

GLAUCON: Of any other sort, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t the reason for all this the fact that each element [b] within him does its own job where ruling and being ruled are concerned?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that and nothing else.

 

SOCRATES: Are you still looking for justice to be something besides this [5] power that produces men and cities of the sort we have described?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I am not.

 

SOCRATES: The dream we had has been completely fulfilled, then—I mean the suspicion we expressed that right from the beginning, when we were founding the city, we had, with the help of some god, chanced to hit [c] upon the origin and pattern of justice.27

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: So, Glaucon, it really was—which is why it was so helpful—a sort of image of justice, this principle that it is right for someone who is, by [5] nature, a shoemaker to practice shoemaking and nothing else, for a carpenter to practice carpentry, and the same for all the others.

 

GLAUCON: Apparently so.

 

SOCRATES: And in truth, justice is, it seems, something of this sort. Yet it is not concerned with someone’s doing his own job on the outside. On the [10] contrary, it is concerned with what is inside; with himself, really, and the [d] things that are his own. It means that he does not allow the elements in him each to do the job of some other, or the three sorts of elements in his soul to meddle with one another. Instead, he regulates well what is really his own, rules himself, puts himself in order, becomes his own friend, and harmonizes [5] the three elements together, just as if they were literally the three defining notes of an octave—lowest, highest, and middle—as well as any others that may be in between. He binds together all of these and, from [e] having been many, becomes entirely one, temperate and harmonious. Then and only then should he turn to action, whether it is to do something concerning the acquisition of wealth or concerning the care of his body, or even something political, or concerning private contracts. In all these areas, he considers and calls just and fine the action that preserves this inner harmony [5] and helps achieve it,28 and wisdom the knowledge that oversees such action; and he considers and calls unjust any action that destroys this harmony, and ignorance the belief that oversees it.29 [444a]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if we claim to have found the just man, the just city, and what justice really is in them, we won’t, I imagine, be thought to [5] be telling a complete lie.

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, we certainly won’t.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we claim it, then?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, let’s.

 

SOCRATES: So be it, then. I take it we must look for injustice next. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Mustn’t it, in turn, be a kind of faction among those three—[b] their meddling and interfering with one another’s jobs; the rebellion of a part of the soul against the whole in order to rule in it inappropriately, since its nature suits it to be a slave of the ruling class.30 We will say something [5] like that, I imagine, and that their disorder and wandering is injustice, licentiousness, cowardice, ignorance, and, in a word, the whole of vice.

 

GLAUCON: That is precisely what they are.

 

SOCRATES: Doing unjust actions, then, and being unjust; and, the opposite, [c] doing just ones—they all surely become clear at once, don’t they, provided that both injustice and justice are also clear?

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: That they do not differ in any way from healthy actions and [5] unhealthy ones, that what the latter are in the body, they are in the soul.

 

GLAUCON: In what respect?

 

SOCRATES: Surely, healthy actions engender health, unhealthy ones disease.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Well, doesn’t doing just actions also engender justice, unjust ones injustice? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: But to produce health is to put the elements that are in the body in their natural relations of mastering and being mastered by one another; while to produce disease is to establish a relation of ruling and being ruled by one another that is contrary to nature. [5]

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t it follow, then, that to produce justice is to establish the elements in the soul in a natural relation of mastering and being mastered by one another, while to produce injustice is to establish a relation of [10] ruling and being ruled by one another that is contrary to nature?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Virtue, then, so it seems, is a sort of health, a fine and good [e] state of the soul; whereas vice seems to be a shameful disease and weakness.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t fine practices lead to the possession of virtue, [5] shameful ones to vice?

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: So it now remains, it seems, for us to consider whether it is [445a] more profitable to do just actions, engage in fine practices, and be just, whether one is known to be so or not; or to do injustice and be unjust, provided that one does not have to pay the penalty and become a better person as a result of being punished.

 

[5] GLAUCON: But, Socrates, that question seems to me, at least, to have become ridiculous, now that the two have been shown to be as we described. Life does not seem worth living when the body’s natural constitution is ruined, not even if one has food and drink of every sort, all the money in the world, and every political office imaginable. So how—even if [b] one could do whatever one wished, except what would liberate one from vice and injustice and make one acquire justice and virtue—could it be worth living when the natural constitution of the very thing by which we live31 is ruined and in turmoil?

 

SOCRATES: Yes, it is ridiculous. All the same, since in fact we have reached [5] a point from which we can see with the utmost clarity, as it were, that these things are so, we must not give up.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely the last thing we should do.

 

SOCRATES: Come up here, then, so that you can see how many kinds of [c] vice there are—the ones, at any rate, that are worth seeing.

 

GLAUCON: I am following. Just tell me.32

 

SOCRATES: Well, from the vantage point, so to speak, that we have reached [5] in our argument, it seems to me that there is one kind of virtue and an unlimited number of kinds of vice, four of which are worth mentioning.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: It seems likely that there are as many types of soul as there are types of political constitution of a specific kind. [10]

 

GLAUCON: How many is that?

 

SOCRATES: Five types of constitution, and five of soul. [d]

 

GLAUCON: Tell me what they are.

 

SOCRATES: I will tell you that one type would be the constitution we have been describing. However, there are two ways of referring to it: if one outstanding man emerges among the rulers, it is called a kingship; if more than [5] one, it is called an aristocracy.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is one of the kinds I had in mind. You see, whether many arise or just one, they won’t change any of the laws of the city that are worth mentioning, since they will have been brought up and [e] educated in the way we described.

 

GLAUCON: No, they probably won’t.

 

1 This discussion begins at 445c, but is interrupted and does not resume again until Book 8.

2 Ancient Greek statues were painted and gilded.

3 At formal drinking parties (sumposia), the toastmaster (sumposiarchos) sat at the head of the table. The others sat in order of their importance, from his right counterclockwise around the table to his left.

4 The reference is obscure; it may be to a saying or proverb, or to a game like checkers called poleis, or cities, in which the set of pieces on each side, or perhaps any subset of them, were called cities, while the individual members of the sets were called dogs.

5 415a–c.

6 See 423c4.

7 Odyssey 1.351–2. Our text of Homer is slightly different.

8 Roughly seven feet. A cubit is between seventeen and twenty-two inches long.

9 The Hydra was a mythical monster. When one of its heads was cut off, two or three new heads grew in its place. Heracles (or Hercules) had to slay the Hydra as one of his labors.

10 The oracle of Apollo at Delphi was traditionally consulted by all Greeks on religious and other such matters. A stone there marked the supposed center of the earth.

11 368b7–c3.

12 Euboulos: In Greek cities, the boulê was the council that had day-to-day responsibility for public affairs. In kingships it served as an advisory body to the kings; in democratic Athens it served as an advisory body and steering committee for the assembly of all the adult male citizens.

13 414b1–6.

14 Carbonate of soda from Chalestra, a town and lake in Macedonia.

15 See Glossary of Terms s.v. temperance.

16 See 427d8–e4.

17 Iou iou: usually a cry of woe in tragedy, not (like iô iô) a cry of joy.

18 428a2–9.

19 368c7–369a3.

20 See 423c5–e2.

21 See 504b1–c4 for an explanation.

22 A fragment of the comedy Kapêlides by Theopompus (410–370 BCE) tells us that a certain Leontinus (emended to Leontius because of Plato’s reference here) was known for his love of boys as pale as corpses. So his desire is probably sexual in origin, and for that reason appetitive. The North and South Walls enclosed an area connecting Athens to Piraeus.

23 439e5.

24 Odyssey 20.17. See 390d.

25 Reading 1234 with Adam.

26 See 344b3 note.

27 432d2–433b4.

28 Cf. 338e1–339a4.

29 The difference between knowledge (epistêmê) and belief (doxa) is explored at 475d1–480a13.

30 Reading 1234 with Adam.

31 I.e., the soul. See 353d9–10.

32 See 432c3–4.

Book 5

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION CONTINUES:

[449a] SOCRATES: That, then, is the sort of city and constitution—and the sort of man—I call good and correct. And if indeed this one is correct, all the others are bad and mistaken, both as city governments and as ways of organizing [5] the souls of private individuals. The deficient ones fall into four kinds.

 

GLAUCON: What are they?

 

I was going to describe them in the order in which I thought they developed [b] out of one another.1 But Polemarchus, who was sitting not far from Adeimantus, extended his hand, gripped the latter’s cloak by the shoulder from above, drew Adeimantus toward him, and, leaning forward himself, said some things [5] in his ear. We overheard nothing of what he said, other than this:

 

Shall we let it go, then, or what?

 

ADEIMANTUS: (Now speaking aloud.) Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: What is it exactly you won’t let go?

 

ADEIMANTUS: You!

 

[c] SOCRATES: Why exactly?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We think you are being lazy, that you are robbing us of a whole important section of the argument in order to avoid having to explain it. You thought we would not notice when you said—as though it were something inconsequential—that, as regards women and children, anyone [5] could see that it will be a case of friends sharing everything in common.2

 

SOCRATES: But isn’t that correct, Adeimantus?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is. But it is just like all the rest we have discussed; its correctness requires an explanation of how the sharing will be arranged, since there are many ways to bring it about. So, do not omit to tell us about [d] the particular one you have in mind. We have all been waiting for a long time in the expectation that you would surely discuss how procreation will be handled, how the children that are born will be reared, and the whole subject of what you mean by sharing women and children. You see, we think that this makes a considerable difference—indeed, all the difference—to whether a constitution is correct or incorrect. So now that you are [5] beginning to describe another constitution without having analyzed this matter adequately, we are resolved, as you overheard, not to let you go until you explain all this just as you did the rest. [450a]

 

GLAUCON: Include me, too, as having a share in this vote.

 

And Thrasymachus said:

 

In fact, you can take it as the resolution of all of us, Socrates. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What a thing to do, attacking me like that. You have started up a huge discussion about the constitution—it will be like starting from the beginning. I was delighted to think I had already completed its description by this time and was satisfied to have what I had said earlier be accepted as is. You do not realize what a swarm of arguments you are now stirring up [10] by making this demand. It was because I could see it that I left the topic [b] aside, to avoid all the trouble it would cause us.

 

THRASYMACHUS: What of it? Don’t you think these people have come here now to listen to arguments, not to smelt ore?3

 

SOCRATES: Yes—within moderation, at least. [5]

 

GLAUCON: But surely it is within moderation, Socrates, for people with any sense to listen to such arguments their whole life long. So never mind about us. Don’t you get tired of explaining your views on what we asked about: namely, what the sharing of children and women will amount to for [c] our guardians, and how the children will be brought up while they are still small. After all, the time between birth and the beginning of formal education seems to be the most troublesome period of all. So, try to tell us in what way it should be handled. [5]

 

SOCRATES: It is not easy to explain, my happy fellow. It raises even more doubts than the topics we have discussed so far. One might, in fact, doubt whether what we proposed is possible, and, even if one granted that it is entirely so, one might still have doubts about whether it would be for the best. That, then, is why I was somewhat hesitant to bring it up: I was afraid, my dear comrade, that our argument might seem to be no more than wishful thinking. [d]

 

GLAUCON: Do not hesitate at all. You see, your audience won’t be inconsiderate, or incredulous, or hostile.

 

SOCRATES: My very good fellow, are you saying that because you want to [5] encourage me?

 

GLAUCON: I am.

 

SOCRATES: Well, you are having precisely the opposite effect. If I were confident that I was speaking with knowledge, your encouragement would be all very well. When one is among knowledgeable and beloved friends, and one is speaking what one knows to be the truth about the [10] greatest and most beloved things, one can feel both secure and [e] confident. But to produce arguments when one is uncertain and searching, [451a] as I am doing, is a frightening thing and makes one feel insecure. I am not afraid of being ridiculed—that would be childish, indeed—but I am afraid that if I fail to secure the truth, just where it is most important to do so, I will not only fall myself but drag my friends down as well. So I bow [5] to Adrasteia, Glaucon, for what I am about to say. You see, I suspect that involuntary homicide is a lesser crime than misleading people about beautiful, good, and just norms. That is a risk it would be better to run among enemies than among friends. So you have well and truly encouraged [b] me.

 

Glaucon laughed and said:

 

Well, Socrates, if we suffer from any false note you strike in the argument, we will release you, as we would in a homicide case, as guiltless and no [5] deceiver of us. So you may speak with confidence.

 

SOCRATES: Well, it is true; the one who is acquitted in that situation is guiltless, so the law says. And if it is true there, it is probably true here, too.

 

GLAUCON: On these grounds, then, tell us.

 

SOCRATES: I will have to go back again, then, and say now what perhaps I [c] should have said then in the proper place. But maybe it is all right, after having completed a male drama, to perform a female one next4—especially when you demand it in this way. For people born and educated as we have described, then, there is, I believe, no correct way to acquire and employ [5] children and women other than to follow the path on which we first set them. Surely, in our argument, we tried to establish the men as guard-dogs of their flock.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s proceed by giving corresponding rules for birth and [d] rearing, and see whether they suit us or not.

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: As follows. Do we think that the females of our guard-dogs should join in guarding precisely what the males guard, hunt with them, [5] and share everything with them? Or do we think that they should stay indoors and look after the house,5 on the grounds that they are incapable of doing this because they must bear and rear the puppies, while the males should work and have the entire care of the flock?

 

GLAUCON: They should share everything—except that we employ the females as we would weaker animals, and the males as we would stronger [e] ones.

 

SOCRATES: Is it possible, then, to employ an animal for the same tasks as another if you do not give it the same upbringing and education?

 

GLAUCON: No, it is not. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then if we employ women for the same tasks as men, they must also be taught the same things.

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [452a]

 

SOCRATES: Now, we gave the latter musical and physical training.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, we must also give these two crafts, as well as military training, to the women, and employ them in the same way. [5]

 

GLAUCON: That seems reasonable, given what you say.

 

SOCRATES: But perhaps many of the things we are now saying, because they are contrary to custom, would seem ridiculous if they were put into practice.

 

GLAUCON: Indeed, they would.

 

SOCRATES: What do you see as the most ridiculous aspect of them? Isn’t it obvious that it is the idea of the women exercising stripped in the palestras [10] alongside the men?6 And not just the young women, but the older ones too—like the old men we see in gymnasiums who, even though their bodies [b] are wrinkled and not pleasant to look at, still love physical training.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, that would look really ridiculous, at least under [5] present conditions.

 

SOCRATES: Yet, since we have started to discuss the matter, we must not be afraid of the various jokes that the wits will make both about this sort of change in musical and physical training and—even more so—about the [c] change in the bearing of arms and the mounting of cavalry horses.7

 

GLAUCON: You are right.

 

SOCRATES: But since we have started, we must move on to the rougher [5] part of the law, and ask these wits not to do their own job, but to be serious. And we will remind them that it is not long since the Greeks thought it shameful and ridiculous (as many barbarians still do) for men to be seen stripped, and that when first the Cretans and then the Lacedaemonians began the gymnasiums, the wits of the time had the opportunity to make a [d] comedy of it all. Or don’t you think so?

 

GLAUCON: I certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: But when it became clear, I take it, to those who employed these practices, that it was better to strip than to cover up all such parts, the laughter in the eyes faded away because of what the arguments had proved [5] to be best. And this showed that it is a fool who finds anything ridiculous except what is bad, or tries to raise a laugh at the sight of anything except what is stupid or bad, or—putting it the other way around—who takes [e] seriously any standard of what is beautiful other than what is good.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, shouldn’t we first agree about whether our proposals [5] are viable or not? And mustn’t we give anyone who wishes to do so—whether it is someone who loves a joke or someone serious—the opportunity [453a] to dispute whether the female human does have the natural ability to share in all the tasks of the male sex, or in none at all, or in some but not others; and, in particular, whether this holds in the case of warfare? By making the best beginning in this way, wouldn’t one also be likely to reach [5] the best conclusion?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So, would you like us to dispute with one another on their behalf, so that their side of the argument won’t be attacked without defenders?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Why not?

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s say this on their behalf: “Socrates and Glaucon, you do not need other people to dispute you. After all, you yourselves, when you were beginning to found your city, agreed that each one had to do the one job for which he was naturally suited.” [5]

 

GLAUCON: We did agree to that, I think. Of course we did.

 

SOCRATES: “Can it be, then, that a woman is not by nature very different from a man?”

 

GLAUCON: Of course she is different.

 

SOCRATES: “Then isn’t it also appropriate to assign a different job to each of them, the one for which they are naturally suited?” [10]

 

GLAUCON: Certainly. [c]

 

SOCRATES: “How is it, then, that you are not making a mistake now and contradicting yourselves, when you say that men and women must do the same jobs, seeing that they have natures that are most distinct?” Do you [5] have any defense, you amazing fellow, against that attack?

 

GLAUCON: It is not easy to think of one on the spur of the moment. On the contrary, I shall ask—indeed, I am asking—you to explain the argument on our side as well, whatever it is.

 

SOCRATES: That, Glaucon, and many other problems of the same sort, which I foresaw long ago, was what I was afraid of when I hesitated to [d] tackle the law concerning the possession and upbringing of women and children.

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, it certainly does not seem to be a simple matter.

 

SOCRATES: No, it is not. But the fact is that whether one falls into a small [5] diving pool or into the middle of the greatest sea, one has to swim all the same.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then we must swim, too, and try to save ourselves from the sea of argument, hoping for a dolphin to pick us up, or for some other [10] unlikely rescue.8

 

GLAUCON: It seems so. [e]

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, let’s see if we can find a way out. We have agreed, of course, that different natures must have different pursuits, and that the natures of a woman and a man are different. But we now say that those different natures must have the same pursuits. Isn’t that the charge against us? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, exactly.

 

SOCRATES: What a noble power, Glaucon, the craft of disputation9 possesses! [454a]

 

GLAUCON: Why is that?

 

SOCRATES: Because many people seem to me to fall into it even against [5] their wills, and think they are engaging not in eristic,10 but in discussion. This happens because they are unable to examine what has been said by dividing it up into kinds. Instead, it is on the purely verbal level that they look for the contradiction in what has been said, and employ eristic, not dialectic, on one another.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, that certainly does happen to many people. But surely it is not pertinent to us at the moment, is it?

 

SOCRATES: It most certainly is. At any rate, we are in danger of unconsciously [b] dealing in disputation.

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: We are trying to establish the principle that different natures [5] should not be assigned the same pursuits in a bold and eristic manner, on the verbal level. But we did not at all investigate what kind of natural difference or sameness we had in mind, or in what regard the distinction was pertinent, when we assigned different pursuits to different natures and the same ones to the same.

 

[10] GLAUCON: No, we did not investigate that.

 

SOCRATES: And because we did not, it is open to us, apparently, to ask [c] ourselves whether the natures of bald and long-haired men are the same or opposite. And, once we agree that they are opposite, it is open to us to forbid the long-haired ones to be shoemakers, if that is what the bald ones are [5] to be, or vice versa.

 

GLAUCON: But that would be ridiculous.

 

SOCRATES: And is it ridiculous for any other reason than that we did not have in mind every kind of difference and sameness in nature, but were keeping our eyes only on the kind of difference and sameness that was pertinent [d] to the pursuits themselves? We meant, for example, that a male and female whose souls are suited for medicine have the same nature. Or don’t you think so?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

[5] SOCRATES: But a male doctor and a male carpenter have different ones?

 

GLAUCON: Of course, completely different.

 

SOCRATES: In the case of both the male and the female sex, then, if one of them is shown to be different from the other with regard to a particular craft or pursuit, we will say that is the one who should be assigned to it. But if it is apparent that they differ in this respect alone, that the female bears the offspring while the male mounts the female, we will say it has not [10] yet been demonstrated that a woman is different from a man with regard to [e] what we are talking about, and we will continue to believe our guardians and their women should have the same pursuits.

 

GLAUCON: And rightly so.

 

SOCRATES: Next, won’t we urge our opponent to tell us the precise craft or pursuit, relevant to the organization of the city, for which a woman’s [455a] nature and a man’s are not the same but different?

 

GLAUCON: That would be a fair question, at least.

 

SOCRATES: Perhaps, then, this other person might say, just as you did a moment ago,11 that it is not easy to give an adequate answer on the spur of [5] the moment, but that after reflection it would not be at all difficult.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, he might say that.

 

SOCRATES: Do you want us to ask the one who disputes things in this way, then, to follow us to see whether we can somehow show him that there is no pursuit relevant to the management of the city that is peculiar to [b] women?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, we will say to him, give us an answer: “Is this what you meant by one person being naturally well suited for something and another naturally unsuited: that the one learns it easily, the other with [5] difficulty; that the one, after a little instruction, can discover a lot for himself in the subject being studied, whereas the other, even if he gets a lot of instruction and attention, does not even retain what he was taught; that the bodily capacities of the one adequately serve his mind, while those of the other obstruct his? Are there any other factors than these, by which you [c] distinguish a person who is naturally well suited for each pursuit from one who is not?”

 

GLAUCON: No one will be able to mention any others.

 

SOCRATES: Do you know of anything practiced by human beings, then, at which the male sex is not superior to the female in all those ways? Or must [5] we make a long story of it by discussing weaving and the preparation of baked and boiled food12—the very pursuits in which the female sex is thought to excel, and in which its defeat would expose it to the greatest [d] ridicule of all?

 

GLAUCON: It is true that the one sex shows greater mastery than the other in pretty much every area. Yet there are many women who are better than [5] many men at many things. But on the whole, it is as you say.

 

SOCRATES: Then, my friend, there is no pursuit relevant to the management of the city that belongs to a woman because she is a woman, or to a man because he is a man; but the various natural capacities are distributed in a similar way between both creatures, and women can share by nature in every pursuit, and men in every one, though for the purposes of all of them [e] women are weaker than men.13

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So shall we assign all of them to men and none to women?

 

[5] GLAUCON: How could we?

 

SOCRATES: We could not. For we will say, I imagine, that one woman is suited for medicine, another not, and that one is naturally musical, another not.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t one be suited for physical training or war, then, while [456a] another is unwarlike and not a lover of physical training?

 

GLAUCON: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: And one a philosopher (lover of wisdom), another a “misosopher” [5] (hater of wisdom)? And one spirited, another spiritless?

 

GLAUCON: That too.

 

SOCRATES: So there is also a woman who is suited to be a guardian, and one who is not. Or wasn’t that the sort of nature we selected for our male guardians, too?14

 

GLAUCON: It certainly was.

 

SOCRATES: A woman and a man can have the same nature, then, relevant [10] to guarding the city—except to the extent that she is weaker and he is stronger.

 

GLAUCON: Apparently so.

 

SOCRATES: Women of that sort, then, must be selected to live and guard with men of the same sort, since they are competent to do so and are akin [b] to the men by nature.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t we assign the same pursuits to the same natures? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, the same ones.

 

SOCRATES: We have come around, then, to what we said before, and we are agreed that it is not against nature to assign musical and physical training to the female guardians. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: So, we are not legislating impossibilities or mere fantasies, at any rate, since the law we were proposing is in accord with nature. Rather, it is the contrary laws that we have now that turn out to be more contrary [c] to nature, it seems.

 

GLAUCON: It does seem that way.

 

SOCRATES: Now, wasn’t our inquiry about whether our proposals were both viable and best? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it was.

 

SOCRATES: And that they are in fact viable has been agreed, hasn’t it?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, we must next come to an agreement about whether they are for the best?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Now, as regards producing a woman who is equipped for guardianship, we won’t have one sort of education that will produce our guardian men, will we, and another our women—especially not when it will have the same nature to work on in both cases? [d]

 

GLAUCON: No, we won’t.

 

SOCRATES: What is your belief about this, then?

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: The notion that one man is better or worse than another—or [5] do you think they are all alike?

 

GLAUCON: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: In the city we are founding, who do you think will turn out to be better men: our guardians, who get the education we have described, or the shoemakers, who are educated in shoemaking? [10]

 

GLAUCON: What a ridiculous question!

 

[e] SOCRATES: I realize that. Aren’t the guardians the best of the citizens?

 

GLAUCON: By far.

 

SOCRATES: And what about the female guardians? Won’t they be the best of the women?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, they are by far the best, too.

 

SOCRATES: Is there anything better for a city than that the best possible men and women should come to exist in it?

 

GLAUCON: No, there is not.

 

SOCRATES: And that is what musical and physical training, employed as we [457a] have described, will achieve?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then the law we were proposing was not only possible, but also best for a city?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then the female guardians must strip, clothing themselves in virtue instead of cloaks.15 They must share in warfare, and whatever else guarding the city involves, and do nothing else. But within these areas, the women must be assigned lighter tasks than the men, because of the weakness [10] of their sex. And the man who laughs at the sight of women stripped for physical training, when their stripping is for the best, is “plucking the [b] unripe fruit of laughter’s wisdom,”16 and knows nothing, it seems, about what he is laughing at or what he is doing. For it is, and always will be, the [5] finest saying that what is beneficial is beautiful; what is harmful ugly.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: May we claim, then, that we are avoiding one wave,17 as it were, in our discussion of the law about women, so that we are not altogether swept away when we declare that our male and female guardians must [c] share all their pursuits, and that our argument is somehow self-consistent when it states that this is both viable and beneficial?

 

GLAUCON: It is certainly no small wave that you are avoiding.

 

[5] SOCRATES: You won’t think it is so great when you see the next.

 

GLAUCON: I won’t see it unless you tell me about it.18

 

SOCRATES: The law that is consistent with that one, and with the others that preceded it, is this, I take it.

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: That all these women should be shared among all the men, [10] that no individual woman and man should live together, and that the children, [d] too, should be shared, with no parent knowing its own offspring, and no child its parent.

 

GLAUCON: That wave is far greater and more dubitable than the other, both as regards its viability and its benefit. [5]

 

SOCRATES: As far as its benefit is concerned, at least, I do not think anyone would argue that the sharing of women and children is not the greatest good, if indeed it is viable. But I imagine there would be a lot of dispute about whether or not it is viable.

 

GLAUCON: No, both could very well be disputed. [e]

 

SOCRATES: You mean I will have to face a coalition of arguments. I thought I had at least escaped one of them—namely, whether you thought the proposal was beneficial—and that I would just be left with the argument about whether it is viable or not.

 

GLAUCON: Well, you did not escape unnoticed. So you will have to give an argument for both.

 

SOCRATES: I must pay the penalty. But do me this favor: let me take a holiday and act like those lazy people who make a banquet for themselves of [458a] their own thoughts when they are walking alone. People like that, as you know, do not bother to find out how any of their appetites might actually be fulfilled, so as to avoid the trouble of deliberating about what is possible and what is not. They assume that what they want is available, and then [5] proceed to arrange all the rest, taking pleasure in going through everything they will do when they get it—thus making their already lazy souls even lazier. Well, I, too, am succumbing to this weakness at the moment and [b] want to postpone consideration of the viability of our proposals until later. I will assume now that they are viable, if you will permit me to do so, and examine how the rulers will arrange them when they come to pass. And I will try to show that, if they were put into practice, they would be the most beneficial arrangements of all, both for the city and for its guardians. These [5] are the things I will try to examine with you first, leaving the others for later—if indeed you will permit this.

 

GLAUCON: You have my permission; so proceed with the examination.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, I imagine that if indeed our rulers, and likewise their auxiliaries, are worthy of their names, the latter will be prepared to [c] carry out orders, and the former to give orders, obeying our laws in some cases and imitating them in the others that we leave to their discretion.

 

GLAUCON: Probably so. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Now, you are their lawgiver, and in just the way you selected these men, you will select as the women to hand over to them those who have natures as similar to theirs as possible. And because they have shared dwellings and meals, and none of them has any private property of that [d] sort, they will live together; and through mixing together in the gymnasia and in the rest of their daily life, they will be driven by innate necessity, I take it, to have sex with one another. Or don’t you think I am talking about necessities here?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Not geometric necessities, certainly, but erotic ones; and they probably have a sharper capacity to persuade and attract most people.

 

SOCRATES: They do, indeed. But the next point, Glaucon, is that for them to have unregulated sexual intercourse with one another, or to do anything else of that sort, would not be a pious thing in a city of happy [e] people, and the rulers won’t allow it.

 

GLAUCON: No, it would not be just.

 

SOCRATES: It is clear, then, that we will next have to make marriages as sacred as possible. And sacred marriages will be those that are most beneficial.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: How, then, will the most beneficial ones come about? Tell me [459a] this, Glaucon. I see you have hunting dogs and quite a flock of noble birds at home.19 Have you, by Zeus, noticed anything in particular about their [5] “marriages” and breeding?

 

GLAUCON: Like what?

 

SOCRATES: In the first place, though they are all noble animals, aren’t there some that are, or turn out to be, the very best?

 

GLAUCON: There are.

 

SOCRATES: Do you breed from them all to the same extent, then, or do [10] you try hard to breed as far as possible from the best ones?

 

GLAUCON: From the best ones.

 

[b] SOCRATES: And do you breed from the youngest, the oldest, or as far as possible from those in their prime?

 

GLAUCON: From those in their prime.

 

SOCRATES: And if they were not bred in this way, do you think that your [5] race of birds and dogs would get much worse?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: And what do you think about horses and other animals? Is the situation any different with them?

 

GLAUCON: It would be strange if it were.

 

SOCRATES: Good heavens, my dear comrade! Then our need for eminent [10] rulers is quite desperate, if indeed the same also holds for the human race.

 

GLAUCON: Well, it does hold of them. But so what? [c]

 

SOCRATES: It follows that our rulers will then have to employ a great many drugs. You know that when people do not need drugs for their bodies, and they are prepared to follow a regimen, we regard even an inferior doctor as adequate. But when drugs are needed, we know that a much [5] bolder doctor is required.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true. But what is your point?

 

SOCRATES: This: it looks as though our rulers will have to employ a great many lies and deceptions for the benefit of those they rule. And you remember, I suppose, we said all such things were useful as a kind of drug.20 [d]

 

GLAUCON: And we were correct.

 

SOCRATES: Well, in the case of marriages and procreation, its correctness is particularly evident. [5]

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: It follows from our previous agreement that the best men should mate with the best women in as many cases as possible, while the opposite should hold of the worst men and women; and that the offspring of the former should be reared, but not that of the latter, if our flock is going to be an eminent one. And all this must occur without anyone [e] knowing except the rulers—if, again, our herd of guardians is to remain as free from faction as possible.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: So then, we will have to establish by law certain festivals and [5] sacrifices at which we will bring together brides and bridegrooms, and our poets must compose suitable hymns for the marriages that take place. We [460a] will leave the number of marriages for the rulers to decide. That will enable them to keep the number of males as constant as possible, taking into account war, disease, and everything of that sort; so that the city will, as far as possible, become neither too great nor too small.21 [5]

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: I imagine that some sophisticated lotteries will have to be created, then, so that an inferior person of that sort will blame chance rather than the rulers at each mating time. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And presumably, the young men who are good at war or at [b] other things must—among other prizes and awards—be given a greater opportunity to have sex with the women, in order that a pretext may also be created at the same time for having as many children as possible fathered [5] by such men.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And then, as offspring are born, won’t they be taken by the officials appointed for this purpose, whether these are men or women or [10] both—for surely our offices are also open to both women and men.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose they will take the offspring of good parents to [c] the rearing pen and hand them over to special nurses who live in a separate part of the city. But those of inferior parents, or any deformed offspring of [5] the others, they will hide in a secret and unknown place, as is fitting.22

 

GLAUCON: Yes, if indeed the race of guardians is going to remain pure.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t these nurses also take care of the children’s feeding by bringing the mothers to the rearing pen when their breasts are full, while devising every device23 to ensure that no mother will recognize her [d] offspring? And won’t they provide other women as wet nurses if the mothers themselves have insufficient milk—taking care, however, that the mothers breast-feed the children for only a moderate period of time, and [5] assigning sleepless nights and similar burdens to the nurses and wet nurses?

 

GLAUCON: You are making childbearing a soft job for the guardians’ women.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, properly so. But let’s take up the next thing we proposed.

 

We said, as you know, that offspring should be bred from parents who are [10] in their prime.24

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: Do you agree that a woman’s prime lasts, on average, for a [e] period of twenty years and a man’s for thirty?

 

GLAUCON: Which years are those?

 

SOCRATES: A woman should bear children for the city from the age of twenty to that of forty; whereas a man should beget them for the city from the time that he passes his peak as a runner until he reaches fifty-five.25

 

GLAUCON: At any rate, that is the physical and mental prime for both. [461a]

 

SOCRATES: Then if any male who is younger or older than that engages in reproduction for the community, we will say that his offense is neither pious nor just. For the child he fathers for the city, if it escapes discovery, [5] will be begotten and born without the benefit of sacrifices, or of the prayers that priestesses, priests, and the entire city will offer at every marriage festival, asking that from good and beneficial parents ever better and more beneficial offspring should be produced. On the contrary, it will be [b] born in darkness through a terrible act of lack of self-control.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: The same law will apply if a man who is still of breeding age has sex with a woman in her prime when the rulers have not mated them. [5] We will say that he is imposing an illegitimate, unauthorized, and unholy child on the city.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: But when women and men have passed breeding age, I imagine we will leave them free to have sex with whomever they wish—except that a man may not have sex with his daughter, mother, daughters’ daughters, [c] or mother’s female ancestors, or a woman with her son and his descendants or her father and his ancestors. And we will permit all that only after telling them to be very careful not to let even a single fetus see the light of day, if one should happen to be conceived; but if one does force its way [5] out, they must dispose of it on the understanding that no nurture is available for such a child.

 

GLAUCON: All that sounds reasonable. But how will they recognize one another’s fathers, daughters, and the others you mentioned? [d]

 

SOCRATES: They won’t. Instead, from the day a man becomes a bridegroom, he will call all offspring born in the tenth month afterward (and in the seventh, of course) his sons,26 if they are male, and his daughters, if they [5] are female; and they will call him father. Similarly, he will call their children his grandchildren, and they, in turn, will call the group to which he belongs grandfathers and grandmothers. And those who were born at the same time as their mothers and fathers were breeding, they will call their brothers and [e] sisters. Thus, as we were saying just now, they will avoid sexual relations with each other. However, the law will allow brothers and sisters to have sex with one another, if the lottery works out that way and the Pythia approves.27

 

GLAUCON: You are absolutely right.

 

[5] SOCRATES: That, then, Glaucon, or something like it, is how the sharing of women and children by the guardians of your city will be handled. The next point we need to have confirmed by argument, then, is that this arrangement is both consistent with the rest of the constitution and by far the best. Isn’t that so?

 

[462a] GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, it is.

 

SOCRATES: As a beginning step toward reaching agreement, shouldn’t we ask ourselves what we think is the greatest good for the organization of the city—the one at which the legislator should aim in making its laws—and [5] what the greatest evil? And then examine whether what we have just described is in harmony with the tracks of the good we have found, and in disharmony with those of the bad?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Now, do we know of any greater evil for a city than what tears [b] it apart and makes it many instead of one? Or any greater good than what binds it together and makes it one?

 

GLAUCON: No, we do not.

 

SOCRATES: Well, doesn’t sharing pleasure and pain bind it together—[5] when, as far as possible, all the citizens feel more or less the same joy or pain at the same gains or losses?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, doesn’t the privatization of these things dissolve the city—when some are overwhelmed with distress and others overjoyed [c] by the same things happening to the city or some of its inhabitants?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t that what happens when people do not apply such phrases as “mine” and “not mine” in unison in the city? And similarly with “someone else’s”? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Precisely.

 

SOCRATES: Then isn’t the city that is best governed the one in which the vast majority of people apply “mine” and “not mine” to the same things on the basis of the same principle?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t it the city whose condition is most like that of a single person? I mean, when one of us somehow hurts his finger, you know [10] the entire partnership—the one that binds body and soul together into a single system under the ruling part within it—is aware of this, and all of it as a whole feels the pain in unison with the part that suffers. That is why we [d] say that this person has a pain in his finger. And the same principle applies, doesn’t it, to any other part of a person, whether it is suffering pain or relieved by pleasure? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, the same one. And, to answer your question, the city that manages to come closest to this condition is the best-governed one.

 

SOCRATES: I imagine, then, that whenever one of its citizens has an experience, whether good or bad, such a city will most certainly say that the experience is its own, and all of it together will share his pleasure or pain. [e]

 

GLAUCON: That must be so, since it is well governed.

 

SOCRATES: It is time for us to return to our own city, then, to look there for the features we have agreed on and to see whether it, or rather some [5] other city, possesses them to the greatest degree.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is.

 

SOCRATES: Well, now, what about those other cities? Presumably there are rulers and people in them as well as in ours? [463a]

 

GLAUCON: There are.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t all of them call one another “citizens”?

 

GLAUCON: Of course. [5]

 

SOCRATES: But besides “citizens,” what do the people in those other cities call the rulers?

 

GLAUCON: In most, they call them “masters,” but in democracies they are called just that—“rulers.”28

 

[10] SOCRATES: What about the people in our city? Besides “citizens,” what do they call the rulers?

 

[b] GLAUCON: “Preservers”29 and “auxiliaries.”

 

SOCRATES: And what do they call the people?

 

GLAUCON: “Paymasters” and “providers.”

 

SOCRATES: What do the rulers in other cities call the people?

 

[5] GLAUCON: “Slaves.”

 

SOCRATES: And what do the rulers call each other?

 

GLAUCON: “Co-rulers.”

 

SOCRATES: And ours?

 

GLAUCON: “Co-guardians.”

 

[10] SOCRATES: Now, can you tell me whether a ruler in other cities could address one of his co-rulers as his kinsman and another as an outsider?

 

GLAUCON: Many do, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t he regard and speak of his kinsman as belonging [c] to him, while he regards the outsider as not doing so?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: What about your guardians? Could any of them regard or address a co-guardian as an outsider?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Certainly not. He will regard everyone he meets as a brother or a sister, a father or a mother, a son or a daughter, or some ancestor or descendant of these.

 

SOCRATES: Very well put. But tell me this, too: will your laws require them simply to use these terms of kinship, or must they also do all the [d] things that go along with the names? In the case of fathers, for example, must they show them the customary respect, solicitude, and obedience owed to parents? Will they fare worse at the hands of gods or men, as people [5] whose actions are neither pious nor just, if they do otherwise? Will these be the sayings that are chanted by all the citizens, and that sound in their ears right from their earliest childhood? Or will they hear something else about their fathers—or the ones they are told to regard as their fathers—or about their other relatives?

 

GLAUCON: They will hear those. It would be ridiculous if they only [e] mouthed the terms of kinship, without the actions.

 

SOCRATES: So, in this city more than in any other, when someone is doing well or badly, they will utter in concord the words we mentioned a moment ago, and say “my such-and-such is doing well” or “my so-and-so is doing badly.” [5]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Well, didn’t we say that this conviction and way of talking are [464a] accompanied by the having of pleasures and pains in common?30

 

GLAUCON: Yes, and we were right to do so.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t our citizens share to the fullest, and call “mine,” the very same thing? And because they share it, won’t they experience to [5] the fullest the sharing of pleasures and pains?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And—in the context of the rest of the political system—isn’t the sharing of women and children by the guardians responsible for it?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is by far the most important cause. [10]

 

SOCRATES: But we further agreed that this sharing is the greatest good for a city, when we compared a well-governed city to the way a human body [b] relates to pain and pleasure in one of its parts.

 

GLAUCON: And we were right to agree.

 

SOCRATES: Then we have shown that the cause of the greatest good for our city is the sharing of women and children by the auxiliaries. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we certainly have.

 

SOCRATES: And what is more, it is consistent with what we said before. For we said, as you know, that if these people are going to be real guardians, they should not have private houses, land, or any other possession, but should receive their upkeep from the other citizens as a wage for their [c] guardianship, and should all eat communally.31

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: So, as I say, doesn’t what was said earlier, as well as what is [5] being said now, make them into even better guardians and prevent them from tearing the city apart by applying the term “mine” not to the same thing, but to different ones—with one person dragging into his own house whatever he, apart from the others, can get his hands on, and another into a different house to a different wife and children, who create private pleasures [d] and pains at things that are private? Instead of that, don’t our guardians share a single conviction about what is their own, aim at the same goal, and, as far as possible, feel pleasure and pain in unison? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: What about lawsuits and accusations? Won’t they pretty much disappear from among them because they have no private possessions except their own bodies and share all the rest? As a result, won’t they be free from faction—at any rate, from the sort of faction that the possession of [e] property, children, and families causes among people?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they will inevitably be entirely free of it.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, lawsuits neither for violence nor for assault should justifiably occur among them. For we will declare, surely, that for people to [5] defend themselves against others of the same age is a fine and just thing, since it will compel them to stay in good physical shape.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

[465a] SOCRATES: This law is also correct for another reason: if a spirited person vents his anger in this way, he will be less likely to move on to more serious sorts of faction.

 

GLAUCON: He certainly will.

 

SOCRATES: As for an older person, he will be authorized to rule and punish [5] all the younger ones.

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And, unless the rulers command it, it is unlikely that a younger person will ever employ any sort of violence against an older one, or strike him. And I do not imagine he will fail to show him respect in other ways [10] either, since two guardians—fear and shame—are sufficient to prevent it. Shame will prevent him from laying a hand on his parents, as will the fear that [b] the others would come to his victim’s aid—some because they are his sons, some because they are his brothers, and some because they are his fathers.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that is what would happen.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t the laws induce men to live at peace with one [5] another in all respects?

 

GLAUCON: Very much so.

 

SOCRATES: And if there is no faction among the guardians, there is no terrible danger that the rest of the city will form factions, either against them [10] or among themselves.

 

GLAUCON: No, there is not.

 

SOCRATES: As for the pettiest of the evils the guardians would escape, they are so unseemly, I hesitate even to mention them: the flatteries of the rich [c] by the poor; the perplexities and sufferings involved in bringing up children; the need to make the money necessary to feed the household—the borrowings, the defaults, and all the things people have to do to provide an [5] income to hand over to their wives and slaves to spend on housekeeping. The various troubles men endure in these areas, my dear Glaucon, are obvious, quite demeaning, and not worth discussing.

 

GLAUCON: They are obvious even to the blind. [d]

 

SOCRATES: They will escape from all these things, then, and live a more blessedly happy life than the most blessedly happy one—that of the victors in the Olympian games.

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: Surely, these victors are considered happy on account of only a small part of what the guardians possess, since the latter victory is even [5] finer, and their upkeep from public funds more complete.32 After all, the victory they gain is the salvation of the whole city, and the crown of victory they and their children receive is their upkeep and all the necessities of life. They receive privileges from their own city during their lifetime and a [e] worthy burial after their death.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, those are very fine rewards.

 

SOCRATES: Now, do you remember that earlier in our discussion we were rebuked by an argument—I forget whose—to the effect that we had not made our guardians happy, that though it was possible for them to have [5] everything that belongs to the citizens, they actually had nothing? We said, [466a] didn’t we, that if this happened to come up at some point, we would look into it then, but that our concern at the time was to make our guardians guardians, and to make the city the happiest possible, rather than looking to any one group within it and molding it for happiness?33 [5]

 

GLAUCON: I remember.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if indeed the life of our auxiliaries has been shown to be much finer and better than that of Olympian victors, is there any need to compare it with the lives of shoemakers or any other craftsmen, or [b] with that of the farmers?

 

GLAUCON: I do not think there is.

 

SOCRATES: Nevertheless, it is surely right to repeat here what I also said on that earlier occasion: if a guardian tries to become happy in such a way [5] that he is no longer a guardian at all, and is not satisfied with a life that is moderate, stable, and (we claim) best, but is seized by a foolish, adolescent belief about happiness, which incites him to use his power to take everything in the city for himself—he will come to realize the true wisdom of [c] Hesiod’s saying that, in a sense, “the half is worth more than the whole.”34

 

[5] GLAUCON: If he takes my advice, he will keep to the former life.

 

SOCRATES: Do you agree, then, that the women should share with the men, in the way we described, in the areas of education, children, and guarding the other citizens; that whether they remain in the city or go out to war, they must guard together and hunt together, as hounds do, and [d] share everything to the extent possible; and that by behaving in this way, they will be doing what is best, not something contrary to the natural relationship of female to male, and the one they are most naturally fitted to share in with one another?

 

[5] GLAUCON: I do agree.

 

SOCRATES: Then doesn’t it remain for us to determine whether it is also possible among human beings, as it is among other animals, for this sort of sharing to come about, and if so, how?

 

GLAUCON: You took the words out of my mouth.

 

SOCRATES: As far as war is concerned, I think it is clear how they will [e] wage it.

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: They will go to war together. What is more, they will take the children with them to the war, when they are sturdy enough, so that, like the children of other craftsmen, they can see what they will have to do in their own craft when they are grown up. But in addition to observing, they [467a] should help and assist in every aspect of war, and take care of their mothers and fathers. For haven’t you noticed in the other crafts how the children of potters, for example, assist and watch for a long time before actually putting [5] their hands to the clay?

 

GLAUCON: I have, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Well, should these people take more care than the guardians in training their children by appropriate experience and observation?

 

GLAUCON: Of course not. That would be completely ridiculous.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Besides, every animal will fight better in the presence of its [b] young.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right. But there is a risk, Socrates, and not a small one either, that in the event of a disaster of the sort that is likely to happen in a war, they will lose their children’s lives as well as their own, making it impossible for the rest of the city to recover.

 

SOCRATES: That’s true. But, in the first place, do you think they should arrange for the avoidance of all risk?

 

GLAUCON: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if they must face some risk, shouldn’t it be one in which they will be improved by success?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly. [10]

 

SOCRATES: But you think, do you, that it makes little difference—and so is not worth the risk—whether or not men who are going to be warriors [c] watch warfare when they are still boys?

 

GLAUCON: No, it does make a difference to what you are talking about.

 

SOCRATES: Starting from the assumption, then, that we are to make the children observers of war, we must further devise some way of keeping [5] them safe. Then everything will be fine, won’t it?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Well, in the first place, their fathers won’t be ignorant, will they, but rather as knowledgeable as people can be, about which military campaigns are dangerous and which are not? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Presumably so.

 

SOCRATES: So, they will take the children on the latter, but be wary of taking them on the former.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And they will not put the worst people in charge of them, I presume, but those whose experience and age qualifies them to be leaders [5] and tutors.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that would be proper.

 

SOCRATES: But we will say that the unexpected happens to many people and on many occasions. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: So, with that in mind, my friend, we must provide the young children with wings at the outset, so that, if the need arises, they can fly away and escape.

 

GLAUCON: What do you mean? [e]

 

SOCRATES: We must mount them on horses when they are still very young, and when they have been taught to ride, they must be taken to view the fighting, not on spirited or aggressive horses, but on the fastest and most manageable ones. In this way, they will get the best view of their own [5] future job, and will be able to make the safest escape, if the need arises, by following their older leaders.

 

GLAUCON: I think you are right.

 

SOCRATES: What about warfare itself? How should your soldiers behave [468a] toward one another and the enemy? Are my views correct or not?

 

GLAUCON: Tell me what they are.

 

[5] SOCRATES: If one of them leaves his post, throws away his shield, or does anything else of that sort out of cowardice, shouldn’t he be demoted to craftsman or farmer?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And if anyone is captured alive by the enemy, shouldn’t he be [10] presented to his captors as a catch to use however they wish?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: But if someone distinguishes himself and earns high honors, do you or don’t you think that in the first place, while still on campaign, he should be crowned in turn by each of the adolescents and children who are [5] with the army?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: What about shaking him by the right hand?

 

GLAUCON: That too.

 

SOCRATES: But I do not imagine you would go so far as this.

 

[5] GLAUCON: As what?

 

SOCRATES: That he should kiss, and be kissed by, each of them.

 

GLAUCON: By all means. And I would add to the law that while they are still on campaign, no one he wants to kiss shall be allowed to refuse, so that [c] if anyone passionately loves another, whether male or female, he will try harder to win the prize for bravery.

 

SOCRATES: Excellent! For we have already mentioned that more opportunities [5] for marriage will be available for a good man,35 and that men like him will be selected more often than others for such things, so that as many children as possible may be produced from them.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we did mention that.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, according to Homer too, it is just to honor in such ways those young people who are good. For Homer says that when Ajax [d] distinguished himself in battle, he “was rewarded with the whole backbone,”36 since he considered that to be an appropriate honor for a courageous young man because it honored him and built up his strength at the [5] same time.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: Then we will follow Homer in this matter, at any rate. I mean that at sacrifices and all other such occasions, we too will honor good men—insofar as they have exhibited their goodness—not only with hymns and all the other things we mentioned, but also with “seats of honor, cuts of [10] meats, and well-filled cups of wine,”37 so that while honoring our good men and women, we may train them at the same time. e

 

GLAUCON: That’s an excellent idea.

 

SOCRATES: All right. And if any of those who died while on campaign has had a particularly distinguished death, won’t we, in the first place, declare that he belongs to the golden race?38 [5]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t we believe with Hesiod that, whenever any of that race die, they become “unsullied daimons living upon the earth, noble [469a] beings, protectors against evil, guardians of articulate mortals?”39

 

GLAUCON: We will certainly believe that.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t we ask the god,40 then, to tell us how and with what distinction these daimons, these godlike people, should be buried, and perform their burial in whatever way he prescribes? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And for the remainder of time, won’t we regard their graves as those of daimons, and take care of them and worship at them? And won’t we follow these same rites whenever anyone who has been judged outstandingly [b] good throughout his life dies of old age, or in some other way?

 

GLAUCON: It would be just to do so, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: Now, what about enemies? How will our soldiers behave toward them? [5]

 

GLAUCON: In what respect?

 

SOCRATES: First, as regards enslavement, do you think it is just for Greek cities to enslave other Greeks, or should they try as hard as possible not even to allow other cities to do so, and make a habit of sparing the Greek [10] race as a precaution against being enslaved by barbarians? [c]

 

GLAUCON: Sparing them is by far the best course.

 

SOCRATES: So, they should not possess any Greek slaves themselves, and should advise the other Greeks to do the same? [5]

 

GLAUCON: By all means. In that way, at any rate, they would be more likely to turn against the barbarians and keep their hands off one another.

 

SOCRATES: What about despoiling the dead? Is it a good thing to strip the dead of anything besides their armor after a victory? Doesn’t it give cowards [d] a pretext for not facing the enemy, since when they are greedily bending over corpses, they will be performing an important duty? And haven’t many armies been lost because of such plundering?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you think it is illiberal and money-loving to strip a corpse? And isn’t it small-minded and womanish to regard a dead body as your enemy, when the enemy himself has flitted away leaving behind only the instrument with which he fought? Do you think that people who do this are any different from dogs who get angry with the stones thrown at [e] them but leave the person throwing them alone?

 

GLAUCON: No different at all.

 

SOCRATES: So they should not strip corpses, should they, or refuse the [5] enemy permission to pick up their dead?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, they certainly should not.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we surely won’t take weapons to the temples as offerings, and if we care anything about the goodwill of other Greeks, we [470a] especially won’t do this with Greek weapons. On the contrary, we would even be afraid of polluting41 the temples if we brought them such things from our own race, unless, of course, the god ordains otherwise.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

[5] SOCRATES: What about ravaging Greek land and burning Greek houses? How will your soldiers behave toward their enemies?

 

GLAUCON: I would like to hear what you believe about that.

 

SOCRATES: Well, I believe they should do neither of these things, but [b] destroy only the year’s harvest. Do you want me to tell you why?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: It seems to me that just as we have the two names “war” and “faction,” so there are also two things, and the names apply to differences [5] between the two. The two I mean are, on the one hand, what is one’s own and kin, and, on the other, what is foreign and strange. “Faction” applies to hostility toward one’s own, “war” to hostility toward strangers.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, there is nothing wrong with that claim.

 

[c] SOCRATES: Consider, then, whether this too is correct. I say that the Greek race, in relation to itself, is its own and kin, but, in relation to barbarians, is strange and foreign.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: When Greeks fight with barbarians, then, or barbarians with Greeks, we will say that that is warfare, that they are natural enemies, and [5] that such hostilities should be called war. But when Greeks engage in such things with Greeks, we will say they are natural friends, that Greece is sick and divided into factions in such a situation, and that such hostilities should be called faction. [d]

 

GLAUCON: I, for one, agree to think that way.

 

SOCRATES: Now, notice that whenever something of the sort that is currently called faction occurs and a city is divided, if each side devastates the land and burns the houses of the other, the faction is thought abominable [5] and neither party is thought to love the city—otherwise they would never have dared to ravage their own nurse and mother.42 But it is thought reasonable for the ones who have proved stronger to carry off the weaker ones’ crops, and to have the attitude of mind of people who will one day be reconciled [e] and won’t always be at war.

 

GLAUCON: That attitude of mind is far more civilized than the other.

 

SOCRATES: What about the city you are founding? Won’t it be Greek? [5]

 

GLAUCON: It will have to be.

 

SOCRATES: So won’t its citizens be good and civilized people?

 

GLAUCON: Indeed, they will.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t they be lovers of Greeks? Won’t they consider Greece as their own and share the same religious festivals as other Greeks? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t they regard their conflicts with Greeks—their own people—as faction, and not even use the name “war”? [471a]

 

GLAUCON: No, they won’t use it.

 

SOCRATES: And so, they will quarrel with the aim of being reconciled, won’t they?

 

GLAUCON: Of course. [5]

 

SOCRATES: They will discipline their foes in a friendly spirit, then, and not punish them with enslavement and destruction, since they are discipliners, not enemies.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: As Greeks, then, they won’t devastate Greece or burn its houses, nor will they agree that all the inhabitants in any city—men, women, and children—are their enemies, but only those few responsible for the conflict. For all these reasons, they won’t be willing to devastate [b] their country, since the majority of the inhabitants are their friends, nor destroy the houses, and they will pursue the conflict only to the point at which those responsible are forced to pay the penalty by the innocent ones [5] who are suffering painfully.

 

GLAUCON: I agree that this is how our citizens should treat their enemies, but they should treat barbarians the way Greeks currently treat each other.

 

SOCRATES: Then shall we also establish this law for the guardians, that [c] they should neither ravage Greek land nor burn Greek houses?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, let’s establish it. And let’s assume that this law and its predecessors are right. But, Socrates, I think that if you are allowed to go on talking about this sort of thing, you will never remember the topic you set [5] aside in order to say all this—namely, whether it is possible for this constitution to come into existence, and how it could ever do so. I agree that if it came into existence, everything would be lovely for the city that had it. I will even add some advantages that you have left out: they would fight excellently against their enemies because they would be least likely to [d] desert each other. After all, they recognize each other as brothers, fathers, and sons, and call each other by those names. And if the women, too, joined in their campaigns, either stationed in the same ranks or in the rear, [5] either to strike terror in the enemy or to provide support should the need ever arise, I know that this would make them quite unbeatable. And I also see all the good things they would have at home that you have omitted. [e] Take it for granted that I agree that all these benefits, as well as innumerable others, would result, if this constitution came into existence, and say no more about it. Instead, let’s now try to convince ourselves of just this: that it is possible and how it is possible, and let’s leave the rest aside.

 

[472a] SOCRATES: All of a sudden, you have practically assaulted my argument and lost all sympathy for my holding back. Perhaps you do not realize that just as I have barely escaped from the first two waves of objections, you are now bringing the greatest and most difficult of the three down upon me.43 [5] When you see and hear it, you will have complete sympathy and recognize that I had good reason after all for hesitating and for being afraid to state and try to examine so paradoxical an argument.

 

GLAUCON: The more you talk like that, the less we will let you get away [b] without explaining how this constitution could come into existence. So explain it, and do not delay any further.

 

SOCRATES: The first thing to recall, then, is that it was our inquiry into [5] the nature of justice and injustice that brought us to this point.

 

GLAUCON: True. But what of it?

 

SOCRATES: Oh, nothing. However, if we discover the nature of justice, should we also expect the just man not to differ from justice itself in any way, but, on the contrary, to have entirely the same nature it does? Or will we be satisfied if he approximates as closely as possible to it and partakes in [c] it far more than anyone else?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we will be satisfied with that.

 

SOCRATES: So, it was in order to have a model that we were inquiring into the nature of justice itself and of the completely just man, supposing he [5] could exist, and what he would be like if he did; and similarly with injustice and the most unjust man. We thought that by seeing how they seemed to us to stand with regard to happiness and its opposite, we would also be compelled to agree about ourselves as well: that the one who was most like them would have a fate most like theirs. But we were not doing this in [d] order to demonstrate that it is possible for these men to exist.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think, then, that someone would be any less good a painter if he painted a model of what the most beautiful human being would be like, and rendered everything in the picture perfectly well, but [5] could not demonstrate that such a man could actually exist?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: What about our own case, then? Weren’t we trying, as we put it, to produce a model in our discussion of a good city?44 [e]

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: So, do you think that our discussion will be any less satisfactory if we cannot demonstrate that it is possible to found a city that is the same as the one we described in speech?

 

GLAUCON: Not at all. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then that is the truth of the matter. But if, in order to please you, we must do our best to demonstrate how, and under what condition, this would be most possible, you must again grant me the same points for the purposes of that demonstration.

 

GLAUCON: Which ones? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Is it possible for anything to be carried out exactly as described in speech, or is it natural for practice to have less of a grasp of truth than [473a] speech does, even if some people do not think so? Do you agree with this or not?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Then do not compel me to demonstrate it as coming about in practice exactly as we have described it in speech. Rather, if we are able to discover how a city that most closely approximates to what we have described could be founded, you must admit that we have discovered how [b] all you have prescribed could come about.45 Or wouldn’t you be satisfied with that? I certainly would.

 

GLAUCON: Me, too.

 

SOCRATES: Then next, it seems, we should try to discover and show what is badly done in cities nowadays that prevents them from being managed our way, and what the smallest change would be that would enable a city to arrive at our sort of constitution—preferably one change; otherwise, two; otherwise, the fewest in number and the least extensive in effect.

 

[c] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Well, there is one change we could point to that I think would accomplish this. It certainly is not small or easy, but it is possible.

 

[5] GLAUCON: What is it?

 

SOCRATES: I am now about to confront what we likened to the greatest wave. Yet, it must be stated, even if it is going to drown me in a wave of outright ridicule and contempt, as it were. So listen to what I am about to say.

 

GLAUCON: Say it.

 

SOCRATES: Until philosophers rule as kings in their cities, or those who are nowadays called kings and leading men become genuine and adequate [d] philosophers so that political power and philosophy become thoroughly blended together, while the numerous natures that now pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest [5] from evils, my dear Glaucon, nor, I think, will the human race. And until that happens, the same constitution we have now described in our discussion [e] will never be born to the extent that it can, or see the light of the sun. It is this claim that has made me hesitate to speak for so long. I saw how very unbelievable it would sound, since it is difficult to accept that there [5] can be no happiness, either public or private, in any other city.

 

GLAUCON: Socrates, what a speech, what an argument you have let burst with! But now that you have uttered it, you must expect that a great many people—and not undistinguished ones either—will immediately throw off [474a] their cloaks and, stripped for action, snatch any available weapon and make a headlong rush at you, determined to do terrible things to you. So, if you do not defend yourself by argument and escape, you really will pay the penalty of general derision.

 

SOCRATES: But aren’t you the one who is responsible for this happening to me? [5]

 

GLAUCON: And I was right to do it. Still, I won’t desert you. On the contrary, I will defend you in any way I can. And what I can do is provide good will and encouragement, and maybe give you more careful answers to your questions than someone else. So, with the promise of this sort of assistance, try to demonstrate to the unbelievers that things are as you claim. [b]

 

SOCRATES: I will have to, especially when you agree to be so great an ally! If we are going to escape from the people you mention, I think we need to define for them who the philosophers are that we dare to say should rule; [5] so that once that is clear, one can defend oneself by showing that some people are fitted by nature to engage in philosophy and to take the lead in a [c] city, while there are others who should not engage in it, but should follow a leader.

 

GLAUCON: This would be a good time to define them.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, follow me on the path I am about to take, to see if it somehow leads to an adequate explanation. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Lead on.

 

SOCRATES: Do I have to remind you, or do you recall, that when we say someone loves something, if the description is correct, it must be clear not just that he loves some part of it but not another; but, on the contrary, that he cherishes the whole of it?46 [10]

 

GLAUCON: You will have to remind me, it seems. I do not recall the point at all. [d]

 

SOCRATES: I did not expect you to give that response, Glaucon. A passionate man should not forget that all boys in the bloom of youth somehow manage to sting and arouse a passionate lover of boys, and seem to merit his [5] attention and passionate devotion. Isn’t that the way you people behave to beautiful boys? One, because he is snub-nosed, you will praise as “cute;” another who is hook-nosed you will say is “regal;” while the one in the middle you say is “well proportioned.” Dark ones look “manly,” and pale [e] ones are “children of the gods.” As for the “honey-colored,” do you think that this very term is anything but the euphemistic coinage of a lover who found it easy to tolerate a sallow complexion, provided it was accompanied by the bloom of youth? In a word, you people find any excuse, and use any [5] expression, to avoid rejecting anyone whose flower is in full bloom. [475a]

 

GLAUCON: If you insist on taking me as your example of what passionate men do, I will go along with you . . . for the sake of argument!

 

SOCRATES: What about lovers of wine? Don’t you observe them behaving [5] in just the same way? Don’t they find any excuse to indulge their passionate devotion to wine of any sort?

 

GLAUCON: They do, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And you also observe, I imagine, that if honor-lovers cannot become generals, they serve as lieutenants,47 and if they cannot be honored [10] by important people and dignitaries, they are satisfied with being honored [b] by insignificant and inferior ones, since it is honor as a whole of which they are desirers.

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: Then do you affirm this or not? When we say that someone has an appetite for something, are we to say that he has an appetite for [5] everything of that kind, or for one part of it but not another?

 

GLAUCON: Everything.

 

SOCRATES: Then in the case of the philosopher, too, won’t we say that he has an appetite for wisdom—not for one part and not another, but for all of it?

 

[10] GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: So, if someone is choosy about what he learns, especially if he [c] is young and does not have a rational grasp of what is useful and what is not, we won’t say that he is a lover of learning or a philosopher—any more than we would say that someone who is choosy about his food is famished, or has an appetite for food, or is a lover of food rather than a picky eater.

 

[5] GLAUCON: And we would be right not to say it.

 

SOCRATES: But someone who is ready and willing to taste every kind of learning, who turns gladly to learning and is insatiable for it, he is the one we would be justified in calling a philosopher. Isn’t that so?

 

[d] GLAUCON: In that case, many strange people will be philosophers! I mean, all the lovers of seeing are what they are, I imagine, because they take pleasure in learning things. And the lovers of listening are very strange people to include as philosophers: they would never willingly attend a serious discussion [5] or spend their time that way; yet, just as if their ears were under contract to listen to every chorus, they run around to all the Dionysiac festivals, whether in cities or villages, and never miss one. Are we to say that these people—and others who are students of similar things or of petty [e] crafts—are philosophers?

 

SOCRATES: Not at all, but they are like philosophers.

 

GLAUCON: Who do you think, then, are the true ones?

 

SOCRATES: The lovers of seeing the truth.

 

GLAUCON: That, too, is no doubt correct,48 but what exactly do you mean by it? [5]

 

SOCRATES: It would not be easy to explain to someone else. But you, I imagine, will agree to the following.

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: That since beautiful is the opposite of ugly, they are two things.

 

GLAUCON: Of course. [476a]

 

SOCRATES: And since they are two things, each of them is also one?

 

GLAUCON: That’s true too.

 

SOCRATES: And the same argument applies, then, to just and unjust, good and bad, and all the forms: each of them is itself one thing, but because [5] they appear all over the place in partnership with actions and bodies, and with one another, each of them appears to be many things.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is the basis of the distinction I draw: on one side are the lovers of seeing, the lovers of crafts, and the practical people [10] you mentioned a moment ago; on the other, those we are arguing about, the only ones it is correct to call philosophers. [b]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The lovers of listening and seeing are passionately devoted to beautiful sounds, colors, shapes, and everything fashioned out of such [5] things.49 But their thought is unable to see the nature of the beautiful itself things. or to be passionately devoted to it.

 

GLAUCON: That’s certainly true.

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, won’t those who are able to approach the beautiful itself, and see it by itself, be rare? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Very. [c]

 

SOCRATES: What about someone who believes in beautiful things but does not believe in the beautiful itself, and would not be able to follow anyone who tried to lead him to the knowledge of it? Do you think he is living in a dream, or is he awake? Just consider. Isn’t it dreaming to think—[5] whether asleep or awake—that a likeness is not a likeness, but rather the thing itself that it is like?

 

GLAUCON: I certainly think that someone who does that is dreaming.

 

SOCRATES: But what about someone who, to take the opposite case, does believe in the beautiful itself, is able to observe both it and the things that [d] participate in it, and does not think that the participants are it, or that it is the participants—do you think he is living in a dream or is awake?

 

GLAUCON: He is very much awake.

 

[5] SOCRATES: So, because this person knows these things, we would be right to describe his thought as knowledge; but the other’s we would be right to describe as belief, because he believes what he does?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: What if the person we describe as believing but not knowing is angry with us and disputes the truth of what we say? Will we have any [e] way of soothing and gently persuading him, while disguising the fact that he is not in a healthy state of mind?

 

GLAUCON: We certainly need one, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, consider what we will say to him. Or—once [5] we have told him that nobody envies him any knowledge he may have—that, on the contrary, we would be delighted to discover that he knows something—do you want us to question him as follows? “Tell us this: does someone who knows know something or nothing?” You answer for him.

 

GLAUCON: I will answer that he knows something.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Something that is50 or something that is not?

 

[477a] GLAUCON: That is. How could something that is not be known?

 

SOCRATES: We are adequately assured of this, then, and would remain so, no matter how many ways we examined it: what is completely is completely an object of knowledge and what is in no way at all is an object of ignorance.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Most adequately.

 

SOCRATES: Good. In that case, then, if anything is such as to be and also not to be, wouldn’t it lie in between what purely is and what in no way is?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, in between them.

 

SOCRATES: Then, since knowledge deals with what is, ignorance must deal with what is not, while we must look in between knowledge and [10] ignorance for what deals with what lies in between, if there is anything of [b] that sort.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, then, do we think there is such a thing as belief?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Is it a different power from knowledge, or the same? [5]

 

GLAUCON: A different one.

 

SOCRATES: So, belief has been assigned to deal with one thing, then, and knowledge with another, depending on what power each has.

 

GLAUCON: Right.

 

SOCRATES: Now, doesn’t knowledge naturally deal with what is, to know [10] how what is is? But first I think we had better go through the following.

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: We think powers are a type of thing that enables us—or anything [c] else that has an ability—to do whatever we are able to do. Sight and hearing are examples of what I mean by powers, if you understand the kind of thing I am trying to describe.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Listen, then, to what I think about them. A power has no color for me to see, nor a shape, nor any feature of the sort that many other things have, and that I can consider in order to distinguish them for myself as different from one another. In the case of a power, I can consider only what it deals with and what it does, and it is on that basis that I come to call [d] each the power it is: those assigned to deal with the same things and do the same, I call the same; those that deal with different things and do different things, I call different. What about you? What do you do? [5]

 

GLAUCON: The same.

 

SOCRATES: Going back, then, to where we left off, my very good fellow: do you think knowledge is itself a power? Or to what type would you assign it?

 

GLAUCON: To that one. It is the most effective power of all.

 

SOCRATES: What about belief? Shall we include it as a power or assign it to a different kind? [e]

 

GLAUCON: Not at all. Belief is nothing other than the power that enables us to believe.

 

SOCRATES: But a moment ago you agreed that knowledge and belief are not the same. [5]

 

GLAUCON: How could anyone with any sense think a fallible thing is the same as an infallible one?

 

SOCRATES: Fine. Then clearly we agree that belief is different from knowledge. [478a]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is different.

 

SOCRATES: Each of them, then, since it has a different power, deals by nature with something different?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: Surely knowledge deals with what is, to know what is as it is?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Whereas belief, we say, believes?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: The very same thing that knowledge knows? Can the object [10] of knowledge and the object of belief be the same? Or is that impossible?

 

GLAUCON: It is impossible, given what we have agreed. If different powers by nature deal with different things, and both opinion and knowledge are [b] powers but, as we claim, different ones, it follows from these that the object of knowledge and the object of belief cannot be the same.

 

SOCRATES: Then if what is is the object of knowledge, mustn’t the object of belief be something other than what is?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, it must be something different.

 

SOCRATES: Does belief, then, believe what is not? Or is it impossible even to believe what is not? Consider this: doesn’t a believer take his belief to deal with something? Or is it possible to believe, yet to believe nothing?

 

GLAUCON: No, it is impossible.

 

[10] SOCRATES: In fact, there is some single thing that a believer believes?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: But surely what is not is most correctly characterized not as a [c] single thing, but as nothing?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But we had to assign ignorance to what is not and knowledge to what is?

[5] GLAUCON: Correct.

 

SOCRATES: So belief neither believes what is nor what is not?

 

GLAUCON: No, it does not.

 

SOCRATES: Then belief cannot be either ignorance or knowledge?

 

GLAUCON: Apparently not.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Well, then, does it lie beyond these two, surpassing knowledge in clarity or ignorance in opacity?

 

GLAUCON: No, it does neither.

 

SOCRATES: Then does belief seem to you to be more opaque than knowledge but clearer than ignorance?

 

GLAUCON: Very much so. [15]

 

SOCRATES: It lies within the boundaries determined by them? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So belief will lie in between the two?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Now, didn’t we say earlier that if something turned out both [5] to be and not to be at the same time, it would lie in between what purely is and what in every way is not, and that neither knowledge nor ignorance would deal with it; but whatever it was again that turned out to lie in between ignorance and knowledge would?

 

GLAUCON: Correct. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And now, what we are calling belief has turned out to lie in between them?

 

GLAUCON: It has.

 

SOCRATES: Apparently, then, it remains for us to find what partakes in [e] both being and not being, and cannot correctly be called purely one or the other, so that if we find it, we can justifiably call it the object of belief, thereby assigning extremes to extremes and in-betweens to in-betweens. Isn’t that so? [5]

 

GLAUCON: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Now that all that has been established, I want him to tell me this—the excellent fellow who believes that there is no beautiful itself, no form of beauty itself that remains always the same in all respects, but who [479a] does believe that there are many beautiful things—I mean, that lover of seeing who cannot bear to hear anyone say that the beautiful is one thing, or the just, or any of the rest—I want him to answer this question: “My very good fellow,” we will say, “of all the many beautiful things, is there one that [5] won’t also seem ugly? Or any just one that won’t seem unjust? Or any pious one that won’t seem impious?”

 

GLAUCON: There is not. On the contrary, it is inevitable that they would somehow seem both beautiful and ugly; and the same with the other things [b] you asked about.

 

SOCRATES: What about the many things that are doubles? Do they seem to be any the less halves than doubles?

 

GLAUCON: No. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And again, will things that we say are great, small, light, or heavy be any more what we say they are than they will be the opposite?

 

GLAUCON: No, each of them is always both.

 

SOCRATES: Then is each of the many things any more what one says it is [10] than it is not what one says it is?

 

GLAUCON: No, they are like those puzzles one hears at parties, or the children’s [c] riddle about the eunuch who threw something at a bat—the one about what he threw at it and what it was in.51 For these things, too, are ambiguous, and one cannot understand them as fixedly being or fixedly not [5] being, or as both, or as neither.

 

SOCRATES: Do you know what to do with them, then, or anywhere better to put them than in between being and not being? Surely they cannot be more opaque than what is not, by not-being more than it; nor clearer [d] than what is, by being more than it.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: So, we have now discovered, it seems, that the masses’ many conventional norms concerning beauty and the rest are somehow [5] rolling around between what is not and what purely is.52

 

GLAUCON: We have.

 

SOCRATES: And we agreed earlier that if anything turned out to be of that sort, it would have to be called an object of belief, not an object of knowledge—a wandering, in-between object grasped by the in-between power.

 

[10] GLAUCON: We did.

 

SOCRATES: As for those, then, who look at many beautiful things but do [e] not see the beautiful itself, and are incapable of following another who would lead them to it; or many just things but not the just itself, and similarly with all the rest—these people, we will say, have beliefs about all these [5] things, but have no knowledge of what their beliefs are about.

 

GLAUCON: That is what we would have to say.

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, what about those who in each case look at the things themselves that are always the same in every respect? Won’t we say that they have knowledge, not mere belief?

 

GLAUCON: Once again, we would have to.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we say, then, that these people are passionately devoted to and love the things with which knowledge deals, as the others are [10] devoted to and love the things with which belief deals? We have not forgotten, [480a] have we, that the latter love and look at beautiful sounds, colors, and things of that sort, but cannot even bear the idea that the beautiful itself is a thing that is?

 

GLAUCON: No, we have not. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Will we be striking a false note,53 then, if we call such people “philodoxers” (lovers of belief) rather than “philosophers” (lovers of wisdom or knowledge)? Will they be very angry with us if we call them that?

 

GLAUCON: Not if they take my advice. It is not in accord with divine law to be angry with the truth. [10]

 

SOCRATES: So, those who in each case are passionately devoted to the thing itself are the ones we must call, not “philodoxers,” but “philosophers”?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

1 This task is taken up in Book 8.

2 See 423e4–424a2.

3 A proverbial expression applied to those who neglect the task at hand for an uncertain profit. Thrasymachus is reminding Socrates of his own words at 336e4–9.

4 This may be an allusion to the mimes of Sophron of Syracuse (c. 470–400 BCE), which were divided into male mimes, in which men were represented, and female ones, in which women were represented.

5 Respectable, well-to-do women lived secluded lives in most Greek states: they were confined to the household (see 579b8) and to domestic work and were largely excluded from the public spheres of culture, politics, and warfare. See John Gould, “Law, Custom and Myth: Aspects of the Social Position of Women in Classical Athens,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 100 (1980): 38–59.

6 The women will be gumnozomenas, which can mean stripped naked, but often also means wearing a tunic, or undergarment, without a cloak (see 457a6–7). A palestra was a wrestling school and training ground.

7 A reference, perhaps, to Aristophanes, Assembly Women, which makes fun of the idea of women having political power and making laws like these. As in English, the term hoplon (“weapon” or “tool”) was used to refer to the male genitals, and ocheuein (“mounting,” “riding”) to refer to sexual intercourse (as at 454e1).

8 The story of Arion’s rescue by the dolphin is told in Herodotus, Histories 1.23–4.

9 See Glossary of Terms s.v. disputation.

10 See Glossary of Terms s.v. eristic.

11 453c7–9.

12 Men were in charge of roasting meat. See 404b10–c4.

13 Epi pasi:The claim is not that no woman is stronger or better than any man in any such pursuit (which would contradict 455d4–5), but that the physical weakness of women is a relevant factor in all of them. See 451e1–2, 456a10–11.

14 374e4–376c5.

15 See Glossary of Terms s.v. cloak.

16 Plato is adapting a phrase of Pindar.

17 The metaphor begins at 453c10–d7.

18 See 432c3–4.

19 Both hunting dogs and aviaries were common in rich Greek households.

20 382c6–d3.

21 See 423b4–c5.

22 Infanticide by exposure was commonly used in ancient Greece as a method of birth control.

23 See 414b8–c2.

24 452b1–3.

25 Greek women were often married before they turned twenty. The puzzling characterization of the minimum age for male procreation is, perhaps, explained by a passage from Aristotle’s Politics: “As to the bodily characteristics in parents that are most beneficial to the offspring being produced. . . . Neither the physical condition of athletes nor that of one who is overly reliant on medical treatment and poorly suited to exertion is useful from the point of view of health or procreation, or is the condition needed in a good citizen. But the condition that is in a mean between these two is useful for these purposes. The proper physical condition, therefore, is one that is achieved by exertion, but not by violent exertion, and that promotes not just one thing, as the athletic condition does, but the actions of free people. And these should be provided to women and men alike” (7.16 1335b2–12).

26 These are lunar months. The period is from roughly seven to roughly nine calendar months. A fetus of less than seven months was considered nonviable.

27 Greek law did not usually permit marriage between biological siblings, who will be included in the class referred to here. See 427c3.

28 The Athenian democracy had nine rulers (archons) in Plato’s time.These included the chief magistrates, the chief military leader, and an important authority in religious matters.

29 See 429c5.

30 462b4–c9.

31 416d3–417b8.

32 Men victorious in the Olympic games were often awarded free meals for life by their cities. See Apology 36d5–9.

33 419a1–421c6.

34 Works and Days 40.

35 460b1–5.

36Iliad 7.321.

37 Iliad 8.162.

38 See 415a1–c7.

39 Works and Days 122. See Glossary of Terms s.v. diamon.

40 Apollo. See 427c2 note.

41 Greek views on pollution are discussed in R. Parker, Miasma (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).

42 See 414e1–6.

43 The third wave was proverbially the greatest.

44 See 369a5–c10.

45 As at 458c6 and 473e4–5, Socrates is supposing that Glaucon is designing the ideal city.

46 See 437d8–e8, 475b11–c4.

47 Trittarchousi: “command the soldiers in a trittys.” A trittys was one third of one of the ten tribes of which Athens consisted.

48 See 449c6–8.

49 A poem or play is fashioned out of sounds, a painting out of colors and shapes. See 600e4–601b4.

50 See Glossary of Terms s.v. thing that is.

51 The riddle seems to have been this: a man who is not a man saw and did not see a bird that was not a bird in a tree (xulon) that was not a tree; he hit (ballein) and did not hit it with a stone that was not a stone. The answer is that a eunuch with bad eyesight saw a bat on a rafter, threw a pumice stone at it, and missed. For “he saw a bird” is ambiguous between “he saw what was actually a bird” and “he saw what he took to be a bird,” xulon means both “tree” and “rafter” or “roof tree,” and ballein means both “to throw” and “to hit.”The rest is obvious.

52 See 484c6–d3, 493a6–494a4.

53 See 451b3.

Book 6

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION CONTINUES:

SOCRATES: Who the philosophers are, then, Glaucon, and who they aren’t [484a] has, through a somewhat lengthy argument and with much effort, somehow been made clear.

 

GLAUCON: That’s probably because it could not easily have been done through a shorter one.

 

SOCRATES: I suppose not. Yet I, at least, think that the matter would have [5] been made even clearer if we had had only that topic to discuss, and not the many others that remain for us to explore if we are to discover the difference [b] between the just life and the unjust one.

 

GLAUCON: What comes after this one, then?

 

SOCRATES: What else but the one that comes next? Since the philosophers are the ones who are able to grasp what is always the same in all respects, while those who cannot—those who wander among the many things that [5] vary in every sort of way—are not philosophers, which of the two should be the leaders of a city?

 

GLAUCON: What would be a reasonable answer for us to give?

 

[10] SOCRATES: Whichever of them seems capable of guarding a city’s laws and [c] practices should be established as guardians.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: So, is the answer to the following question clear: should a guardian who is going to keep watch over something be blind or keen-sighted?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Of course it is.

 

SOCRATES: Well, do you think there is any difference, then, between the blind and those who are really deprived of the knowledge of each thing that is, and have no clear model of it in their souls—those who cannot look away, like painters, to what is most true, and cannot, by making constant reference to it and by studying it as exactly as possible, establish here [d] on earth conventional norms concerning beautiful, just, or good things1 when they need to be established, or guard and preserve those that have been established?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, there is not much difference between them.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we appoint these blind people as our guardians, then, or those who know each thing that is, have no less experience than the others,[5] 2 and are not inferior to them in any other part of virtue?

 

GLAUCON: It would be absurd to choose anyone but philosophers, if indeed they are not inferior in these other things. For the very area in which they are superior is just about the greatest one. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Shouldn’t we explain, then, how the same men can have both [485a] sets of qualities?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then, as we were saying at the beginning of this discussion, it is first necessary to understand the nature of philosophers.3 And I think that if we can agree sufficiently about that, we will also agree that the same people [5] can have both qualities, and that they alone should be leaders in cities.

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: Let’s agree that philosophic natures always love the sort of [10] learning that makes clear to them some feature of the being4 that always is [b] and does not wander around between coming-to-be and decaying.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, let’s.

 

SOCRATES: And further, let’s agree that they love all of it and are not willing [5] to give up any part, whether great or small, significant or insignificant, just like the honor-lovers and passionate men we described before.5

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Consider next whether there is a further feature they must have [10] in their nature if they are going to be the way we described. [c]

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: Truthfulness; that is to say they must never willingly tolerate falsehood in any form. On the contrary, they must hate it and have a natural affection for the truth.

 

GLAUCON: They probably should have that feature. [5]

 

SOCRATES: But it is not only probable, my friend; it is entirely necessary for a naturally passionate man to love everything akin to or related to the boys he loves.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, could you find anything that is more intimately related [10] to wisdom than truth?

 

GLAUCON: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Then is it possible for the same nature to be a philosopher [d] (lover of wisdom) and a lover of falsehood?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: So, right from childhood, a genuine lover of learning must strive above all for truth of every kind.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: But in addition, when someone’s appetites are strongly inclined in one direction, we surely know that they become more weakly inclined in the others, just like a stream that has been partly diverted into another channel.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then when a person’s desires flow toward learning and everything [10] of that sort, they will be concerned, I imagine, with the pleasures that the soul experiences just by itself, and will be indifferent to those that come through the body—if indeed the person is not a counterfeit, but rather a [e] true, philosopher.6

 

GLAUCON: That’s entirely inevitable.

 

SOCRATES: A person like that will be temperate, then, and in no way a lover of money. After all, money and the big expenditures that go along with it are sought for the sake of things that other people may take seriously, [5] but that he does not.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And of course, there is also this to consider when you are [486a] going to judge whether a nature is philosophic or not.

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: You should not overlook its sharing in illiberality; for surely petty-mindedness is altogether incompatible with that quality in a soul that is [5] always reaching out to grasp all things as a whole, whether divine or human.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: And do you imagine that a thinker who is high-minded enough to look at all time and all being will consider human life to be a very great thing? [10]

 

GLAUCON: He couldn’t possibly.

 

SOCRATES: Then he won’t consider death to be a terrible thing either, will he? [b]

 

GLAUCON: Not in the least.

 

SOCRATES: Then a cowardly and illiberal nature could not partake, apparently, in true philosophy.

 

GLAUCON: Not in my opinion. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, is there any way that an orderly person, who is not money-loving, illiberal, a lying imposter, or a coward, could come to drive a hard bargain or be unjust?

 

GLAUCON: There is not.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, when you are considering whether someone has a philosophic soul or not, you will consider whether he is just and gentle, [10] right from the time he is young, or unsociable and savage.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And you won’t ignore this either, I imagine. [c]

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: Whether he is a slow learner or a fast one. Or do you expect someone to love something sufficiently well when it pains him to do it and a lot of effort brings only a small return? [5]

 

GLAUCON: No, it could not happen.

 

SOCRATES: What if he could retain nothing of what he learned, because he was completely forgetful? Could he fail to be empty of knowledge?

 

GLAUCON: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Then if he is laboring in vain, don’t you think that in the end [10] he is bound to hate himself and what he is doing?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So let’s never include a person with a forgetful soul among those who are sufficiently philosophical; the one we look for should be [d] good at remembering.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, we would deny that an unmusical and graceless nature is drawn to anything besides what is disproportionate. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And do you think that truth is akin to what is disproportionate or to what is proportionate?

 

GLAUCON: To what is proportionate.

 

SOCRATES: Then, in addition to those other things, let’s look for a mind that has a natural sense of proportion and grace, one whose innate disposition [10] makes it easy to lead to the form of each thing which is.

 

GLAUCON: Indeed.

 

[e] SOCRATES: Well, then, do you think the properties we have gone through aren’t interconnected, or that any of them is in any way unnecessary to a soul that is going to have a sufficiently complete grasp of what is?

 

[487a] GLAUCON: No, they are all absolutely necessary.

 

SOCRATES: Is there any criticism you can find, then, of a pursuit that a person cannot practice adequately unless he is naturally good at remembering, quick to learn, high-minded, graceful, and a friend and relative of [5] truth, justice, courage, and temperance?

 

GLAUCON: Not even Momus could criticize a pursuit like that.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, when people of this sort are in perfect condition because of their education and their stage of life, wouldn’t you entrust the city to them alone?

 

And Adeimantus replied:

 

[b] No one, Socrates, would be able to contradict these claims of yours. But all the same, here is pretty much the experience people have on any occasion on which they hear the sorts of things you are now saying: they think that because they are inexperienced in asking and answering questions, they are [5] led astray a little bit by the argument at every question, and that when these little bits are added together at the end of the discussion, a great false step appears that is the opposite of what they said at the outset. Like the unskilled, who are trapped by the clever checkers players in the end and [c] cannot make a move, they too are trapped in the end, and have nothing to say in this different kind of checkers, which is played not with pieces, but with words. Yet they are not a bit more inclined to think that what you claim is true. I say this in relation to the present case. You see, someone might well say now that he is unable to find the words to oppose you as you [5] ask each of your questions. Yet, when it comes to facts rather than words, he sees that of all those who take up philosophy—not those who merely dabble in it while still young in order to complete their upbringing, and [d] then drop it, but those who continue in it for a longer time—the majority become cranks, not to say completely bad, while the ones who seem best [5] are rendered useless to the city because of the pursuit you recommend.

 

When I had heard him out, I said:

 

Do you think that what these people say is false?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do not know. But I would be glad to hear what you think.

 

SOCRATES: You would hear that they seem to me to be telling the truth. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How, then, can it be right to say that there will be no end to evils in our cities until philosophers—people we agree to be useless to [e] cities—rule in them?

 

SOCRATES: The question you ask needs to be answered by means of an image.7[5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: And you, of course, are not used to speaking in images!

 

SOCRATES: So! After landing me with a claim that is so difficult to establish, are you mocking me, too? Anyway, listen to my image, and you will [488a] appreciate all the more how I have to strain to make up images. What the best philosophers experience in relation to cities is so difficult to bear that there is no other single experience like it. On the contrary, one must construct one’s image and one’s defense of these philosophers from many [5] sources, just as painters paint goat-stags by combining the features of different things.

 

Imagine, then, that the following sort of thing happens either on one ship or on many. The shipowner is taller and stronger than everyone else on board. But he is hard of hearing, he is a bit shortsighted, and his [b] knowledge of seafaring is correspondingly deficient. The sailors are quarreling with one another about captaincy.8 Each of them thinks that he should captain the ship, even though he has not yet learned the craft and cannot name his teacher or a time when he was learning it. Indeed, they [5] go further and claim that it cannot be taught at all, and are even ready to cut to pieces anyone who says it can. They are always crowding around the shipowner himself, pleading with him, and doing everything possible to [c] get him to turn the rudder over to them. And sometimes, if they fail to persuade him and others succeed, they execute those others or throw them overboard. Then, having disabled their noble shipowner with mandragora9 or drink or in some other way, they rule the ship, use up its cargo [5] drinking and feasting, and make the sort of voyage you would expect of such people. In addition, they praise anyone who is clever at persuading or forcing the shipowner to let them rule, calling him a “sailor,” a “skilled captain,” and “an expert about ships” while dismissing anyone else as a [d] [5] good-for-nothing. They do not understand that a true captain must pay attention to the seasons of the year, the sky, the stars, the winds, and all that pertains to his craft if he is really going to be expert at ruling a ship. As for how he is going to become captain of the ship, whether people want him [e] to or not, they do not think it possible to acquire the craft or practice of doing this at the same time as the craft of captaincy. When that is what is happening onboard ships, don’t you think that a true captain would be sure [489a] to be called a “stargazer,” a “useless babbler,” and a “good-for-nothing” by those who sail in ships so governed?

ADEIMANTUS: I certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: I do not think you need to examine the image to see the [5] resemblance to cities and how they’re disposed toward true philosophers, but you already understand what I mean.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, I do.

 

SOCRATES: First teach this image, then, to the person who is surprised [10] that philosophers are not honored in cities, and try to persuade him that it [b] would be far more surprising if they were honored.

 

ADEMANTUS: I will.

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, try to persuade him that you are speaking the truth when you say that the best among the philosophers are useless to the masses. But tell him to blame their uselessness on those who do not make [5] use of them, not on those good philosophers. You see, it is not natural for the captain to beg the sailors to be ruled by him, nor for the wise to knock at the doors of the rich. The man who came up with that bit of sophistry was lying.10 What is truly natural is for the sick person, rich or poor, to go [c] to doctors’ doors, and for anyone who needs to be ruled to go to the doors of the one who can rule him. It is not for the ruler—if he is truly any use—to beg the subjects to accept his rule. Tell him he will make no mistake if he likens our present political rulers to the sailors we mentioned a [5] moment ago, and those who are called useless stargazers by them to the true ship’s captains.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: For those reasons, then, and in these circumstances, it is not easy for the best pursuit to be highly honored by those whose pursuits are its [10] very opposites. But by far the greatest and most serious slander is brought [d] on philosophy by those who claim to practice it—the ones about whom the prosecutor of philosophy declares, as you put it, that the majority of those who take it up are completely bad, while the best ones are useless. And I admitted that what you said was true, didn’t I?11 [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Haven’t we now explained why the good ones are useless?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We certainly have.

 

SOCRATES: Do you next want us to discuss why it is inevitable that the greater number are bad, and try to show, if we can, that philosophy is not [10] responsible for this either?[e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s begin our dialogue by recalling the starting point of our description of the nature that someone must have if he is to become a fine and good person. First of all, if you remember, he was led by truth,12 [490a] and he had to follow it wholeheartedly and unequivocally, on pain of being a lying imposter with no share at all in true philosophy.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s what we said.

 

SOCRATES: Well, isn’t that fact alone completely contrary to the belief currently held about him? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly is.

 

SOCRATES: So, won’t it be reasonable, then, for us to plead in his defense that a real lover of learning naturally strives for what is? He does not linger over each of the many things that are believed to be, but keeps on going, [b] without losing or lessening his passion, until he grasps what the nature of each thing itself is13 with the part of his soul that is fitted to grasp a thing of that sort because of its kinship with it.14 Once he has drawn near to it, has intercourse with what really is, and has begotten understanding and truth, [5] he knows, truly lives, is nourished, and—at that point, but not before—is relieved from his labor pains.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Nothing could be more reasonable.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, will a person of that sort love falsehood or, in completely opposite fashion, will he hate it? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: He will hate it. [c]

 

SOCRATES: And if truth led the way, we would never say, I imagine, that a chorus of evils could follow it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: On the contrary, it is followed by a healthy and just character, [5] and the temperance that accompanies it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: What need is there, then, to go back to the beginning and compel the rest of the philosophic nature’s chorus to line up all over again? [10] You surely remember that courage, high-mindedness, ease in learning, and a good memory all belong to philosophers. Then you objected that anyone would be compelled to agree with what we are saying, but that if he left the [d] arguments aside and looked at the very people the argument is about, he would say that some of those he saw were useless, while the majority of them were thoroughly bad. Trying to discover the reason for this slander, we have arrived now at this question: why are the majority of them bad? [5] And that is why we have again taken up the nature of the true philosophers and defined what it necessarily has to be.

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: What we now have to do is look at the ways this nature gets corrupted; how it gets completely destroyed in the majority of cases, while a small number escape—the very ones that are called useless, rather than bad. After that, we must next look at those who imitate this nature and [491a] adopt its pursuit. We must see what natures the souls have that enter into a pursuit that is too valuable and too high for them—souls that, by often striking false notes, give philosophy the reputation that you said it has with [5] everyone everywhere.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What sorts of corruption do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: I will try to explain them to you if I can. I imagine that everyone would agree with us about this: the sort of nature that possesses all the qualities we prescribed just now for the person who is going to be a complete [b] philosopher, is seldom found among human beings, and there will be few who possess it. Or don’t you think so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I most certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, then, how many great sources of destruction there [5] are for these few.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What are they?

 

SOCRATES: The most surprising thing of all to hear is that each one of the things we praised in that nature tends to corrupt the soul that has it and drag it away from philosophy. I mean courage, temperance, and the other [10] things we mentioned.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That does sound strange.

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, in addition to those, all so-called good things [c] also corrupt it and drag it away—beauty, wealth, physical strength, powerful family connections in the city, and all that goes along with these. You understand the general pattern of thing I mean?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do, and I would be glad to acquire a more precise understanding of it. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Grasp the general principle correctly and the matter will become clear to you, and what I said about it before won’t seem so strange.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What are you telling me to grasp? [10]

 

SOCRATES: In the case of every seed or growing thing, whether plant or [d] animal, we know that if it fails to get the food, climate, or location suitable for it, then the more vigorous it is, the more it is deficient in the qualities proper to it. For surely bad is more opposed to good than to not-good. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So, I suppose it is reasonable that the best nature comes off worse than an inferior one from unsuitable nurture.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, Adeimantus, won’t we also say that if souls with the [e] best natures get a bad education, they become exceptionally bad? Or do you think that great injustices and unalloyed evil originate in an inferior nature, rather than in a vigorous one that has been corrupted by its upbringing? Or that a weak nature is ever responsible for great good things [5] or great bad ones?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, you are right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, if the nature we proposed for the philosopher happens [492a] to receive the proper instruction, I imagine it will inevitably grow to attain every virtue. But if it is not sown, planted, and grown in a suitable environment, it will develop in entirely the opposite way, unless some god comes to its aid. Or do you too believe, as the masses do, that some young [5] people are corrupted by sophists—that there are sophists, private individuals, who corrupt them to a significant extent? Isn’t it, rather, the very people who say this who are the greatest sophists of all, who educate most effectively and produce young and old men and women of just the sort [b] they want?

 

ADEIMANTUS: When do they do that?

 

SOCRATES: When many of them sit together in assemblies, courts, theaters, [5] army camps, or any other gathering of a majority in public and, with a loud uproar, object excessively to some of the things that are said or done, then approve excessively of others, shouting and clapping; and when, in addition to these people themselves, the rocks and the surrounding [c] space itself echo and redouble the uproar of their praise or blame. In a situation like that, how do you think—as the saying goes—a young man’s heart is affected?15 How will whatever sort of private education he received [5] hold up for him, and not get swept away by such praise and blame, and go be carried off by the flood wherever it goes, so that he will call the same things beautiful or ugly as these people, practice what they practice, and become like them?

 

[d] ADEIMANTUS: The compulsion to do so will be enormous, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: And yet we have not mentioned the greatest compulsion of all.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What is that?

 

[5] SOCRATES: It is what these educators and sophists impose by their actions if their words fail to persuade. Or don’t you know that they punish anyone who is not persuaded, with disenfranchisement, fines, or death?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They most certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: What other sophist, then, or what sort of private conversations [10] do you think will oppose these and prove stronger?

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: None, I imagine.

 

SOCRATES: No, indeed, even to try would be very foolish. You see, there is not now, never has been, nor ever will be, a character whose view of virtue goes contrary to the education these provide. I mean a human character, [5] comrade—the divine, as the saying goes, is an exception to the rule. You may be sure that if anything is saved and turns out well in the political [493a] systems that exist now, you won’t be mistaken in saying that divine providence saved it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That is what I think, too.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, you should also agree to this.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: What?

 

SOCRATES: Each of those private wage-earners—the ones these people call sophists and consider to be their rivals in craft16—teaches anything other than the convictions the masses hold when they are assembled together, and this he calls wisdom. It is just as if someone were learning [10] the passions and appetites of a huge, strong beast that he is rearing—how [b] to approach and handle it, when it is most difficult to deal with or most docile and what makes it so, what sounds it utters in either condition, and what tones of voice soothe or anger it. Having learned all this through associating and spending time17 with the beast, he calls this wisdom, gathers [5] his information together as if it were a craft, and starts to teach it. Knowing nothing in reality about which of these convictions or appetites is fine or shameful, good or bad, just or unjust, he uses all these terms in conformity [c] with the great beast’s beliefs—calling the things it enjoys good and the things that anger it bad. He has no other account to give of them, but calls everything he is compelled to do just and fine, never having seen how [5] much the natures of necessity and goodness really differ, and being unable to explain it to anyone. Don’t you think, by Zeus, that someone like that would make a strange educator?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then does this person seem any different from the one who believes that wisdom is understanding the passions and pleasures of the [10] masses—multifarious people—assembled together, whether in regard to [d] painting, music, or politics for that matter? For if a person associates with the masses and exhibits his poetry or some other piece of craftsmanship to them or his service to the city, and gives them mastery over him to any degree beyond what is unavoidable, he will be under Diomedean compulsion,[5] 18 as it is called, to produce the things of which they approve. But that such things are truly good and beautiful—have you ever heard anyone presenting an argument for that conclusion that was not absolutely ridiculous?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, and I do not suppose I ever will. [e]

 

SOCRATES : So then, bearing all that in mind, recall our earlier question: can the majority in any way tolerate or accept that the beautiful itself (as opposed to the many beautiful things), or each thing itself (as opposed to the corresponding many), exists? [494a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not in the least.

 

SOCRATES: It is impossible, then, for the majority to be philosophic.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is impossible.[5]

 

SOCRATES: And so, those who practice philosophy are inevitably disparaged by them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: And also by those private individuals who associate with the majority and want to please them.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly. [10]

 

SOCRATES: On the basis of these facts, then, do you see any way to preserve a philosophic nature and ensure that it will continue to practice philosophy and reach the end? Consider the question in light of what we said [b] before. We agreed that ease in learning, a good memory, courage, and high-mindedness belong to the philosophic nature.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Right from the start, then, won’t someone like that be first [5] among the children in everything, especially if his body’s nature matches that of his soul?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course he will.

 

SOCRATES: So as he gets older, I imagine his family and fellow citizens [10] will want to make use of him in connection with their own affairs.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: They will get down on their knees, begging favors from him [c] and honoring him, flattering ahead of time the power that is going to be his, so as to secure it for themselves.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s usually what happens, at least.

 

SOCRATES: What do you think someone like that will do in such circumstances—especially [5] if he happens to be from a great city where he is rich and noble, and if he is good-looking and tall as well? Won’t he be filled with an impractical expectation and think himself capable of managing the affairs, not only of the Greeks, but of the barbarians, too? And won’t he [d] exalt himself to great heights, as a result, and be brimming with pretension and empty, senseless pride?19

 

ADEIMANTUS: He certainly will.

 

SOCRATES: Now, suppose someone gently approaches a young man in that state of mind and tells him the truth: that he has no sense, although he [5] needs it, and that it cannot be acquired unless he works like a slave to attain it. Do you think it will be easy for him to hear that message through the evils that surround him?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Far from it.

 

SOCRATES: And suppose that, because of his noble nature and his natural affinity for such arguments, he somehow sees the point and is turned [5] around and drawn toward philosophy. What do we suppose those people will do if they believe that they are losing his services and companionship? Is there anything they won’t do or say in his regard to prevent him from being persuaded? Or anything they won’t do or say in regard to his persuader to prevent him from succeeding, whether it is in private plots or [5] public court cases?20

 

ADEIMANTUS: There certainly is not. [495a]

 

SOCRATES: Then is there any chance that such a person will practice philosophy?

 

ADEIMANTUS: None at all.

 

SOCRATES: Do you see, then, that we weren’t wrong to say that when a philosophic nature is badly brought up, its very components—together [5] with the other so-called goods, such as wealth and every provision of that sort—are somehow the cause of its falling away from the pursuit?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, we were not. What we said was right.

 

SOCRATES: There you are, then, you amazing fellow! That is the extent of the sort of destruction and corruption that the nature best suited for the [10] noblest pursuit undergoes. And such a nature is a rare occurrence anyway, [b] we claim. Moreover, men who possess it are the ones that do the worst things to cities and individuals, and also—if they happen to be swept that way by the current21—the greatest good. For a petty nature never does anything [5] great, either to a private individual or a city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s very true.

 

SOCRATES: So when these men, for whom philosophy is most appropriate, fall away from her, they leave her desolate and unwed, and themselves lead a life that is inappropriate and untrue. Then others, who are unworthy [c] of her, come to her as to an orphan bereft of kinsmen, and shame her. They are the ones responsible for the reproaches that you say are cast upon philosophy by her detractors—that some of her consorts are useless, while the majority deserve many evils. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is what they say.

 

SOCRATES: And it is a reasonable thing to say. For other worthless little men see that this position has become vacant, even though it is brimming with fine accolades and pretensions, and—like prisoners escaping from jail [d] who take refuge in a temple—leap gladly from their crafts to philosophy. These are the ones who are most sophisticated at their own petty craft. You see, at least in comparison to other crafts, and even in its present state, philosophy [5] still has a grander reputation. And that is what many people are aiming at, people with defective natures, whose souls are as cramped and spoiled by their menial tasks as their bodies are warped by their crafts and [e] occupations. Isn’t that inevitably what happens?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly is.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think that they look any different than a little, bald-headed [5] blacksmith who has come into some money and, newly released from debtor’s prison, has taken a bath, put on a new cloak, got himself up as a bridegroom, and is about to marry the master’s daughter because she is poor and abandoned?

 

[496a] ADEIMANTUS: They are no different at all.

 

SOCRATES: What sort of offspring are they likely to beget, then? Won’t their children be wretched illegitimates?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: What about when men who are unworthy of education [5] approach philosophy and associate with her in a way unworthy of her? What kinds of thoughts and beliefs are we to say they beget? Won’t they be what are truly and appropriately called sophisms, since they have nothing genuine or truly wise about them?

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then there remains, Adeimantus, only a very small group who [b] associate with philosophy in a way that is worthy of her: a noble and well brought-up character, perhaps, kept down by exile, who stays true to his nature and remains with philosophy because there is no one to corrupt him; or a great soul living in a small city, who disdains the city’s affairs and looks beyond them. A very few might perhaps come to philosophy from [5] other crafts that they rightly despise because they have good natures. And some might be held back by the bridle that restrains our friend Theages—you see, he meets all the other conditions needed to make him fall away [c] from philosophy, but his physical illness keeps him out of politics and prevents it. Finally, my own case is hardly worth mentioning—my daimonic sign22—since I don’t suppose it has happened to anyone else or to only a [5] few before. Now, those who have become members of this little group have tasted how sweet and blessed a possession philosophy is. At the same time, they have also seen the insanity of the masses and realized that there is nothing healthy, so to speak, in public affairs, and that there is no ally with [d] whose aid the champion of justice can survive; that instead he would perish before he could profit either their city or his friends, and be useless both to himself and to others—like a man who has fallen among wild animals and is neither willing to join them in doing injustice nor sufficiently strong to [5] oppose the general savagery alone. Taking all this into his calculations, he keeps quiet and does his own work, like someone who takes refuge under a little wall from a storm of dust or hail driven by the wind. Seeing others filled with lawlessness, the philosopher is satisfied if he can somehow lead his present life pure of injustice and impious acts, and depart from it with [e] good hope, blameless and content.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well, that is no small thing for him to have accomplished before departing. [497a]

 

SOCRATES: But no very great one either, since he did not chance upon a suitable constitution. In a suitable one, his own growth will be fuller and he will save the community, as well as himself. Anyway, it seems to me that we [5] have now said enough about the slander brought against philosophy and why it is unjust—unless, of course, you have got something to add.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I have nothing further to add on that issue. But which of our present constitutions do you think is suitable for philosophy? [10]

 

SOCRATES: None of them. But that is exactly my complaint. There is not [b] one city today with a constitution worthy of the philosophic nature. That is precisely why it is perverted and altered. It is like foreign seed sown in alien ground: it tends to be overpowered and to fade away into the native species. Similarly, the philosophic species does not maintain its own power at [5] present, but declines into a different character. But if it were to find the best constitution, as it is itself the best, it would be clear that it is really divine [c] and that other natures and pursuits are merely human. Obviously, you are going to ask next what that constitution is.

 

ADEIMANTUS: You are wrong there. You see, I was not going to ask that, [5] but whether it was the constitution we described when we were founding our city or a different one.

 

SOCRATES: In all other respects, it is that one. But we said even then23 that there must always be some people in the city who have a rational account of the constitution, the same one that guided you, the lawgiver, when you [d] made the laws.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, we did say that.

 

SOCRATES: But we did not explain it clearly enough, for fear of what our own objections have made clear: namely, that the demonstration of it would be long and difficult. Indeed, even what remains is not the easiest of [5] all things to discuss.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What is that?

 

SOCRATES : How a city can engage in philosophy without being destroyed. You see, all great things are prone to fall and, as the saying goes, beautiful things are really difficult. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: All the same, the demonstration won’t be complete until [e] this has been cleared up.

 

SOCRATES: If anything prevents that, it won’t be lack of willingness, but lack of ability. At any rate, you will see how passionate I am. Look now, in [5] fact, at how passionately and recklessly I am going to argue that a city should practice philosophy in the opposite way to the present one.

 

ADEIMANTUS: How?

 

SOCRATES: At present, those who take it up at all do so as young men, just out of childhood, who have yet to take up household management and [498a] moneymaking. Then, just when they reach the most difficult part they abandon it and are regarded as the most fully trained philosophers. By the most difficult part, I mean the one concerned with arguments.24 In later life, if others are engaged in it and they are invited and deign to listen to [5] them, they think they have done a lot, since they think this should only be a sideline. And, with a few exceptions, by the time they reach old age they are more thoroughly extinguished than the sun of Heraclitus, since they are [b] never rekindled.25

 

ADEIMANTUS: What should they do instead?

 

SOCRATES : Entirely the opposite. As young men and children, they should occupy themselves with an education and philosophy suitable to the young. Their bodies are blooming and growing into manhood at this time, and [5] they should take very good care of them, so as to acquire a helper for philosophy. But as they grow older and their soul begins to reach maturity, they should make its exercises more rigorous. Then, when their strength begins to fail and they have retired from politics and military service, they [c] should graze freely in the pastures of philosophy and do nothing else, except as a sideline—I mean those who are going to live happily and, when the end comes, crown the life they have lived with a fitting providence in that other place.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: You seem to be arguing with real passion, Socrates. But I am sure that most of your hearers will oppose you with even greater passion and won’t be convinced in the least—beginning with Thrasymachus.

 

SOCRATES: Please do not try to raise a quarrel between me and Thrasymachus just as we have become friends—not that we were enemies before.[d] You see, we won’t relax our efforts until we convince him and the others—or at least do something that may benefit them in a later incarnation when, reborn, they happen upon these arguments again.26

 

ADEIMANTUS: You are talking about the short term, I see! [5]

 

SOCRATES: It is certainly nothing compared to the whole of time! However, it is no wonder that the masses are not convinced by our arguments. I mean, they have never seen a man that matched our plan—though they have more often seen words purposely chosen to rhyme with one another [e] than just happening to do so as in the present case.27 But a man who, as far as possible, matched and rhymed with virtue in word and deed, and wielded dynastic power in a city of the same type—that is something they have never seen even once. Or do you think they have? [499a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, definitely not.

 

SOCRATES: Nor, bless you, have they spent enough time listening to fine and free arguments that vigorously seek the truth in every way, so as to [5] acquire knowledge and keep their distance from all the sophistries and eristic quibbles that—whether in public trials or private gatherings—strive for nothing except reputation and disputation.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, they have not. [10]

 

SOCRATES: It was for these reasons, and because we foresaw these difficulties, that we were afraid. All the same, we were compelled by the truth to [b] say that no city, no constitution, and no individual man will ever become perfect until some chance event compels those few philosophers who are not vicious (the ones who are now called useless) to take care of a city, whether they are willing to or not, and compels the city to obey them—or [5] until a true passion for true philosophy flows by some divine inspiration into the sons of the men now wielding dynastic power or sovereignty, or into the men themselves. Now, it cannot be reasonably maintained, in my [c] view, that either or both of these things is impossible. But if they were, we would be justly ridiculed for indulging in wishful thinking. Isn’t that so? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Then if, in the limitless past, some necessity forced those who were foremost in philosophy to take charge of a city, or is doing so now in some barbaric place far beyond our ken, or will do so in the future, this is [d] something we are prepared to fight about—our argument that the constitution we have described has existed, does exist, and will exist, at any rate, whenever it is that the muse of philosophy gains mastery of a city. It is not impossible for this to happen, so we are not speaking of impossibilities—that it is difficult, we agree ourselves. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I certainly think so.

 

SOCRATES: But the masses do not—is that what you are going to say?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They probably don’t.

 

SOCRATES: Bless you, you should not make such a wholesale charge [10] against the masses! They will surely come to hold a different belief if, [e] instead of wanting to win a victory at their expense, you soothe them and try to remove their slanderous prejudice against the love of learning. You must show them what you mean by philosophers and define their nature [500a] and pursuit the way we did just now. Then they will realize you do not mean the same people they do. And if they once see it that way, even you will say that they will have a different opinion from the one you just attributed to them and will answer differently. Or do you think that anyone who is gentle and without malice is harsh to one who is not harsh, or malicious [5] to one who is not malicious? I will anticipate you and say that I think a few people may have such a harsh character, but not the majority.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And I agree, of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then don’t you also agree that the harshness of the masses [b] toward philosophy is caused by those outsiders who do not belong and who have burst in like a band of revelers, abusing one another, indulging their love of quarreling, and always arguing about human beings—something [5] that is least appropriate in philosophy?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: For surely, Adeimantus, someone whose mind is truly directed toward the things that are has not the leisure to look down at human affairs and be filled with malice and hatred as a result of entering into their disputes. [c] Instead, as he looks at and contemplates things that are orderly and always the same, that neither do injustice to one another nor suffer it, being all in a rational order, he imitates them and tries to become as like them as [5] he can. Or do you think there is any way to prevent someone from associating with something he admires without imitating it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: He can’t possibly.

 

SOCRATES: Then the philosopher, by associating with what is orderly and divine, becomes as divine and orderly as a human being can. Though, mind [d] you, there are always plenty of slanders around.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And if he should come to be compelled to make a practice—in private and in public—of stamping what he sees there into the people’s [5] characters, instead of shaping only his own, do you think he will be a poor craftsman of temperance, justice, and the whole of popular virtue?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: And when the masses realize that what we are saying about him is true, will they be harsh with philosophers or mistrust us when we [e10] say that there is no way a city can ever find happiness unless its plan is drawn by painters who use the divine model?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They won’t be harsh, if they do realize this. But what sort [5] of drawing do you mean? [501a]

 

SOCRATES: They would take the city and people’s characters as their sketching slate, but first they would wipe it clean—which is not at all an easy thing to do. And you should be aware that this is an immediate difference between them and others—that they refuse to take either a private individual or a city in hand, or to write laws, unless they receive a clean [5] slate or are allowed to clean it themselves.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And rightly so.

 

SOCRATES: And after that, don’t you think they would draw the plan of the constitution? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose that, as they work, they would look often in each direction: on the one hand, toward what is in its nature just, beautiful, [b] temperate, and all the rest; and, on the other, toward what they are trying to put into human beings, mixing and blending pursuits to produce a human likeness, based on the one that Homer too called divine and godly [5] when it appeared among human beings.28

 

ADEIMANTUS: Right.

 

SOCRATES: They would erase one thing, I suppose, and draw in another, until they had made people’s characters as dear to the gods as possible. [c]

 

ADEIMANTUS: At any rate, the drawing would be most beautiful that way.

 

SOCRATES: Are we at all persuading the people you said were rushing to attack us, then, that the philosopher we were praising to them is really this [5] sort of painter of constitutions? They were angry because we were entrusting cities to him; are they any calmer at hearing it now?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They will be much calmer, if they have any sense.

 

SOCRATES: After all, how could they possibly dispute it? Will they deny [d] that philosophers are lovers both of what is and of the truth?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That would be silly.

 

SOCRATES: Or that their nature, as we have described it, is akin to the best? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: They cannot deny that either.

 

SOCRATES: Or that such a nature, when it happens to find appropriate pursuits, will not be as completely good and philosophic as any other? Or [10] are they going to claim that the people we excluded are more so?

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: Will they still be angry, then, when we say that until the philosopher class gains mastery of a city, there will be no respite from evils for either city or citizens, and the constitution we have been describing in our [5] discussion will never be completed in practice?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They will probably be less so.

 

SOCRATES: If it is all right with you, then, let’s not say that they will simply be less angry, but that they will become altogether gentle and persuaded; [502a] so that out of shame, if nothing else, they will agree.

 

ADEIMANTUS: All right.

 

SOCRATES: So let’s assume that they have been convinced of this. Will [5] anyone contend, then, that there is no chance that the offspring of kings or men in power could be natural-born philosophers?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No one could.

 

SOCRATES: Could anyone claim that if such offspring are born, they must inevitably be corrupted? We agree ourselves that it is difficult for them to be saved. But that in the whole of time not one of them could be saved—[b] could anyone contend that?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course not.

 

SOCRATES: But surely the occurrence of one such individual is enough, provided his city obeys him, to bring to completion all the things that now [5] seem so incredible.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, one is enough.

 

SOCRATES: For I suppose that if a ruler established the laws and practices we have described, it is hardly impossible that the citizens would be willing to carry them out.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Would it be either surprising or impossible, then, that others should think as we do?

 

[c] ADEIMANTUS: I don’t suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: But I think our earlier discussion was sufficient to show that these arrangements are best, provided they are possible.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, it was.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that the conclusion we have now reached [5] about legislation is that the one we are describing is best, provided it is possible; and that while it is difficult for it to come about, it certainly is not impossible.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is the conclusion we have reached.

 

SOCRATES: Now that this conclusion has, with much effort, been reached, we must next deal with the remaining issues—in what way, by means of what subjects and pursuits, the saviors of our constitution will come to [10] exist, and at what ages they will take up each of them. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, we must deal with that.

 

SOCRATES: I gained nothing by my cleverness, then, in omitting from our earlier discussion the troublesome topic of acquiring women, begetting [5] children, and establishing rulers, because I knew the whole truth would provoke resentment and would be difficult to bring about. As it turned out, the need to discuss them arose anyway. Now, the subject of women and children has already been discussed. But that of the rulers has to be taken [e] up again from the beginning. We said,29 if you remember, that they must show themselves to be lovers of the city, when tested by pleasures and [503a] pains, by not abandoning this conviction through labors, fears, and all other adversities. Anyone who was incapable of doing so was to be rejected, while anyone who always came through pure—like gold tested in a fire—[5] was to be made ruler and receive gifts and prizes, both while he lived and after his death. These were the sorts of things we were saying while our argument veiled its face and slipped by, for fear of stirring up the very problems that now confront us. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true. I do remember.

 

SOCRATES: I was reluctant, my friend, to say the things we have now dared to say anyway. But now, let’s also dare to say that we must establish philosophers as guardians in the most exact sense. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Let’s do so.

 

SOCRATES: Bear in mind, then, that there will probably be only a few of them. You see, they have to have the nature we described, and its parts rarely consent to grow together in one person; rather, its many parts grow split off from one another. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How do you mean? [c]

 

SOCRATES: Ease of learning, good memory, astuteness, and smartness, as you know, and all the other things that go along with them, such as youthful passion and high-mindedness, are rarely willing to grow together simultaneously with a disposition to live an orderly, quiet, and completely stable [5] life. On the contrary, those who possess the former traits are carried by their quick wits wherever chance leads them, and have no stability at all.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Those with stable characters, on the other hand, who do not change easily, whom one would employ because of their greater reliability, [d] and who in battle are not easily moved by fears, act in the same way when it comes to their studies. They are hard to get moving and learn with difficulty, as if they are anesthetized, and are constantly falling asleep and yawning [5] whenever they have to work hard at such things.

 

ADEIMANTUS: They are.

 

SOCRATES: Yet we say that someone must have a good and fine share of both characters, or he won’t receive the truest education or honor, or be [10] allowed to rule.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Then don’t you think this will rarely occur?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

[e] SOCRATES: He must be tested, then, in the labors, fears, and pleasures we mentioned before. He must also be exercised in many other subjects, however, which we did not mention but are adding now, to see whether his nature can endure the most important subjects or will shrink from them [504a] like the cowards who shrink from the other tests.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is certainly important to find that out. But what do you mean by the greatest subjects?

 

SOCRATES: Do you remember when we distinguished three kinds of [5] things in the soul in order to help bring out what justice, temperance, courage, and wisdom each is?30

 

ADEIMANTUS: If I didn’t, I would not deserve to hear the rest.

 

SOCRATES: Do you also remember what preceded it?

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: No, what?

 

[b] SOCRATES: We said, I believe, that in order to get the finest view of these matters, we would need to take a longer road, which would make them plain to anyone who took it, but that it was possible to give demonstrations that would be up to the standard of the previous discussion.31 All of you said that was enough. The result was that our subsequent discussion, as it [5] seemed to me, was less than exact. But whether or not it satisfied all of you is for you to say.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I, at any rate, thought you gave us good measure. And so, apparently, did the others.

 

SOCRATES: No, my friend, any measure of such things that falls short in [c] any way of what is, is not good measure at all, since nothing incomplete is a measure of anything. Some people, however, are occasionally of the opinion that an incomplete treatment is already adequate and that there is no need for further inquiry.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, a lot of people feel like that. Laziness is the cause. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, that is a feeling that is least appropriate in a guardian of a city and its laws.

 

ADEIMANTUS: No doubt.

 

SOCRATES: He will have to take the longer road then, comrade, and put no less effort into learning than into physical training. For otherwise, as we [d] were just saying, he will never pursue the greatest and most appropriate subject to the end.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Why, aren’t these virtues the greatest things? Is there something yet greatest than justice and the other virtues we discussed? [5]

 

SOCRATES: Not only is it greatest, but, even in the case of the virtues themselves, it is not enough to look at a mere sketch as we are doing now, while neglecting the most finished portrait. I mean, it is ridiculous, isn’t it, to strain every nerve to attain the utmost exactness and clarity about other things of little value, while not treating the greatest things as [e] meriting the most exactness?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly is. But do you think that anyone is going to let you off without asking you what you mean by this greatest subject, and what it is concerned with? [5]

 

SOCRATES: No, I do not. And you may ask it, too. You have certainly heard the answer often, but now either you are not thinking or you intend to make trouble for me again by interrupting. And I suspect it is more the latter.You see, you have often heard it said that the form of the good is the [505a] greatest thing to learn about, and that it is by their relation to it that just things and the others become useful and beneficial. And now you must be pretty certain that that is what I am going to say, and, in addition, that we have no adequate knowledge of it. And if we do not know it, you know [5] that even the fullest possible knowledge of other things is of no benefit to us, any more than if we acquire any possession without the good. Or do you think there is any benefit in possessing everything but the good? Or to [b] know everything without knowing the good, thereby knowing nothing fine or good?

 

ADEIMANTUS: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Furthermore, you also know that the masses believe pleasure to be the good, while the more refined believe it to be knowledge.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And, my friend, that those who believe this cannot show us what sort of knowledge it is, but in the end are forced to say that it is [10] knowledge of the good.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which is completely ridiculous.

 

[c] SOCRATES: How could it not be, when they blame us for not knowing the good and then turn around and talk to us as if we did know it? I mean, they say it is knowledge of the good—as if we understood what they mean when they utter the word “good.”

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: What about those who define the good as pleasure? Are they any less full of confusion than the others? Or aren’t even they forced to admit that there are bad pleasures?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Most definitely.

 

SOCRATES: I suppose it follows, doesn’t it, that they have to admit that the same things are both good and bad?

 

[d] ADEIMANTUS: It certainly does.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it clear, then, that there are lots of serious disagreements about the good?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Well, isn’t it also clear that many people would choose [5] things that are believed to be just or beautiful, even if they are not, and would act, acquire things, and form beliefs accordingly? Yet no one is satisfied to acquire things that are believed to be good. On the contrary, everyone seeks the things that are good. In this area, everyone disdains mere reputation.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Right.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is what every soul pursues, and for its sake does everything. The soul has a hunch that the good is something, but it is puzzled [e] and cannot adequately grasp just what it is or acquire the sort of stable belief about it that it has about the other things, and so it misses the benefit, if any, that even those other things may give. Are we to accept that even the [506a] best people in the city, to whom we entrust everything, must remain thus in the dark about something of this kind and importance?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s the last thing we would do.

 

SOCRATES: Anyway, I imagine that just and beautiful things won’t have acquired much of a guardian in someone who does not even know why [5] they are good. And I have a hunch that no one will have adequate knowledge of them until he knows this.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s a good hunch.

 

SOCRATES: But won’t our constitution be perfectly ordered if such a guardian, one who knows these things, oversees it? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is bound to be. But you yourself, Socrates, do you say the good is knowledge or pleasure, or is it something else altogether?

 

SOCRATES: What a man! You made it good and clear long ago that other [5] people’s opinions about these matters would not satisfy you.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well, Socrates, it does not seem right to me for you to be willing to state other people’s convictions but not your own, when you have spent so much time occupied with these matters. [c]

 

SOCRATES: What? Do you think it is right to speak about things you do not know as if you do know them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not as if you know them, but you ought to be willing to state what you believe as what you believe. [5]

 

SOCRATES: What? Haven’t you noticed that beliefs without knowledge are all shameful and ugly things, since the best of them are blind? Do you think that those who have a true belief without understanding are any different from blind people who happen to travel the right road?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They are no different. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Do you want to look at shameful, blind, and crooked things, then, when you might hear fine, illuminating ones from other people? [d]

 

And Glaucon said:

 

By Zeus, Socrates, do not stop now, with the end in sight, so to speak! We will be satisfied if you discuss the good the way you discussed justice, temperance, and the rest. [5]

 

SOCRATES: That, comrade, would well satisfy me too, but I am afraid that I won’t be up to it and that I will disgrace myself and look ridiculous by trying. No, bless you, let’s set aside what the good itself is for the time being. You see, even to arrive at my current beliefs about it seems beyond [e] the range of our present discussion.32 But I am willing to tell you about what seems to be an offspring of the good and most like it, if that is agreeable to you; or otherwise to let the matter drop. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Tell us, then. The story about the father remains a debt you will pay another time.

 

[507a] SOCRATES : I wish I could repay it, and you recover the debt, instead of just the interest. So here, then, is this child and offspring of the good itself. But take care I do not somehow deceive you unintentionally by giving you [5] an illegitimate account of the child.33

 

GLAUCON: We will take as much care as possible. So speak on.

 

SOCRATES: I will once I have come to an agreement with you and reminded you of things we have already said here as well as on many other occasions.

 

[b] GLAUCON: Which things?

 

SOCRATES: We say that there are many beautiful, many good, and many other such things, thereby distinguishing them in words.34

 

GLAUCON: We do.

 

SOCRATES: We also say there is a beautiful itself and a good itself. And so, [5] in the case of all the things that we then posited as many, we reverse ourselves and posit a single form belonging to each, since we suppose there is a single one, and call it what each is.35

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: And we say that the one class of things is visible but not intelligible, [10] while the forms are intelligible but not visible.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

[c] SOCRATES: With what of ours do we see visible things?

 

GLAUCON: With our sight.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t we hear audible things with hearing and perceive all other perceptible things with our other senses?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Have you ever thought about how lavish the craftsman of our senses was in making the power to see and be seen?

 

GLAUCON: No, not really.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Well, think of it this way. Do hearing and sound need another kind of thing in order for the former to hear and the latter to be heard—a [d] third thing in whose absence the one won’t hear or the other be heard?

 

GLAUCON: No.

 

SOCRATES: And I think there cannot be many—not to say any—others that need such a thing. Or can you think of one? [5]

 

GLAUCON: No, I cannot.

 

SOCRATES: Aren’t you aware that sight and the visible realm have such a need?

 

GLAUCON: In what way? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Surely sight may be present in the eyes and its possessor may try to use it, and colors may be present in things; but unless a third kind of thing is present, which is naturally adapted for this specific purpose, you [e] know that sight will see nothing and the colors will remain unseen.

 

GLAUCON: What kind of thing do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The kind you call light.

 

GLAUCON: You are right. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So it is no insignificant form of yoke, then, that yokes the sense of sight and the power to be seen. In fact, it is more honorable than [508a] any that yokes other yoked teams. Provided, of course, that light is not something without honor.

 

GLAUCON: And it is surely far from being without honor.

 

SOCRATES: Which of the gods in the heavens would you say is the controller of this—the one whose light makes our sight see best and visible [5] things best seen?

 

GLAUCON: The very one you and others would name. I mean, it is clear that what you are asking about is the sun.36

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t sight naturally related to that god in the following way?

 

GLAUCON: Which one? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Neither sight itself nor that in which it comes to be—namely, the eye—is the sun. [b]

 

GLAUCON: No, it is not.

 

SOCRATES: But it is, I think, the most sunlike of the sense organs.

 

GLAUCON: By far the most. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t it receive the power it has from the sun, just like an influx from an overflowing treasury?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: The sun is not sight either; yet as its cause, isn’t it seen by sight [10] itself?

 

GLAUCON: It is.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s say, then, that this is what I called the offspring of the good, which the good begot as its analogue. What the latter is in the intelligible [c] realm in relation to understanding and intelligible things, the former is in the visible realm in relation to sight and visible things.

 

GLAUCON: How? Tell me more.

 

SOCRATES: You know that when our eyes no longer turn to things whose [5] colors are illuminated by the light of day, but by the lights of night, they are dimmed and seem nearly blind, as if clear sight were no longer in them.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Yet I suppose that whenever they are turned to things illuminated [d] by the sun, they see clearly and sight is manifest in those very same eyes?

 

GLAUCON: Indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Well, think about the soul in the same way. When it focuses on [5] something that is illuminated both by truth and what is, it understands, knows, and manifestly possesses understanding. But when it focuses on what is mixed with obscurity, on what comes to be and passes away, it believes and is dimmed, changes its beliefs this way and that, and seems bereft of understanding.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes, it does seem like that.

 

[e] SOCRATES: You must say, then, that what gives truth to the things known and the power to know to the knower is the form of the good. And as the cause of knowledge and truth, you must think of it as an object of knowledge. Both knowledge and truth are beautiful things. But if you are to [5] think correctly, you must think of the good as other and more beautiful than they. In the visible realm, light and sight are rightly thought to be sun-like, [509a] but wrongly thought to be the sun. So, here it is right to think of knowledge and truth as goodlike, but wrong to think that either of them is [5] the good—for the status of the good is yet more honorable.

 

GLAUCON : It is an incredibly beautiful thing you are talking about, if it provides both knowledge and truth but is itself superior to them in beauty. I mean, you surely do not think that it could be pleasure.

 

SOCRATES: No words of ill omen, please! Instead, examine our analogy in [10] more detail.

 

[b] GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: The sun, I think you would say, not only gives visible things the power to be seen but also provides for their coming-to-be, growth, and nourishment—although it is not itself coming to be.

 

GLAUCON: I would. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, you should also say that not only do the objects of knowledge owe their being known to the good, but their existence and being are also due to it; although the good is not being, but something yet beyond being, superior to it in rank and power.

 

And Glaucon quite ridiculously replied:

 

By Apollo, what daimonic hyperbole! 37 [c]

 

SOCRATES: It is your own fault, you forced me to tell my beliefs about it.

 

GLAUCON: And don’t you stop, either—at least, not until you have finished [5] discussing the good’s similarity to the sun, if you are omitting anything.

 

SOCRATES: I am certainly omitting a lot.

 

GLAUCON: Well don’t, not even the smallest detail.

 

SOCRATES: I think I will have to omit a fair amount. All the same, as far as is now possible, I won’t purposely omit anything. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Please don’t.

 

SOCRATES: Then you should think, as we said, that there are these two things, one sovereign of the intelligible kind and place, the other of the visible—[d] I do not say “of heaven,” so as not to seem to you to be playing the sophist with the name.38 In any case, do you understand these two kinds, visible and intelligible?

 

GLAUCON: I do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Represent them, then, by a line divided into two unequal sections. Then divide each section—that of the visible kind and that of the intelligible—in the same proportion as the line.39 In terms now of relative clarity and opacity, you will have as one subsection of the visible, images. [e] By images I mean, first, shadows, then reflections in bodies of water and in [510a] all close-packed, smooth, and shiny materials, and everything of that sort. Do you understand?

 

GLAUCON: I do understand.

 

SOCRATES: Then, in the other subsection of the visible, put the originals [5] of these images—that is, the animals around us, every plant, and the whole class of manufactured things.

 

GLAUCON: I will.

 

SOCRATES: Would you also be willing to say, then, that, as regards truth and untruth, the division is in this ratio: as what is believed is to what is [10] known, so the likeness is to the thing it is like?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Next, consider how the section of the intelligible is to be divided.

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: As follows: in one subsection, the soul, using as images the things that were imitated before, is forced to base its inquiry on hypotheses, proceeding [5] not to a first principle, but to a conclusion. In the other subsection, by contrast, it makes its way to an unhypothetical first principle, proceeding from a hypothesis, but without the images used in the previous subsection, using forms themselves and making its investigation through them.

 

[10] GLAUCON: I do not fully understand what you are saying.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s try again.You see, you will understand it more easily after [c] this explanation. I think you know that students of geometry, calculation, and the like hypothesize the odd and the even, the various figures, the three kinds of angles, and other things akin to these in each of their investigations, [5] regarding them as known. These they treat as hypotheses and do not think it necessary to give any account of them, either to themselves or to others, as if they were evident to everyone. And going from these first principles [d] through the remaining steps, they arrive in full agreement at the point they set out to reach in their investigation.

 

GLAUCON: I certainly know that much.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Then don’t you also know that they use visible forms and make their arguments about them, although they are not thinking about them, but about those other things that they are like? They make their arguments with a view to the square itself and the diagonal itself, not the [e] diagonal they draw, and similarly with the others. The very things they make and draw, of which shadows and reflections in water are images, they now in turn use as images in seeking to see those other things themselves [511a] that one cannot see except by means of thought.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: This, then, is the kind of thing that I said was intelligible. The soul is forced to use hypotheses in the investigation of it, not traveling up to a first principle, since it cannot escape or get above its hypotheses, but using [5] as images those very things of which images were made by the things below them, and which, by comparison to their images, were thought to be clear and to be honored as such.

 

GLAUCON: I understand that you mean what is dealt with in geometry and [b] related crafts.

 

SOCRATES: Also understand, then, that by the other subsection of the intelligible I mean what reason itself40 grasps by the power of dialectical discussion, treating its hypotheses, not as first principles, but as genuine hypotheses (that is, stepping stones and links in a chain), in order to arrive [5] at what is unhypothetical and the first principle of everything. Having grasped this principle, it reverses itself and, keeping hold of what follows from it, comes down to a conclusion, making no use of anything visible at all, but only of forms themselves, moving on through forms to forms, and [c] ending in forms.

 

GLAUCON: I understand, though not adequately—you see, in my opinion you are speaking of an enormous task. You want to distinguish the part of what is and is intelligible, the part looked at by the science of dialectical discussion, as clearer than the part looked at by the so-called sciences—those [5] for which hypotheses are first principles. And although those who look at the latter part are forced to do so by means of thought rather than sense perception, still, because they do not go back to a genuine first principle in considering it, but proceed from hypotheses, you do not think that they have true understanding of them, even though—given such a first principle—they [5] are intelligible. And you seem to me to call the state of mind of the geometers—and the others of that sort—thought but not understanding; thought being intermediate between belief and understanding. [5]

 

SOCRATES: You have grasped my meaning most adequately. Join me, then, in taking these four conditions in the soul as corresponding to the four subsections of the line: understanding dealing with the highest, thought dealing with the second; assign belief to the third, and imagination to the last. [e] Arrange them in a proportion and consider that each shares in clarity to the degree that the subsection it deals with shares in truth.

 

GLAUCON: I understand, agree, and arrange them as you say. [5]

 

1 See 479d3–5 for what happens to conventions not established in this way.

2 See 539e2–540c2, 581c10–583a11.

3 See 474b3–c3.

4 See Glossary of Terms s.v. being.

5 See 474d3–475b2.

6 See Phaedo 64c10–67c3.

7Eikos: also, likeness.

8 See Glossary of Terms s.v. captain.

9 An intoxicant.

10 Aristotle, Rhetoric 1391a7–12, says that when Simonides was asked whether it was better to be rich or wise, he replied: “Rich—because the wise spend their time at the doors of the rich.”

11 487d10.

12 485c3.

13Autou ho estin hekastou tês phuseôs: literally, “the what it is of the nature of each thing itself.” See Glossary of Terms s.v. what it is.

14 See 611e1–612a6.

15 See Homer, Iliad 24.367.

16 I.e., rivals in the craft of teaching virtue. See Apology 24c–25c, Protagoras 317e– 328d, and Glossary of Terms s.v. sophist.

17 Chronou tribê: On the distinction between a craft (technê ) and an experience-based knack (tribê, empeiria ), see Gorgias 462b–465a.

18 An inescapable compulsion. The origin of the phrase is uncertain.

19 Plato seems to have had Alcibiades in mind here and in what follows. See Alcibiades 104a–c, 105b–c, Symposium 215d–216d. Alcibiades’ extraordinary career is described in Thucydides, Books 6–8.

20 The trial of Socrates in 399 BCE is the obvious case in point.

21 See 485d.

22 See Plato, Apology 31c–32a, where Socrates explains that his daimonion has kept him out of politics.

23 See 412a–b, which gives a hint of this need.

24 I.e., dialectic.

25 Heraclitus’ sun was extinguished at night but rekindled the next morning.

26 See 614b ff.

27 Plato is mocking the rhetoricians who were fond of forced rhyme. His own words ou gar pôpote eidon genomenon to nun legomenon—“they’ve never seen anything come into existence that matches our account”—exhibit the phenomenon he is mocking.

28 See, e.g., Iliad 1.131.

29 At 412b–414a.The conviction referred to is identified at 412e6.

30 434d–444e.

31 435d.

32 See 532a–534d.

33 Throughout, Socrates is punning on the word tokos, which means either a child or the interest on capital.

34 See 596b5–10.

35 See Glossary of Terms s.v. what it is.

36 Helios—the sun—was considered a god.

37 Socrates’ claim ends with the words dunamei huperechontas (“superior in . . .power”), Glaucon responds with the punning daimonias huperbolês . Hence the joke.

38 The play seems to be on the similarity of sound between orano (“heaven”) and orato (“visible”).

39 9781603842761_0240_001

40 Autos ho logos .

Book 7

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION CONTINUES:

SOCRATES: Next, then, compare the effect of education and that of the [514a] lack of it on our nature to an experience like this. Imagine human beings living in an underground, cavelike dwelling, with an entrance a long way up that is open to the light and as wide as the cave itself. They have been [5] there since childhood, with their necks and legs fettered, so that they are fixed in the same place, able to see only in front of them, because their fetter [b] prevents them from turning their heads around. Light is provided by a fire burning far above and behind them. Between the prisoners and the fire, there is an elevated road stretching. Imagine that along this road a low wall [5] has been built—like the screen in front of people that is provided by puppeteers, and above which they show their puppets.

 

GLAUCON: I am imagining it.

 

SOCRATES: Also imagine, then, that there are people alongside the wall [c] carrying multifarious artifacts that project above it—statues of people and [515a] other animals, made of stone, wood, and every material. And as you would expect, some of the carriers are talking and some are silent.

 

GLAUCON: It is a strange image you are describing, and strange prisoners.

 

[5] SOCRATES: They are like us. I mean, in the first place, do you think these prisoners have ever seen anything of themselves and one another besides the shadows that the fire casts on the wall of the cave in front of them?

 

GLAUCON: How could they, if they have to keep their heads motionless [b] throughout life?

 

SOCRATES: What about the things carried along the wall? Isn’t the same true where they are concerned?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And if they could engage in discussion with one another, don’t you think they would assume that the words they used applied to the [5] things they see passing in front of them?

 

GLAUCON: They would have to.

 

SOCRATES : What if their prison also had an echo from the wall facing them? When one of the carriers passing along the wall spoke, do you think they would believe that anything other than the shadow passing in front of them was speaking?

 

GLAUCON: I do not, by Zeus. [10]

 

SOCRATES: All in all, then, what the prisoners would take for true reality is nothing other than the shadows of those artifacts. [c]

 

GLAUCON: That’s entirely inevitable.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, then, what being released from their bonds and cured of their foolishness would naturally be like, if something like this [5] should happen to them. When one was freed and suddenly compelled to stand up, turn his neck around, walk, and look up toward the light, he would be pained by doing all these things and be unable to see the things whose shadows he had seen before, because of the flashing lights. What do you think he would say if we told him that what he had seen before was [d] silly nonsense, but that now—because he is a bit closer to what is, and is turned toward things that are more—he sees more correctly? And in particular, if we pointed to each of the things passing by and compelled him to answer what each of them is, don’t you think he would be puzzled and [5] believe that the things he saw earlier were more truly real than the ones he was being shown?

 

GLAUCON: Much more so.

 

SOCRATES: And if he were compelled to look at the light itself, wouldn’t [e] his eyes be pained and wouldn’t he turn around and flee toward the things he is able to see, and believe that they are really clearer than the ones he is being shown?

 

GLAUCON: He would. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And if someone dragged him by force away from there, along the rough, steep, upward path, and did not let him go until he had dragged him into the light of the sun, wouldn’t he be pained and angry at being treated that way? And when he came into the light, wouldn’t he have his [516a] eyes filled with sunlight and be unable to see a single one of the things now said to be truly real?

 

GLAUCON: No, he would not be able to—at least not right away.

 

SOCRATES: He would need time to get adjusted, I suppose, if he is going to see the things in the world above. At first, he would see shadows most [5] easily, then images of men and other things in water, then the things themselves. From these, it would be easier for him to go on to look at the things in the sky and the sky itself at night, gazing at the light of the stars and the moon, than during the day, gazing at the sun and the light of the sun. [b]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Finally, I suppose, he would be able to see the sun—not reflections [5] of it in water or some alien place, but the sun just by itself in its own place—and be able to look at it and see what it is like.

 

GLAUCON: He would have to.

 

SOCRATES: After that, he would already be able to conclude about it that [10] it provides the seasons and the years, governs everything in the visible [c] world, and is in some way the cause of all the things that he and his fellows used to see.

 

GLAUCON: That would clearly be his next step.

 

SOCRATES: What about when he reminds himself of his first dwelling place, what passed for wisdom there, and his fellow prisoners? Don’t you [5] think he would count himself happy for the change and pity the others?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And if there had been honors, praises, or prizes among them for the one who was sharpest at identifying the shadows as they passed by; [10] and was best able to remember which usually came earlier, which later, and [d] which simultaneously; and who was thus best able to prophesize the future, do you think that our man would desire these rewards or envy those among the prisoners who were honored and held power? Or do you think he would feel with Homer that he would much prefer to “work the earth as a [5] serf for another man, a man without possessions of his own,”1 and go through any sufferings, rather than share their beliefs and live as they do?

 

[e] GLAUCON: Yes, I think he would rather suffer anything than live like that.

 

SOCRATES: Consider this too, then. If this man went back down into the cave and sat down in his same seat, wouldn’t his eyes be filled with darkness, [5] coming suddenly out of the sun like that?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Now, if he had to compete once again with the perpetual prisoners in recognizing the shadows, while his sight was still dim and before [517a] his eyes had recovered, and if the time required for readjustment was not short, wouldn’t he provoke ridicule? Wouldn’t it be said of him that he had returned from his upward journey with his eyes ruined, and that it is not worthwhile even to try to travel upward? And as for anyone who tried to [5] free the prisoners and lead them upward, if they could somehow get their hands on him, wouldn’t they kill him?

 

GLAUCON: They certainly would.

 

SOCRATES: This image, my dear Glaucon, must be fitted together as a whole with what we said before. The realm revealed through sight should [b] be likened to the prison dwelling, and the light of the fire inside it to the sun’s power. And if you think of the upward journey and the seeing of things above as the upward journey of the soul to the intelligible realm, you won’t mistake my intention—since it is what you wanted to hear about. [5] Only the god knows whether it is true. But this is how these phenomena seem to me: in the knowable realm, the last thing to be seen is the form of the good, and it is seen only with toil and trouble. Once one has seen it, however, one must infer that it is the cause of all that is correct and beautiful [c] in anything, that in the visible realm it produces both light and its source, and that in the intelligible realm it controls and provides truth and understanding; and that anyone who is to act sensibly in private or public must see it. [5]

 

GLAUCON: I agree, so far as I am able.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, and join me in this further thought: you should not be surprised that the ones who get to this point are not willing to occupy themselves with human affairs, but that, on the contrary, their souls are always eager to spend their time above. I mean, that is surely what we would expect, if indeed the image I described before is also accurate here. [d]

 

GLAUCON: It is what we would expect.

 

SOCRATES: What about when someone, coming from looking at divine things, looks to the evils of human life? Do you think it is surprising that he behaves awkwardly and appears completely ridiculous, if—while his sight is [5] still dim and he has not yet become accustomed to the darkness around him—he is compelled, either in the courts or elsewhere, to compete about the shadows of justice, or about the statues of which they are the shadows; and to dispute the way these things are understood by people who have never seen justice itself? [e]

 

GLAUCON: It is not surprising at all.

 

SOCRATES: On the contrary, anyone with any sense, at any rate, would remember that eyes may be confused in two ways and from two causes: [518a] when they change from the light into the darkness, or from the darkness into the light. If he kept in mind that the same applies to the soul, then when he saw a soul disturbed and unable to see something, he would not [5] laugh absurdly. Instead, he would see whether it had come from a brighter life and was dimmed through not having yet become accustomed to the dark, or from greater ignorance into greater light and was dazzled by the increased brilliance. Then he would consider the first soul happy in its [b] experience and life, and pity the latter. But even if he wanted to ridicule it, at least his ridiculing it would make him less ridiculous than ridiculing a soul that had come from the light above.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s an entirely reasonable claim.

 

SOCRATES: Then here is how we must think about these matters, if that is true: education is not what some people boastfully profess it to be. They say that they can pretty much put knowledge into souls that lack it, [c] like putting sight into blind eyes.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they do say that.

 

SOCRATES: But here is what our present account shows about this power to [5] learn that is present in everyone’s soul, and the instrument with which each of us learns: just as an eye cannot be turned around from darkness to light except by turning the whole body, so this instrument must be turned around from what-comes-to-be together with the whole soul, until it is able [10] to bear to look at what is and at the brightest thing that is—the one we call [d] the good. Isn’t that right?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Of this then—of this very turning around—there would be a craft concerned with how this instrument can be most easily [5] and effectively turned around, not of putting sight into it. On the contrary, it takes for granted that sight is there, though not turned in the right way or looking where it should look, and contrives to redirect it appropriately.

 

GLAUCON: That’s probably right.

 

SOCRATES: The other so-called virtues of the soul then, do seem to be [10] closely akin to those of the body: they really are not present in it initially, [e] but are added later by habit and practice. The virtue of wisdom, on the other hand, belongs above all, so it seems, to something more godlike, which never loses its power, but is either useful and beneficial or useless and [519a] harmful, depending on the way it is turned. Or haven’t you ever noticed in people who are said to be bad, but clever, how sharp the vision of their little soul is and how sharply it distinguishes the things it is turned toward? This shows that its sight is not inferior, but is forced to serve vice, so that the [5] sharper it sees, the more evils it accomplishes.

 

GLAUCON: I certainly have.

 

SOCRATES: However, if this element of this sort of nature had been hammered at right from childhood, and struck free of the leaden weights, as it were, of kinship with becoming, which have been fastened to it by eating [b] and other such pleasures and indulgences, which pull its soul’s vision downward2—if, I say, it got rid of these and turned toward truly real things, then the same element of the same people would see them most sharply, just as it [5] now does the things it is now turned toward.

 

GLAUCON: That’s probably right.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it also probable, then—indeed, doesn’t it follow necessarily from what was said before—that uneducated people who have no experience of true reality will never adequately govern a city, and neither will people who have been allowed to spend their whole lives in education. The [c] former fail because they do not have a single goal in life at which all their actions, public and private, inevitably aim; the latter because they would refuse to act, thinking they had emigrated, while still alive, to the Isles of the Blessed. [5]

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: It is our task as founders, then, to compel the best natures to learn what was said before3 to be the most important thing: namely, to see the good; to ascend that ascent. And when they have ascended and looked [10] sufficiently, we must not allow them to do what they are allowed to do [d] now.

 

GLAUCON: What’s that, then?

 

SOCRATES: To stay there and refuse to go down again to the prisoners in the cave and share their labors and honors, whether the inferior ones or the [5] more excellent ones.

 

GLAUCON: You mean we are to treat them unjustly, making them live a worse life when they could live a better one?

 

SOCRATES: You have forgotten again, my friend, that the law is not concerned with making any one class in the city do outstandingly well, but is [e] contriving to produce this condition in the city as a whole, harmonizing the citizens together through persuasion or compulsion, and making them share with each other the benefit they can confer on the community.4 It [520a] produces such men in the city, not in order to allow them to turn in whatever direction each one wants, but to make use of them to bind the city together.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true.Yes, I had forgotten. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Observe, then, Glaucon, that we won’t be unjustly treating those who have become philosophers in our city, but that what we will say to them, when we compel them to take care of the others and guard them, will be just. We will say: “When people like you come to be in other cities, they are justified in not sharing in the others’ labors. After all, they have [b] grown there spontaneously, against the will of the constitution in each of them. And when something grows of its own accord and owes no debt for its upbringing, it has justice on its side when it is not keen to pay anyone for its upbringing. But both for your own sakes and for that of the rest of [5] the city, we have bred you to be leaders and kings in the hive, so to speak. You are better and more completely educated than the others, and better [c] able to share in both types of life.5 So each of you in turn must go down to live in the common dwelling place of the other citizens and grow accustomed to seeing in the dark. For when you are used to it, you will see infinitely better than the people there and know precisely what each image is, and also what it is an image of, because you have seen the truth about fine, [5] just, and good things. So the city will be awake, governed by us and by you; not dreaming like the majority of cities nowadays, governed by men who fight against one another over shadows and form factions in order to rule—[d] as if that were a great good.6 No, the truth of the matter is surely this: a city in which those who are going to rule are least eager to rule is necessarily best and freest from faction, whereas a city with the opposite kind of rulers is governed in the opposite way.”

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then do you think the people we have nurtured will disobey us when they hear these things, and be unwilling to share the labors of the city, each in turn, and wish instead to live the greater part of their time with one another in the pure realm?

 

GLAUCON: No, they couldn’t possibly. After all, we will be giving just [e] orders to just people. However, each of them will certainly go to rule as to something necessary, which is exactly the opposite of what is done by those who now rule in each city.

 

SOCRATES: That’s right, comrade. If you can find a way of life that is better [521a] than ruling for those who are going to rule, your well-governed city will become a possibility. You see, in it alone the truly rich will rule—those who are rich not in gold, but in the wealth the happy must have: namely, a good and rational life. But if beggars—people hungry for private goods of [5] their own—go into public life, thinking that the good is there for the seizing, then such a city is impossible. For when ruling is something fought over, such civil and domestic war destroys these men and the rest of the city as well.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Do you know of any other sort of life that looks down on [b] political offices besides that of true philosophy?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: But surely it is those who are not lovers of ruling who must go do it. Otherwise, the rivaling lovers will fight over it. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Who else, then, will you compel to go be guardians of the city if not those who know best what results in good government, and have different honors and a better life than the political? [10]

 

GLAUCON: No one else.

 

SOCRATES: Do you want us to consider now how such people will come [c] to exist, and how we will lead them up to the light, like those who are said to have gone up from Hades to the gods?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, of course that’s what I want.

 

SOCRATES: It seems, then, that this is not a matter of flipping a potsherd,7 [5] but of turning a soul from a day that is a kind of night in comparison to the true day—that ascent to what is, which we say is true philosophy.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then mustn’t we try to discover what subjects have the power [10] to bring this about? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So what subject is it, Glaucon, that draws the soul from what is coming to be to what is? It occurs to me as I am speaking that we said, didn’t we, that these people must be athletes of war when they are young?8 [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we did say that.

 

SOCRATES: Then the subject we are looking for must also have this characteristic in addition to the former one.

 

GLAUCON: Which? [10]

 

SOCRATES: It must not be useless to warlike men.

 

GLAUCON: If possible, it must not.

 

SOCRATES: Now, earlier they were educated by us in musical and physical training. [e]

 

GLAUCON: They were.

 

SOCRATES: And surely physical training is concerned with what-comes-to-be and dies, since it oversees the growth and decay of the body. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Obviously.

 

SOCRATES: So it could not be the subject we are looking for.

 

[522a] GLAUCON: No, it could not.

 

SOCRATES: Is it, then, the musical training we described before?

 

GLAUCON: But it is just the counterpart of physical training, if you remember. It educated the guardians through habits, conveying by harmony [5] a certain harmoniousness of temper, not knowledge; and by rhythm a certain rhythmical quality. Its stories, whether fictional or nearer the truth, cultivated other habits akin to these. But as for a subject that leads to the destination you have in mind, of the sort you are looking for now, there [b] was nothing of that in it.

 

SOCRATES: Your reminder is exactly to the point. It really does not have anything of that sort. You’re a marvelous fellow, Glaucon, but what is there [5] that does? The crafts all seemed to be somehow menial.9

 

GLAUCON: Of course. And yet, what subject is left that is separate from musical and physical training, and from the crafts?

 

SOCRATES: Well, if we have nothing left beyond these, let’s consider one of those that touches all of them.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Which?

 

SOCRATES: Why, for example, that common thing, the one that every [c] type of craft, thought, and knowledge uses, and that is among the first things everyone has to learn.

 

GLAUCON: Which one is that?

 

SOCRATES: That inconsequential matter of distinguishing the numbers [5] one, two, and three. In short, I mean number and calculation. Or isn’t it true that every type of craft and knowledge must share in them?

 

GLAUCON: Indeed it is.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Then warfare must too.

 

GLAUCON: It must.

 

SOCRATES: In tragedies, at any rate, Palamedes is always showing up [d] Agamemnon as a totally ridiculous general. Haven’t you noticed? He says that by inventing numbers he established how many troops there were in the army at Ilium and counted their ships and everything else. The implication [5] is that they had not been counted before, and that Agamemnon apparently did not even know how many feet he had, since he did not know how to count. What kind of general do you think that made him?

 

GLAUCON: A very strange one, I’d say, if there is any truth in that.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t we posit this subject, then, as one a warrior has to learn [e] so he can count and calculate?

 

GLAUCON: It is more essential than anything else—if, that is, he is going to know anything at all about marshaling his troops—or if he is even going to be human, for that matter.

 

SOCRATES: Then do you notice the same thing about this subject as I do? [5]

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: That in all likelihood it is one of the subjects we were looking for that naturally stimulate the understanding. But no one uses it correctly, [523a] as something that really is fitted in every way to draw us toward being.

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: I will try to make what I believe clear, at any rate. I will distinguish [5] for myself the things that lead in the direction we mentioned from those that do not. Then you must look at them along with me, and either agree or disagree, so that we may see more clearly whether the distinction is as I imagine.

 

GLAUCON: Show me the things you mean.

 

SOCRATES: All right, I will show you, if you can see that some sense-perceptions[10] do not summon the understanding to look into them, because [b] the judgment of sense-perception is itself adequate; whereas others encourage it in every way to look into them, because sense-perception does not produce a sound result.

 

GLAUCON: You are obviously referring to things appearing in the distance [5] and illusionist paintings.

 

SOCRATES: No, you are not quite getting what I mean.

 

GLAUCON: Then what do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The ones that do not summon the understanding are all those that do not at the same time result in an opposite sense-perception. But the ones that do I call summoners. That is when sense-perception does not make [c] one thing any more clear than its opposite, regardless of whether what strikes the senses is close by or far away. What I mean will be clearer if you look at it this way: these, we say, are three fingers—the smallest, the second, and the middle finger.[5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Assume that I am talking about them as being seen from close by. Now consider this about them with me.

 

GLAUCON: What? [10]

 

SOCRATES: It is obvious, surely, that each of them is equally a finger, and it [d] makes no difference whether it is seen to be in the middle or at either end; whether it is dark or pale, thick or thin, or anything else of that sort. You see, in all these cases, the soul of most people is not compelled to ask the understanding what a finger is, since sight does not at any point suggest to [5] it that a finger is at the same time the opposite of a finger.

 

GLAUCON: No, it does not.

 

SOCRATES: It is likely, then, that a perception of that sort would not summon [e] or awaken the understanding.

 

GLAUCON: It is likely.

 

SOCRATES: Now, what about their greatness and smallness? Does sight perceive them adequately? Does it make no difference to it whether one of them is in the middle or at the end? And is it the same with the sense of [5] touch, as regards thickness and thinness, hardness and softness? What about the other senses, then—do they make such things sufficiently clear? Or doesn’t each of them work as follows: in the first place, the sense that deals [524a] with hardness must also deal with softness; and it reports to the soul that it perceives the same thing to be both hard and soft?

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: In cases of this sort then, isn’t the soul inevitably puzzled as to what this sense-perception means by hardness, if it says that the same thing is also soft; and in the case of the sense-perception of lightness and heaviness, what it means lightness and heaviness are, if what is heavy is light and [10] what is light heavy?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Yes, indeed, those are strange messages for the soul to receive and do need to be examined.

 

SOCRATES: It is likely, then, that it is in cases of this sort that the soul, summoning calculation and understanding, first tries to determine whether [5] each of the things reported to it is one or two.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: If there are obviously two, won’t each of them be obviously one and distinct?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

[10] SOCRATES: If each of them is one, then, and both together are two, the soul will understand that the two are separate. I mean, it would not understand [c] inseparable things as two, but as one.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: But sight, we say, saw greatness and smallness, not as separate, but as mixed up together. Right?

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And to get clear about this, understanding was compelled to see greatness and smallness, too, not mixed up together, but distinguished—the opposite way from sight.

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it in cases like this that it first occurs to us to ask what [10] greatness is, and smallness, too?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Which is why we called one section the intelligible and the other the visible.

 

GLAUCON: Right. [d]

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is what I was trying to express before when I said that some things summon thought, while others do not. I define summoners as those that strike the relevant sense at the same time as do their opposites. Those that do not do this, I said, do not wake up the understanding. [5]

 

GLAUCON: I understand now, and I think you are right.

 

SOCRATES: Well then, to which of them does number, including the number one, belong?

 

GLAUCON: I do not know.

 

SOCRATES: Use what has already been said as an analogy. If the number one is adequately seen just by itself, or grasped by any of the other senses, [10] then just as we were saying in the case of fingers, it would not draw the soul [e] toward being. But if something opposite to it is always seen at the same time, so that it no more appears to be one than the opposite of one, then there would be a need at that point for someone to decide the matter. And he would compel the soul within him to be puzzled, to inquire, to stir up the understanding within itself, and to ask what the number one itself is. [5] So, learning about the number one will be among the subjects that lead the soul and turn it around to look at what is. [525a]

 

GLAUCON: But surely the visual perception of it has just that feature, since we do see the same thing as one and as an unlimited number at the same time. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then if this is true of the number one, won’t it also be true of all numbers?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But now, calculation and arithmetic are wholly concerned with numbers. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Right.

 

[b] SOCRATES: Then they obviously lead toward truth.

 

GLAUCON: To an unnatural degree.

 

SOCRATES: Then they would belong, it seems, among the subjects we are seeking. I mean, a soldier must learn them in order to marshal his troops; and a philosopher, because it is necessary to be rising up out of becoming [5] so as to grasp being, or he will never become able to calculate.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And our guardian is, in fact, both a warrior and a philosopher.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then it would be appropriate, Glaucon, to prescribe this subject in our legislation and to persuade those who are going to take part in [c] the greatest things in the city to go in for calculation and take it up, not as laymen do, but staying with it until they reach the point at which they see the nature of the numbers by means of understanding itself; not like tradesmen and retailers, caring about it for the sake of buying and selling, but for the sake of war and for ease in turning the soul itself around [5] from becoming to truth and being.

 

GLAUCON: Very well put.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, it occurs to me now that the subject of calculation has been mentioned, how refined it is and in how many ways it is useful for [d] our purposes, provided you practice it for the sake of knowledge rather than trade.

 

GLAUCON: Which ways?

 

SOCRATES: Why, in the very one we were talking about just now. It gives [5] the soul a strong lead upward and compels it to discuss the numbers themselves, never permitting anyone to propose for discussion numbers attached to visible or tangible bodies. I mean, you surely know what people who are clever in these matters are like. If, in the course of the argument, someone [e] tries to divide the number one itself, they laugh and won’t permit it. If you divide it, they multiply it, taking care that the number one never appears to be, not one, but many parts.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s very true.

 

SOCRATES: Then what do you think would happen, Glaucon, if someone [526a] were to ask them: “What kind of numbers are you amazing fellows discussing, where the number one is as you assume it to be, wholly equal in each and every case, without the least difference, and having no internal parts?” [5] What do you think they would answer?

 

GLAUCON: I think they would answer that they are talking about those that are accessible only to thought and can be grasped in no other way.

 

SOCRATES: Do you see then, my friend, that this subject really does seem to be necessary to us, since it apparently compels the soul to use understanding [b] itself on the truth itself?

 

GLAUCON: It does so very strongly, in fact.

 

SOCRATES: Now, have you ever noticed that those who are naturally good at calculation are also naturally quick in all subjects, so to speak, and that [5] those who are slow, if they are educated and exercised in it, even if they are benefited in no other way, nonetheless improve and become generally sharper than they were?

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, I do not think you will easily find many subjects that are harder to learn or practice than it. [c]

 

GLAUCON: No indeed.

 

SOCRATES : For all these reasons, then, this subject is not to be neglected. On the contrary, the very best natures must be educated in it. [5]

 

GLAUCON: I agree.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, let’s require that one. Second, let’s consider whether the subject that follows after it is also appropriate for our purposes.

 

GLAUCON: Which one? Or do you mean geometry? [10]

 

SOCRATES: That’s it exactly.

 

GLAUCON: Insofar as it pertains to war, it is clearly appropriate. You see, [d] when it comes to setting up camp, occupying a region, gathering and ordering troops, and all the other maneuvers armies make whether in battle itself or on the march, it makes all the difference whether someone is skilled in geometry or not. [5]

 

SOCRATES: But still, for things like that, even a little bit of geometry—and of calculation—would suffice. What we need to consider is whether the greater and more advanced part of it tends to make it easier to see the form of the good. And that tendency, we say, is to be found in anything that compels [e] the soul to turn itself around toward the region in which lies the happiest of the things that are; the one the soul must do everything possible to see.

 

GLAUCON: You are right. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, if geometry compels one to look at being, it is appropriate; but if at becoming, it is inappropriate.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s what we are saying.

 

SOCRATES: Now, no one with even a little experience of geometry will [527a] dispute with us that this science is itself entirely the opposite of what is said about it in the accounts of its practitioners.

 

[5] GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: Well, they say completely ridiculous things about it because they are so hard up. I mean, they talk as if they were practical people who make all their arguments for the sake of action. They talk of squaring, applying, adding, and the like; whereas, in fact, the entire subject is practiced [b] for the sake of acquiring knowledge.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Mustn’t we also agree on a further point?

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

[5] SOCRATES: That it is knowledge of what always is, not of something that comes to be and passes away.

 

GLAUCON: That’s easy to agree to, since geometry is knowledge of what always is.

 

SOCRATES: In that case, my noble fellow, it can draw the soul toward truth [10] and produce philosophical thought by directing upward what we now wrongly direct downward.

 

GLAUCON: More than anything else.

 

[c] SOCRATES: More than anything else, then, we must require the inhabitants of your beautiful city not to neglect geometry in any way, since even its byproducts are not insignificant.

 

GLAUCON: What are they?

 

[5] SOCRATES: The ones you mentioned that are concerned with war. And in addition, when it comes to being better able to pick up any subject, we surely know there is a world of difference between someone with a grasp of geometry and someone without one.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, a world of difference.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Shall we prescribe it, then, as a second subject for the young?

 

GLAUCON: Let’s.

 

SOCRATES: What about astronomy? Shall we make it the third? What do [d] you think?

 

GLAUCON: That’s fine with me, at least. I mean, a better awareness of the seasons, months, and years is no less appropriate for a general than for a farmer or navigator.

 

SOCRATES: You are funny! You are like someone who is afraid that the [5] masses will think he is prescribing useless subjects. It is no inconsequential task—indeed it is a very difficult one—to become persuaded that in everyone’s soul there is an instrument that is purified and rekindled by such subjects [e] when it has been blinded and destroyed by other pursuits—an instrument that it is more important to preserve than 10,000 eyes, since only with it can the truth be seen. Those who share your belief that this is so will think you are speaking incredibly well, while those who are completely unaware of it will probably think you are talking nonsense, since [5] they can see no other benefit worth mentioning in these subjects. So, decide right now which group you are engaging in discussion. Or is it neither of them, and are you making your arguments mostly for your own [528a] sake—though you do not begrudge anyone else whatever profit he can get from them?

 

GLAUCON: That’s what I prefer—to speak, question, and answer mostly for my own sake. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Let’s backtrack a bit. You see, we were wrong just now about the subject that comes after geometry.

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: After a plain surface, we went immediately to a solid that was revolving, without taking one just by itself. But the right way is to take up [b] the third dimension after the second. And it, I suppose, consists of cubes and of whatever shares in depth.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, you are right. But Socrates, that subject has not even been investigated yet. [5]

 

SOCRATES: There are two reasons for that. Because no city values it, it is not vigorously investigated, due to its difficulty. And investigators need a director if they are to discover anything. Now, in the first place, such a director is difficult to find. Second, even if he could be found, as things stand now, those who investigate it are too arrogant to obey him. But if an [c] entire city served as his co-director and took the lead in valuing this subject, then they would obey him, and consistent and vigorous investigation would reveal the facts about it. For even now, when it is not valued by the masses and is hampered by investigators who lack any account of its usefulness—all [5] the same, in spite of all these handicaps, the force of its appeal has caused it to be developed. So it would not be at all surprising if the facts about it were revealed in any case.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed, it is an outstandingly appealing subject. But [d] explain more clearly to me what you were saying just now.You took geometry, presumably, as dealing with plane surface.

 

SOCRATES: Yes.

 

GLAUCON: Then at first you put astronomy after it, but later you went [5] back on that.

 

SOCRATES : Yes, the more I hurried to get through them all, the slower I went! You see, the subject dealing with the dimension of depth was next. But because of the ridiculous state the investigation of it is in, I passed it by and spoke of astronomy—which deals with the motion of things having [e] depth—after geometry.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s then prescribe astronomy as the fourth subject, on the assumption that solid geometry, which we are now omitting, will be available [5] if a city takes it up.

 

GLAUCON: That seems reasonable. And since you reproached me just now, Socrates, for praising astronomy in a vulgar manner, I will now praise it [529a] your way. You see, I think it is clear to everyone that it compels the soul to look upward and leads it from things here to things there.

 

SOCRATES: It is clear to everyone except me, then, since that is not how I think of it.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Then how do you think of it?

 

SOCRATES: As it is handled today by those who teach philosophy, it makes the soul look very much downward.

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: In my opinion, your conception of “higher studies” is a good [10] deal too generous! I mean, if someone were looking at something by leaning[b] his head back and studying ornaments on a ceiling, it seems as though you would say that he is looking at them with his understanding, not with his eyes! Maybe you are right and I am foolish. You see, I just cannot conceive of any subject making the soul look upward except the one that is [5] concerned with what is—and that is invisible. If anyone tries to learn something about perceptible things, whether by gaping upward or squinting downward, I would say that he never really learns—since there is no knowledge to be had of such things—and that his soul is not looking up but [c] down, whether he does his learning lying on his back on land or on sea!

 

GLAUCON: A fair judgment! You are right to reproach me. But what did you mean, then, when you said that astronomy must be learned in a different [5] way than people learn it at present, if it is going to be useful with regard to what we are talking about?

 

SOCRATES: It is like this: these ornaments in the heavens, since they are ornaments in something visible, may certainly be regarded as having the most beautiful and most exact motions that such things can have. But these [d] fall far short of the true ones—those motions in which the things that are really fast or really slow, as measured in true numbers and as forming all the true geometrical figures, are moved relative to one another, and that move the things that are in them. And these, of course, must be grasped by reason [5] and thought, not by sight. Don’t you agree?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, we should use the ornaments in the heavens as models to help us study these other things.10 It is just as if someone chanced to find diagrams by Daedalus or some other craftsman or painter, which were [e] very carefully drawn and worked out. I mean, anyone experienced in geometry who saw such things would consider them to be very beautifully executed, I suppose. But he would think it ridiculous to examine them seriously in order to find there the truth about equals, doubles, or any other ratio. [530a]

 

GLAUCON: How could it be anything but ridiculous?

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you think, then, that a real astronomer will feel the same way when he looks at the motions of the stars? He will believe that the craftsman of the heavens arranged them and all that is in them in the [5] most beautiful way possible for such things. But as for the ratio of night to day, of these to a month, of a month to a year, or of the motions of the stars to them or to each other, don’t you think he will consider it strange to [b] believe that they are always the same and never deviate in the least, since they are connected to body and are visible things, or to seek by every means possible to grasp the truth about them?

 

GLAUCON: That’s what I think—anyway, now that I hear it from you! [5]

 

SOCRATES: Just as in geometry, then, it is by making use of problems that we will pursue astronomy too. We will leave the things in the heavens alone, if we are really going to participate in astronomy and make the naturally wise element in the soul useful instead of useless. [c]

 

GLAUCON: The task you are prescribing is a lot greater than anything now attempted in astronomy.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose we will prescribe other subjects in the same way, if we are to be of any benefit as lawgivers. But can you in fact suggest [5] any other appropriate subjects?

 

GLAUCON: Not at the moment, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: But motion, it seems to me, presents itself, not just in one form, but in several. A wise person could probably list them all, but there are two that are evident even to us. [d]

 

GLAUCON: What are they?

 

SOCRATES: Besides the one we have discussed, there is also its counterpart.

 

GLAUCON: What’s that? [5]

 

SOCRATES: It is probable that as the eyes fasten on astronomical motions, so the ears fasten on harmonic ones, and that these two sciences are somehow akin, as the Pythagoreans say. And we agree, Glaucon. Don’t we? [10]

 

GLAUCON: We do.

 

[e] SOCRATES: Then, since the task is so huge, shouldn’t we ask them their opinion and whether they have anything to add, all the while guarding our own requirement?

 

GLAUCON: What’s that?

 

SOCRATES: That those we will be rearing should never attempt to learn [5] anything incomplete,11 anything that does not always come out at the place all things should reach—the one we mentioned just now in the case of astronomy.12 Or don’t you know that people do something similar with [531a] harmony, too? They measure audible concordances and sounds against one another, and so labor in vain, just like astronomers.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, by the gods, and pretty ridiculous they are, too. They talk about something they call a “dense interval” or quarter tone13—putting [5] their ears to their instruments, like someone trying to overhear what the neighbors are saying. And some say they hear a tone in between, and that it is the shortest interval by which they must measure, while others argue that this tone sounds the same as a quarter tone. Both groups put ears before the [b] understanding.

 

SOCRATES: You mean those excellent fellows who vex their strings, torturing them and stretching them on pegs. I won’t draw out the analogy by [5] speaking of blows with the pick, or the charges laid against strings that are too responsive or too unresponsive. Instead, I will drop the analogy and say that I do not mean these people, but the ones we just said we were going to question about harmonics. You see, they do the same as the astronomers do.[c] I mean, it is in these audible concordances that they search for numbers, but they do not ascend to problems or investigate which numbers are in concord and which are not, or what the explanation is in each case.

 

[5] GLAUCON: But that would be a daimonic task!

 

SOCRATES : Yet, it is useful in the search for the beautiful and the good! Pursued for any other purpose, though, it is useless.

 

GLAUCON: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, I take it that if the investigation of all the subjects we have mentioned arrives at what they share in common with one [d] another and what their affinities are, and draws conclusions about their kinship, it does contribute something to our goal and is not labor in vain; but that otherwise it is in vain.

 

GLAUCON: I have the same hunch myself. But you are still talking about a very great task, Socrates. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Do you mean the prelude, or what? Or don’t you know that all these subjects are merely preludes to the theme14 itself that must be learned? I mean, you surely do not think that people who are clever in these matters are dialecticians. [e]

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, I do not. Although, I have met a few exceptions.

 

SOCRATES: But did it ever seem to you that those who can neither give an account nor approve one know what any of the things are that we say they must know? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Again, the answer is no.

 

SOCRATES: Then isn’t this at last, Glaucon, the theme itself that dialectical [532a] discussion sings? It itself is intelligible. But the power of sight imitates it. We said that sight tries at last to look at the animals themselves, the stars themselves, and, in the end, at the sun itself.15 In the same way, whenever someone [5] tries, by means of dialectical discussion and without the aid of any sense-perceptions, to arrive through reason at the being of each thing itself, and does not give up until he grasps what good itself is16 with understanding itself, he reaches the end of the intelligible realm, just as the other [b] reached the end of the visible one.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, don’t you call this journey17 dialectic?

 

GLAUCON: I do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then the release from bonds and the turning around from shadows to statues and the light; and then the ascent out of the cave to the sun; and there the continuing inability to look directly at the animals, the plants, and the light of the sun, but instead at divine reflections in water and shadows of the things that are, and not, as before, merely at shadows of statues [c] thrown by another source of light that, when judged in relation to the sun, is as shadowy as they—all this practice of the crafts we mentioned has the power to lead the best part of the soul upward until it sees the best [5] among the things that are, just as before the clearest thing in the body was led to the brightest thing in the bodily and visible world. [d]

 

GLAUCON : I accept that this is so. And yet, I think it is very difficult to accept; although—in another way—difficult not to accept! All the same, since the present occasion is not our only opportunity to hear these things, [5] but we will get to return to them often in the future, let’s assume that what you said about them just now is true and turn to the theme itself, and discuss it in the same way as we did the prelude. So, tell us then, in what way the power of dialectical discussion works, into what kinds it is divided, and what roads it follows. I mean, it is these, it seems, that would lead us at last [e] to that place which is a rest from the road, so to speak, for the one who reaches it, and an end of his journey.

 

SOCRATES: You won’t be able to follow me any farther, my dear Glaucon—though [533a] not because of any lack of eagerness on my part. You would no longer see an image of what we are describing, but the truth itself as it seems to me, at least.18 Whether it is really so or not—that’s not something on which it is any longer worth insisting. But that there is some such thing [5] to be seen, that is something on which we must insist. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t we also insist that the power of dialectical discussion could reveal it only to someone experienced in the subjects we [10] described, and cannot do so in any other way?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that is worth insisting on, too.

 

[b] SOCRATES: At the very least, no one will dispute our claim by arguing that there is another road of inquiry that tries to acquire a systematic and wholly general grasp of what each thing itself is. By contrast, all the other crafts are concerned with human beliefs and appetites, with growing or construction, [5] or with the care of growing or constructed things. As for the rest, we described them as to some extent grasping what is—I mean, geometry and the subjects that follow it. For we saw that while they do dream about what is, they cannot see it while wide awake as long as they make use of hypotheses [c] that they leave undisturbed, and for which they cannot give any account. After all, when the first principle is unknown, and the conclusion and the steps in between are put together out of what is unknown, what mechanism could possibly turn any agreement reached in such cases into [5] knowledge?19

 

GLAUCON: None.

 

SOCRATES: Therefore, dialectic is the only investigation that, doing away [d] with hypotheses, journeys to the first principle itself in order to be made secure. And when the eye of the soul is really buried in a sort of barbaric bog,20 dialectic gently pulls it out and leads it upward, using the crafts we described to help it and cooperate with it in turning the soul around. From force of habit, we have often called these branches of knowledge. But they need another name, since they are clearer than belief and darker than [5] knowledge. We distinguished them by the term “thought” somewhere before.21 But I don’t suppose we will dispute about names, with matters as important as those before us to investigate. [e]

 

GLAUCON: Of course not, just as long as they express the state of clarity the soul possesses. [5]

 

SOCRATES: It will be satisfactory, then, to do what we did before and call the first section knowledge, the second thought, the third opinion, and the fourth imagination. The last two together we call belief, the other two, [534a] understanding.22 Belief is concerned with becoming; understanding with being. And as being is to becoming, so understanding is to belief; and as understanding is to belief, so knowledge is to belief and thought to imagination. But as for the ratios between the things these deal with, and the [5] division of either the believable or the intelligible section into two, let’s pass them by, Glaucon, in case they involve us in discussions many times longer than the ones we have already gone through.

 

GLAUCON: I agree with you about the rest of them, anyway, insofar as I am able to follow. [b]

 

SOCRATES: So don’t you, too, call someone a dialectician when he is able to grasp an account of the being of each thing? And when he cannot do so, won’t you, too, say that to the extent that he cannot give an account of something either to himself or to another, to that extent he does not understand it? [5]

 

GLAUCON: How could I not?

 

SOCRATES: Then the same applies to the good. Unless someone can give an account of the form of the good, distinguishing it from everything else, and can survive all examination as if in a battle, striving to examine23 things [c] not in accordance with belief, but in accordance with being; and can journey through all that with his account still intact, you will say that he does not know the good itself or any other good whatsoever. And if he does manage to grasp some image of it, you will say that it is through belief, not [5] knowledge, that he grasps it; that he is dreaming and asleep throughout his present life; and that, before he wakes up here, he will arrive in Hades and [d] go to sleep forever.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, by Zeus, I will certainly say all that.

 

SOCRATES: Then as for those children of yours, the ones you are rearing and educating in your discussion, if you ever reared them in fact, I don’t suppose that, while they are still as irrational as the proverbial lines,24 you [5] would allow them to rule in your city or control the greatest things.

 

GLAUCON: No, of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t you prescribe in your legislation, then, that they are to give the most attention to the education that will enable them to ask and [10] answer questions most knowledgeably?

 

[e] GLAUCON: I will prescribe it—together with you.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t it seem to you, then, that dialectic is just like a capstone we have placed on top of the subjects, and that no other subject can rightly be placed above it, but that our account of the subjects has now [535a] come to an end?

 

GLAUCON: It does.

 

SOCRATES: Then it remains for you to deal with the distribution of these subjects: to whom we will assign them and in what way.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Do you remember what sort of people we chose in our earlier selection of rulers?25

 

GLAUCON: How could I not?

 

SOCRATES: Well then, as regards the other requirements too, you must suppose that these same natures are to be chosen, since we have to select [10] the most secure, the most courageous, and—as far as possible—the best-looking.26 In addition, we must look not only for people who have a noble [b] and valiant character, but for those who also have natural qualities conducive to this education of ours.

 

GLAUCON: Which ones in particular?

 

[5] SOCRATES: They must be keen on the subjects, bless you, and learn them without difficulty. For people’s souls are much more likely to give up during strenuous studies than during physical training. The pain is more their own, you see, since it is peculiar to them and not shared with the body.

 

GLAUCON: That’s true. [10]

 

SOCRATES: We must also look for someone who has a good memory, is persistent, and is wholeheartedly in love with hard work. How else do you [c] suppose he would be willing to carry out such hard physical labors and also complete so much learning and training?

 

GLAUCON: He would not, not unless his nature were an entirely good one.

 

SOCRATES: In any case, the mistake made at present—which, as we said [5] before, explains why philosophy has fallen into dishonor—is that unworthy people take it up. For illegitimate people should not have taken it up, but genuine ones.

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: In the first place, the one who takes it up must not be halfhearted in his love of hard work, with one half of him loving hard work and the other shirking it. That is what happens when someone is a lover of [d] physical training and a lover of hunting and a lover of all kinds of hard bodily labor; yet is not a lover of learning, a lover of listening, or a keen investigator, but hates the work involved in all such things. And someone [5] whose love of hard work tends in the opposite direction is also defective.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Similarly with regard to truth, won’t we say that a soul is maimed if it hates a voluntary lie, cannot endure to have one in itself, and is [e] greatly angered when others lie; but is nonetheless content to accept an involuntary lie, does not get irritated when it is caught being ignorant, and bears its ignorance easily, wallowing in it like a pig?27 [5]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely. [536a]

 

SOCRATES: And with regard to temperance, courage, high-mindedness, and all the other parts of virtue, too, we must be especially on our guard to distinguish the illegitimate from the genuine. You see, when private individuals or cities do not know how to investigate all these things fully, they [5] unwittingly employ defectives and illegitimates as their friends or rulers for whatever services they happen to need.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s just what happens.

 

SOCRATES: So we must take good care in all these matters, since, if we bring people who are sound of limb and mind to so important a subject, [b] and train and educate them in it, justice itself will not find fault with us, and we will save both the city and its constitution. But if we bring people of a different sort to it, we will achieve precisely the opposite and let loose [5] an even greater flood of ridicule upon philosophy as well.

 

GLAUCON: That would be a shame.

 

SOCRATES: It certainly would. But I seem to have made myself a little ridiculous just now.

 

GLAUCON: In what way?

 

[c] SOCRATES: I forgot we were playing and spoke too vehemently. You see, while I was speaking I looked upon philosophy, and when I saw it undeservedly showered with abuse, I suppose I got irritated and, as if I were angry with those responsible, I said what I had to say in too serious a [5] manner.

 

GLAUCON: Not too serious for me, by Zeus, as a member of the audience.

 

SOCRATES: But too serious for me as the speaker. In any case, let’s not forget that in our earlier selection we chose older people, but here that is not [d] permitted. You see, we must not believe Solon when he says that as someone grows older, he is able to learn a lot. On the contrary, he is even less able to learn than to run. It is to young people that all great and frequent labors properly belong.

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily so.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Well, then, calculation, geometry, and all the preparatory education that serves as preparation for dialectic must be offered to them in childhood—and not in the shape of compulsory instruction, either.

 

GLAUCON: Why’s that?

 

[e] SOCRATES: Because a free person should learn nothing slavishly. For while compulsory physical labors do no harm to the body, no compulsory instruction remains in the soul.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, do not use compulsion, my very good man, to train the children in these subjects; use play instead. That way you will also [537a] be able to see better what each of them is naturally suited for.

 

GLAUCON: What you say makes sense.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you remember that we also said that the children were [5] to be led into war on horseback as observers, and that, wherever it is safe, they should be brought to the front and given a taste of blood, just like young dogs?

 

GLAUCON: I do remember.

 

SOCRATES: Those who always show the greatest facility in dealing with all [10] these labors, studies, and fears must be enrolled in a unit.

 

GLAUCON : At what age? [b]

 

SOCRATES : After they are released from compulsory physical training. For during that period, whether it is two or three years, they are incapable of doing anything else, since weariness and sleep are enemies of learning. At the same time, one of the important tests of each of them is how he fares in [5] physical training.

 

GLAUCON : It certainly is.

 

SOCRATES : Then, after that period, those selected from among the twenty-year-olds will receive greater honors than the others. Moreover, the subjects they learned in no particular order in their education as children, [c] they must now bring together into a unified vision of their kinship with one another and with the nature of what is.

 

GLAUCON : That, at any rate, is the only instruction that remains secure in those who receive it. [5]

 

SOCRATES : It is also the greatest test of which nature is dialectical and which is not. For the person who can achieve a unified vision is dialectical, and the one who cannot isn’t.

 

GLAUCON : I agree.

 

SOCRATES : Well, then, you will have to look out for those among them who most possess that quality; who are resolute in their studies and also resolute [d] in war and the other things conventionally expected of them. And when they have passed their thirtieth year, you will have to select them in turn from among those selected earlier and assign them yet greater honors, and test them by means of the power of dialectical discussion to see which of them can relinquish his eyes and other senses, and travel on in the company [5] of truth to what itself is. And here, comrade, you have a task that needs a lot of safeguarding.

 

GLAUCON : How so?

 

SOCRATES : Don’t you realize the harm caused by dialectical discussion as [e] it is currently practiced?

 

GLAUCON : What harm?

 

SOCRATES : Its practitioners are filled with lawlessness.

 

GLAUCON : They certainly are. [5]

 

SOCRATES : Do you think it is at all surprising that this happens to them? Aren’t you sympathetic?

 

GLAUCON : Why should I be?

 

SOCRATES : It is like the case of a supposititious child brought up amid large wealth, a great and powerful family, and many flatterers, who finds [538a] out, when he has become a man, that he is not the child of his professed parents and that he cannot discover his real ones. Do you have any hunch as to what his attitude would be to the flatterers, and to his supposed parents, [5] during the time when he did not know about the exchange, and, on the other hand, when he did know? Or would you rather hear my hunch?

 

GLAUCON: I would.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, my hunch is that he would be more likely to [b] honor his father, his mother, and the rest of his supposed family than the flatterers, less likely to overlook any of their needs, less likely to treat them lawlessly in word or deed, and less likely to disobey them than the flatterers [5] tters of importance, in the time when he did not know the truth.

 

GLAUCON: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: But when he became aware of the truth, on the other hand, my hunch is that he would withdraw his honor and devotion from his family and increase them for the flatterers, whom he would obey far more than before, and he would begin to live the way they did, spend time with them [c] openly, and—unless he was thoroughly good by nature—care nothing for that father of his or any of the rest of his supposed family.

 

GLAUCON: All that would probably happen as you say. But how is it like [5] the case of those who take up argument?

 

SOCRATES: As follows. I take it we hold from childhood convictions about what things are just and fine; we are brought up with them as with our parents; we obey and honor them.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we do.

 

[d] SOCRATES: And there are also other practices, opposite to those, which possess pleasures that flatter our soul and attract it to themselves, but which do not persuade people who are at all moderate—who continue to honor and obey the convictions of their fathers.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: What happens, then, when someone of that sort is met by the question, “What is the fine?” and, when he answers what he has heard from the traditional lawgiver, the argument refutes him; and by refuting him often and in many ways, reduces him to the belief that the fine is no more [e] fine than shameful, and the same with the just, the good, and the things he honored most—what do you think he will do after that about honoring and obeying his earlier convictions?

 

GLAUCON: It is inevitable that he won’t honor or obey them in the same way.

 

SOCRATES: Then when he no longer regards them as honorable or as his [5] own kin the way he did before, and cannot discover the true ones, will he [539a] be likely to adopt any other sort of life than the one that flatters him?

 

GLAUCON: No, he won’t.

 

SOCRATES: And so he will be taken, I suppose, to have changed from being law-abiding to being lawless.

 

GLAUCON: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it likely, then, that this is what will happen to people who take up argument in that way, and, as I said just now, don’t they deserve a [5] lot of sympathy?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, and pity too.

 

SOCRATES: Then if you do not want your thirty-year-olds to be objects of such pity, won’t you have to employ every sort of precaution when they take up argument?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, indeed. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t one very effective precaution not to let them taste [b] argument while they are young? I mean, I don’t suppose it has escaped your notice that when young people get their first taste of argument, they misuse it as if it were playing a game, always using it for disputation.28 They imitate those who have refuted them by refuting others themselves,29 and, like [5] puppies, enjoy dragging and tearing with argument anyone within reach.

 

GLAUCON: Excessively so.

 

SOCRATES: Then, when they have refuted many themselves and been refuted by many, they quickly fall into violently disbelieving everything [c] they believed before. And as a result of this, they themselves and the whole of philosophy as well are discredited in the eyes of others.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: But an older person would not be willing to take part in such [5] madness. He will imitate someone who is willing to engage in dialectical discussion and look for the truth, rather than someone who plays at disputation as a game. He will be more moderate himself and will bring honor, rather than discredit, to the practice. [d]

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And wasn’t everything we said before this also said as a precaution—that those with whom one takes part in arguments are to be orderly and steady by nature, and not, as now, those, however unsuitable, who [5] chance to come along?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it was.

 

SOCRATES: Is it enough, then, if someone devotes himself continuously and strenuously to taking part in argument, doing nothing else, but training in it just as he did in the physical training that is its counterpart, but for [10] twice as many years?

 

[e] GLAUCON: Do you mean six years or four?

 

SOCRATES: It does not matter. Make it five. You see, after that, you must make them go down into the cave again, and compel them to take command in matters of war and the other offices suitable for young people, so that they won’t be inferior to the others in experience. And in these offices, [5] too, they must be tested to see whether they will remain steadfast when [540a] they are pulled in different directions, or give way.

 

GLAUCON: How much time do you assign to that?

 

SOCRATES: Fifteen years. Then, at the age of fifty, those who have survived [5] the tests and are entirely best in every practical task and every science must be led at last to the end and compelled to lift up the radiant eye–beams of their souls, and to look toward what itself provides light for everything. And once they have seen the good itself, they must use it as their model and put the city, its citizens, and themselves in order throughout the remainder of [b] their lives, each in turn. They will spend most of their time doing philosophy, but, when his turn comes, each must labor in politics and rule for the city’s sake, not as something fine, but rather as something that must be [5] done.30 In that way, always having educated others like themselves to take their place as guardians of the city, they will depart for the Isles of the Blessed and dwell there. And the city will publicly establish memorials and [c] sacrifices to them as daimons,31 if the Pythia agrees; but if not, as happy and divine people.

 

GLAUCON: Like a sculptor,32 Socrates, you have produced thoroughly beautiful ruling men!

 

[5] SOCRATES: And ruling women, too, Glaucon.You see, you must not think that what I have said applies any more to men than it does to those women of theirs who are born with the appropriate natures.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right, if indeed they are to share everything equally with the men, as we said.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, do you agree that the things we have said about [d] the city and its constitution are not altogether wishful thinking; that it is difficult for them to come about, but possible in a way, and in no way except the one we described: namely, when one or more true philosophers come to power in a city—people who think little of present honors, regarding them as illiberal and worthless, who prize what is right and the [5] honors that come from it above everything, and who consider justice as the [e] greatest and most compulsory thing, serving it and fostering it as they set their city in order?

 

GLAUCON: How will they do that?

 

SOCRATES: Everyone in the city who is over ten years old they will send [5] into the country. They will take over the children, and far removed from [541a] current habits, which their parents possess, they will bring them up in their own ways and laws, which are the ones we described before. And with the city and constitution we were discussing thus established in the quickest and easiest way, it will itself be happy and bring the greatest benefit to the [5] people among whom it comes to be.

 

GLAUCON: That’s by far the quickest and easiest way. And in my opinion, Socrates, you have well described how it would come into existence, if it ever did. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Haven’t we said enough, then, about this city and the man who is like it? For surely it is clear what sort of person we will say he has to be.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, it is clear. And as for your question, I think we have reached the end of this topic.

 

1 Odyssey 11.489–90. The shade of Achilles speaks these words to Odysseus, who is visiting Hades. Plato is likening the cave dwellers to the dead.

2 See 611b9–612a6.

3 505a–b.

4 420b–421c, 462a–466c.

5 I.e., the practical life of ruling and the theoretical life of doing philosophy.

6 See 476c–d.

7 A proverbial expression, referring to a children’s game. The players were divided into two groups. A shell or potsherd—white on one side, black on the other—was thrown into space between them to the cry of “night or day?” (Note the reference to night and day in what follows.) According as the white or black fell uppermost, one group ran away pursued by the other.

8 404a, 412b–417b.

9 495c–e.

10 See 510d–511a.

11 504c.

12 528b.

13 A dense interval is evidently the smallest difference in pitch that was recognized in ancient music.

14Nomos: also, law.

15 See 516a–b.

16Auto ho estin agathon: See Glossary of Terms s.v. what it is.

17Poreia: An aporia (puzzle, problem—literally, a blockage on one’s journey forward) is what dialectic attempts to solve.

18 See 506d8–e5.

19 See 510c1–511c2.

20 See 519a7–519b5.

21 511d6–511e4.

22 The reference is to 511d6–e5, where the first section is called understanding (noêsis), not knowledge (epistêmê). Since thought (dianoia) is not now a kind of knowledge, noêsis and epistêmê have in effect become one and the same. Epistêmê and dianoia are now jointly referred to as noêsis, because that whole section of the line on which they appear consists of intelligible objects (noêton).

23Elengchein: (“to examine,” “to refute”)—as in the Socratic elenchus.

24 A pun made possible by the fact that alogon can mean “irrational” (as applied to people) and “incommensurable” (as applied to lines in geometry).

25 412b8–417b9.

26 See –402d1–4.

27 The difference between voluntary and involuntary lies is explained at 382a1– 383a7.

28 See Glossary of Terms s.v. disputation.

29 See Apology 23c.

30 See 346e3–347d8, 520e4–521a8.

31 See Glossary of Terms s.v. daimon.

32 See 361d4–6.

Book 8

 

SOCRATESNARRATION CONTINUES:

[543a] SOCRATES: All right. We are agreed, then, Glaucon, that if a city is going to be eminently well governed, women must be shared; children and their entire education must be shared; in both peace and war, pursuits must be shared; and their kings must be those among them who have proved best [5] both in philosophy and where war is concerned.

 

GLAUCON: We are agreed.

 

[b] SOCRATES: Moreover, we also granted this: once the rulers are established, they will lead the soldiers and settle them in the kind of dwellings we described earlier, which are in no way private, but wholly shared. And surely we also came to an agreement, if you remember, about what sort of [5] possessions they should have.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I do remember. We thought that none of them should acquire any of the things that others now do; but that, as athletes of war and [c] guardians, they should receive their minimum yearly upkeep from the other citizens as a wage for their guardianship, and take care of themselves and the rest of the city.1

 

SOCRATES: That’s right. But since we have completed that discussion, let’s recall the point at which we began the digression that brought us here, so [5] that we can continue on the same path again.

 

GLAUCON: That is not difficult. You see, much the same as now, you were talking as if you had completed the description of the city.2 You were saying that you would class both the city you described and the man who is like it [d] as good, even though, as it seems, you had a still finer city and man to tell [544a] us about. But in any case, you were saying that the others were defective, if it was correct. And you said, if I remember, that of the remaining kinds of constitution four were worth discussing, each with defects we should observe; and that we should do the same for the people like them in order [5] to observe them all, come to an agreement about which man is best and which worst, and then determine whether the best is happiest and the worst most wretched, or whether it is otherwise. I was asking you which four constitutions you had in mind, when Polemarchus and Adeimantus [b] interrupted.3 And that is when you took up the discussion that led here.

 

SOCRATES: That’s absolutely right.

 

GLAUCON: Like a wrestler, then, give me the same hold again, and when I [5] ask the same question, try to tell me what you were about to say before.

 

SOCRATES: If I can.

 

GLAUCON: In any case, I really want to hear for myself what four constitutions you meant.

 

SOCRATES: It won’t be difficult for you to hear them. You see, the ones I mean are the very ones that already have names: the one that is praised by[c] “the many,” your Cretan or Laconian4constitution. The second—and second in the praise it receives—is called oligarchy, a constitution filled with a host of evils. Antagonistic to it, and next in order, is democracy. And [5] “noble” tyranny, surpassing all of them, is the fourth and most extreme disease of cities. Can you think of another form of constitution—I mean, another distinct in form from these? For, no doubt, there are dynasties and purchased kingships and other similar constitutions in between these, [d] which one finds no less among barbarians than among Greeks.

 

GLAUCON: Many strange ones are certainly mentioned, at least. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Are you aware, then, that there must be as many forms of human character as there are of constitutions? Or do you think constitutions arise from oak or rock5 and not from the characters of the people in the cities, which tip the scales, so to speak, and drag the rest along with [e] them?

 

GLAUCON: No, they could not possibly arise from anything other than that.

 

SOCRATES: So, if there are five of cities, there must also be five ways of arranging private individual souls. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Now, we have already described the one who is like aristocracy, the one we rightly describe as good and just.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we have described him. [545a]

 

SOCRATES: Mustn’t we next describe the inferior ones—the victory-loving and honor-loving, which correspond to the Laconian constitution, followed by the oligarchic, democratic, and tyrannical—so that, having discovered the most unjust of all, we can oppose him to the most just and [5] complete our investigation into how pure justice and pure injustice stand with regard to the happiness or wretchedness of the one who possesses them; and be persuaded either by Thrasymachus to practice injustice or by [b] the argument that is now coming to light to practice justice.

 

GLAUCON: That’s exactly what we must do.

 

SOCRATES: Then just as we began by looking for the virtues of character in constitutions before looking for them in private individuals, thinking they would be clearer in the former,6 shouldn’t we first examine the honor-loving [5] constitution? I do not know another name that is commonly applied to it; it should be called either timocracy or timarchy. Then shouldn’t we examine that sort of man by comparing him to it, and, after that, oligarchy [c] and the oligarchic man, and democracy and the democratic man? Fourth, having come to a city that is under a tyrant and having examined it, shouldn’t we look into a tyrannical soul, and so try to become adequate [5] judges of the topic we proposed for ourselves?7

 

GLAUCON: That, at any rate, would be a reasonable way for us to go about observing and judging.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, let’s try to describe how timocracy emerges from aristocracy. Or is it simply the case that, in all constitutions, change [d] originates in the ruling element itself when faction breaks out within it; but that if this group remains of one mind, then—however small it is—change is impossible?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s right.

 

[5] SOCRATES: How, then, Glaucon, will our city be changed? How will faction arise, either between the auxiliaries and the rulers or within either [e] group? Or do you want us to be like Homer and pray to the Muses to tell us “how faction first broke out,”8 and have them speak in tragic tones, playing and jesting with us, as if we were children and they were speaking in earnest?

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: Something like this: “It is difficult for a city constituted in this [546a] way to change. However, since everything that comes-to-be must decay, not even one so constituted will last forever. On the contrary, it, too, must face dissolution. And this is how it will be dissolved: not only plants that grow in the earth, but also animals that grow upon it, have periods of fertility and [5] infertility of both soul and bodies each time their cycles complete a revolution. These cycles are short for what is short-lived and the opposite for what is the opposite. However, even though they are wise, the people you have educated to be leaders in your city will, by using rational calculation combined [b] with sense-perception, nonetheless fail to ascertain the periods of good fertility and of infertility for your species. Instead, these will escape them, and so they will sometimes beget children when they should not.

 

“Now, for the birth of a divine creature there is a cycle comprehended by a perfect number;9 while for a human being, it is the first number in which are found increases involving both roots and powers, comprehending three intervals and four terms, of factors that cause likeness and unlikeness, [5] cause increase and decrease, and make all things mutually agreeable and rational in their relations to one another. Of these factors, the base ones—four in relation to three, together with five—give two harmonies [c] when thrice increased. One is a square, so many times a hundred. The other is of equal length one way, but oblong. One of its sides are 100 squares of the rational diameter of five each diminished by one, or alternatively 100 squares of the irrational diameter each diminished by two. The [5] other side are 100 cubes of three. This whole geometrical number controls better and worse births.10 [d]

“And when, through ignorance of these, your guardians join brides and grooms at the wrong time, the children will be neither good-natured nor fortunate. The older generation will choose the best of these children, even though they do not deserve them. And when they in turn acquire their fathers’ powers, the first thing they will begin to neglect as guardians will [5] be us, by paying less attention to musical training than they should; and the second is physical training. Hence your young people will become more unmusical. And rulers chosen from among them won’t be able to guard [e] well the testing of Hesiod’s and your own races—gold, silver, bronze, and [547a] iron.11 The intermixing of iron with silver and bronze with gold will engender lack of likeness and unharmonious inequality, and these always breed war and hostility wherever they arise. We must declare faction to be [5] ‘of this lineage,’ 12 wherever and whenever it arises.”

GLAUCON: And we will declare that they have answered correctly.

 

SOCRATES: They must. They are Muses, after all!

 

[b] GLAUCON: What do the Muses say next?

 

SOCRATES: When faction arose, each of these two races, the iron and the bronze, pulled the constitution toward moneymaking and the acquisition of land, houses, gold, and silver. The other two, by contrast, the gold and silver [5] races—since they are not poor, but naturally rich in their souls13—led toward virtue and the old political system. Striving and struggling with one another, they compromised on a middle way: they distributed the land and houses among themselves as private property; enslaved and held as serfs and [c] servants those whom they had previously guarded as free friends and providers of upkeep; and took responsibility themselves for making war and for guarding against the ones they had enslaved.

 

[5] GLAUCON: I think that is how the transformation begins.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t this constitution, then, be somehow in the middle between aristocracy and oligarchy?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Anyway, that is how the transformation occurs. But once transformed, how will it be managed? Or isn’t it obvious that it will imitate [d] the first constitution in some respects and oligarchy in others, since it is in the middle between them; and that it will also have some features unique to itself?

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: In honoring the rulers, then, and in the fighting class’s abstention from farming, handicrafts, and other ways of making money, in providing [5] communal meals and being devoted to physical training and training for war—in all such ways, won’t the constitution be like the previous one?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: But in its fear of appointing wise people as rulers, on the [e] grounds that men of that sort are no longer simple and earnest but mixed; in its inclination toward spirited and simpler people, who are more naturally suited for war than peace; in its honoring the tricks and stratagems of war; and spending all its time making war—in these respects, by contrast, [548a] isn’t it pretty much unique?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Such men will have an appetite for money just like those in oligarchies, [5] passionately adoring gold and silver in secret, owning storehouses and private treasuries where they can deposit them and keep them hidden; and they will have walls around their houses, real private nests, where they can spend lavishly on their women or on anyone else they please. [b]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: They will be stingy with money, since they honor it and do not possess it openly, but they will love to spend other people’s money because of their appetites. They will enjoy their pleasures in secret, running [5] away from the law like boys from their father, since they have not been educated by persuasion but by force. This is because they have neglected the true Muse, the companion of discussion and philosophy,14 and honored physical training more than musical training. [c]

 

GLAUCON: The constitution you are describing is a thorough mixture of good and bad.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, it is mixed. But because of its mastery by the spirited element, only one thing really stands out in it—the love of victories and [5] honors.

 

GLAUCON: And very noticeable it is.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is how this constitution would come to exist, and that is what it would be like. It is just an outline sketch of the constitution in words, not an exact account of it, since even from a sketch we will be [10] able to see the most just man and most unjust one. It would be an incredibly [d] long task to discuss every constitution and every character without omitting any detail.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s right. [5]

 

SOCRATES : Who, then, is the man corresponding to this constitution? How does he come to exist and what sort of man is he?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think he would be very like Glaucon here, at least as far as the love of victory is concerned.

 

SOCRATES: Maybe in that respect, but in the following ones I do not think his nature would be like that.

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: Which ones?

 

SOCRATES: He would have to be more stubborn and less well trained in [5] music; a lover of music and of listening, yet not at all skilled in speaking; the [549a] sort of person who is harsh to slaves instead of looking down on them, as an adequately educated person does; gentle to free people and very submissive to rulers; a lover of ruling and of honor, who does not base his claim to [5] rule on his ability to speak or anything like that, but on his exploits in war and anything having to do with war; a lover of physical training and of hunting.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is indeed the character belonging to this constitution.

 

SOCRATES: As regards money, too, wouldn’t someone like that look down [b] on it when he is young; but as he grows older, wouldn’t he love it more and more because he shares in the money-lover’s nature and is not pure in his attitude to virtue, since he lacks the best guardian?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: What’s that?

 

SOCRATES: Reason mixed with musical training. You see, only it dwells within the person who possesses it as the lifelong preserver of his virtue.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well put.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is what a timocratic youth is like; he is like the [10] corresponding city.

 

[c] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And he comes to exist in some such way as this: sometimes he is the young son of a good father, who lives in a city that is not politically well governed; avoids honors, political office, lawsuits, and all such meddling in other people’s affairs; and who is even willing to be put at a disadvantage [5] so as to avoid trouble.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, but how does he become timocratic?

 

SOCRATES: It first happens when he listens to his mother complaining that her man is not one of the rulers and that she is at a disadvantage among the other women as a result. Next, she sees that he is not very serious about [d] money, either; does not fight or exchange insults in private lawsuits or in the public assembly, but takes easily everything of that sort; has a mind always absorbed in its own thoughts; and does not overvalue her or undervalue her either. As a result of all those things, she complains and tells her [5] son that his father is unmanly and too easygoing, and makes a litany of the other sorts of things women love to recite on such occasions. [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed, it is just like them to have lots of such complaints.

 

SOCRATES: You know, then, that the servants of such men—the ones thought to be loyal—also say similar things to the sons in private. If they see someone who owes the father money or has wronged him in some other [5] way, whom he does not prosecute, they urge the son to punish all such people when he becomes a man, and be more of a man than his father. And when he goes out, the boy hears and sees other similar things: those who [550a] do their own work in the city are called fools and held to be of little account, while those who do not are honored and praised. When the young man hears and sees all this, then, and, on the other hand, also listens [5] to what his father says, and sees his practices from close at hand and compares them with those of the others, he is pulled by both—his father nourishing the rational element in his soul and making it grow; the others [b] nourishing the appetitive and spirited elements. And, because he is not a bad man by nature, but has kept bad company, he compromises on a middle way when he is pulled in these two directions, and surrenders the rule within him to the middle element—the victory-loving and spirited one—[5] and becomes a proud and honor-loving man.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I think you have exactly described how such a man comes to exist.

 

SOCRATES: So, we now have the second constitution and the second man. [c]

 

ADEIMANTUS: We have.

 

SOCRATES: Next then, shall we, like Aeschylus, talk of “another man ordered like another city,”15 or follow our plan and talk about the city first?[5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: The latter, of course.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose oligarchy would come next after such a constitution.

 

ADEIMANTUS: And what kind of political system do you mean by oligarchy? [10]

 

SOCRATES: The constitution based on a property assessment, the one in which the rich rule and the poor man does not participate in ruling. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I understand.

 

SOCRATES: So, mustn’t we first describe how timarchy is transformed into oligarchy?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And surely the way it is transformed is clear even to the blind.

 

ADEIMANTUS: How?

 

SOCRATES: That storehouse filled with gold we mentioned,16 which each [10] possesses, destroys such a constitution. First, you see, the timocrats find ways of spending their money, then they alter the laws to allow them to do so, and then they and their women disobey the laws altogether.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: Next, I suppose, through one person seeing another and envying [e] him, they make the majority behave like themselves.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: After that then, they become further involved in moneymaking; [5] and the more honorable they consider it, the less honorable they consider virtue. Or isn’t virtue so opposed to wealth that if they were set on the scale of a balance, they would always incline in opposite directions?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly is.

 

[551a] SOCRATES: So, when wealth and the wealthy are honored in a city, virtue and good people are honored less.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And what is honored is always practiced, and what is not honored, [5] neglected.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, in the end, victory-loving and honor-loving men become lovers of making money and money-lovers, and they praise and admire the [10] wealthy man and appoint him as ruler, and dishonor the poor one.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it then that they pass a law, which is a defining characteristic of an oligarchic constitution, establishing a wealth qualification—[b] higher where it is more oligarchic, lower where it is less so—and proclaim that anyone whose property does not reach the stated assessment cannot participate in ruling? And they either put this through by force of arms, or else, without resorting to that, they use intimidation to establish this sort of [5] constitution. Isn’t that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is, generally speaking, how it is established.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is. But what is the constitution like? What are the defects we said it had?17 [c]

 

SOCRATES: First of all, consider its defining characteristic. I mean, what would happen if ship captains were appointed like that, on the basis of property assessments, and a poor person was turned away even if he were a better captain? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: People would make a very bad voyage!

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t the same apply to any other sort of rule whatsoever?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: Except of a city? Or does it apply to that of a city, too?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It applies to it most of all, since it is the most difficult and greatest kind of rule there is. [10]

 

SOCRATES: That, then, is one major defect in oligarchy. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: So it seems.

 

SOCRATES: And what about this one? Is it any smaller than the other?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which?

 

SOCRATES: That a city of this sort is not one, but inevitably two—a city of [5] the poor and one of the rich, living in the same place and always plotting against one another.

 

ADEIMANTUS: By Zeus, that’s no smaller a defect.

 

SOCRATES: And this is hardly a good quality either: the likelihood of being unable to fight a war because of having to arm and use the majority, [10] and so having to fear them more than the enemy; or else, because of not [e] using them, and so having to show up as true oligarchs18 on the battlefield; and because, at the same time, the fact that they are money-lovers makes them unwilling to pay mercenaries.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That is not good. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And what about what we condemned long ago19—the fact that in this constitution there is the meddling in other people’s affairs that occurs when the same people are farmers, moneymakers, and soldiers simultaneously? Or do you think it is right for things to be that way? [552a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Now, let’s see whether it is the first to admit the greatest of all evils. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which is?

 

SOCRATES: Allowing someone to sell all his possessions and someone else to buy them, and then allowing the seller to continue living in the city while not being any one of its parts—neither moneymaker nor craftsman, [10] nor cavalryman, nor hoplite, but a poor person without means.

 

[b] ADEIMANTUS: It is the first.

 

SOCRATES: Anyway, this sort of thing certainly is not forbidden in oligarchies. I mean, if it were, some of their citizens would not be super rich and others totally impoverished.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Now, consider this: when a person like that was rich and spending his money, was he then of any greater use to the city in the ways we have just mentioned? Or did he merely seem to be one of the rulers, while in fact he was neither ruler nor subject of it, but only a squanderer of property?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right. He seemed to be a ruler but was nothing but a [c] squanderer.

 

SOCRATES: Do you want us to say of him, then, that as a drone existing in a cell is an affliction to the hive, so this person existing in a household is a drone and affliction to the city?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: And hasn’t the god, Adeimantus, made all the winged drones stingless, as well as some of the footed ones, while other footed ones have terrible stings? And don’t those who end up as beggars in old age come from [d] among the stingless ones, while all those with stings are called evildoers?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Clearly then, in any city where you see beggars, somewhere in the neighborhood there are thieves hidden, and pickpockets, temple robbers, [5] and craftsmen of all such sorts of evil.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: What about oligarchic cities? Don’t you see beggars in them?

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Nearly everyone is one, apart from the rulers.

 

[e] SOCRATES: Mustn’t we suppose, then, that there are also many evildoers there with stings, whom the rulers forcibly keep in check by their cautiousness?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We certainly must suppose it.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And aren’t we saying that the presence of such people is the result of lack of education, bad rearing, and a bad constitutional system?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We are.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is roughly what the oligarchic city would be like. It would contain all these evils and probably others as well. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s pretty much it.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s take it, then, that we have disposed of the constitution [553a] they call oligarchy, which gets its rulers on the basis of a property assessment. Next, let’s consider how the person who is like it comes to exist, and what sort of person he is when he does.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, let’s.[5]

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t the transformation from timocrat to oligarch mostly occur in this way?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which?

 

SOCRATES: It happens when a son of his is born who begins by emulating his father and following in his footsteps, and then sees him suddenly crashing [10] against the city as against a reef, and sees him and all his possessions [b] spilling overboard. He had held a generalship or some other high office, was brought to court by sycophants,20 and was put to death or exiled, or was disenfranchised and had all his property confiscated.[5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: Anyway, my friend, after seeing and experiencing all that, and losing his property, the son is afraid, I imagine, and immediately throws the honor-loving and spirited element headlong from the throne in his own soul. And humbled by poverty, he turns greedily to moneymaking and, little [c] by little, saving and working, he amasses property. Don’t you think that someone like that will then establish the appetitive and moneymaking element on that throne, and make it a great king within himself, adorned with [5] golden tiaras and collars and Persian swords?21

 

ADEIMANTUS: I do.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose he makes the rational and spirited elements sit on the ground beneath it, one on either side, and be slaves. He won’t allow [d] the first to calculate or consider anything except how a little money can be made into more; or the second to admire or honor anything except wealth and wealthy people, or to love being honored for anything besides the possession [5] of wealth and whatever contributes to it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: There is no other way to turn an honor-loving young man into a money-loving one that is as swift and sure as that!

 

[e] SOCRATES: Isn’t this, then, the oligarchic person?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well, he certainly developed from the sort of man who resembled the constitution from which oligarchy came.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s see whether he resembles it.

 

[554a] ADEIMANTUS: Let’s.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t he resemble it, primarily, by attaching the greatest importance to money?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And also by being a thrifty worker who satisfies only his necessary [5] appetites and spends nothing on other things but enslaves his other appetites as pointless.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: A pretty squalid fellow, at any rate, who tries to make a profit [10] from everything: a treasury-builder—the sort the majority admire. Isn’t that [b] the sort of man who resembles this sort of constitution?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I certainly think so. At any rate, money is honored more than anything else by both the city and the one who is like it.

 

SOCRATES: Because I don’t suppose someone like that has paid any attention to education.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I don’t think so. I mean, if he had, he would not have chosen [5] a blind leader for his chorus and honored him most.22

 

SOCRATES: Well put! But consider this. Wouldn’t we say that though the dronish appetites exist in him because of his lack of education, some of them beggars and others evildoers, they are forcibly kept in check by his [c] general cautiousness?23

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Do you know, then, where you should look to see the evils [5] such people do?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Where?

 

SOCRATES: Where they are guardians of orphans, or any other situation like that, where they have ample opportunity to do injustice.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: True.

 

SOCRATES : So, doesn’t that make it clear that in other contractual matters, where someone like that has a good reputation and is thought to be just, something good of his is forcibly holding in check the other bad appetites within; not persuading them that they had better not, nor taming them [d] with arguments, but using compulsion and fear, because he is terrified of losing his other possessions?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, by Zeus, my friend, you will find that most of them, [5] when they have other people’s money to spend, have appetites in them akin to those of the drone.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, you certainly will!

 

SOCRATES: So, someone like that would not be entirely free from internal faction, and would not be a single person but somehow a twofold one,24 [10] although his better appetites would generally master his worse appetites. [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Because of this, I suppose someone like that would be more respectable than many other people; but the true virtue of a single-minded and harmonious soul would somehow far escape him. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, the thrifty man is a worthless individual contestant in the city for any prize of victory or any of the other fine things the love of honor craves. He is unwilling to spend money for the sake of fame [555a] or other such results of competition, and, fearing to arouse his appetites for spending by allying them with love of victory, he fights in true oligarchic fashion, with only a few of his resources,25 and is mostly defeated, but remains rich! [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: Are we still in any doubt, then, that, as regards resemblance, a thrifty moneymaker corresponds to an oligarchic city? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Not at all.

 

SOCRATES: Then democracy, it seems, must be considered next—both the way it comes to exist and what it is like when it does—so that when we know the character of this sort of man, we can present him for judgment [5] in turn.

 

ADEIMANTUS: At any rate, that would be consistent with what we have been doing.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, isn’t the change from an oligarchy to a democracy due in some way or other to the insatiable desire for the good set before it—the need to become as rich as possible? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How so?

 

[c] SOCRATES: Since the rulers rule in it because they own a lot, I suppose they are not willing to enact laws to prevent young people who have become intemperate from spending and wasting their wealth, so that by buying and making loans on the property of such people, the rulers themselves [5] can become even richer and more honored.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s their primary goal, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t it clear by now that you cannot honor wealth in a city and maintain temperance in the citizens at the same time, but must inevitably [d] neglect one or the other?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That is pretty clear.

 

SOCRATES: The negligent encouragement of intemperance in oligarchies, [5] then, sometimes reduces people who are not ill born to poverty.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, it does.

 

SOCRATES: And these people sit around in the city, I suppose, armed with stings or weapons—some of them in debt, some disenfranchised, some [10] both—hating and plotting against those who have acquired their property, [e] and all the others as well; passionately longing for revolution.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: These moneymakers, with their heads down,26 pretending not to see them, inject the poison of their money into any of the rest who do not [5] resist, and, carrying away a multitude of offspring in interest from their principal,27 [5] greatly increase the size of the drone and beggar class in the city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: They certainly do increase it greatly.

 

SOCRATES: In any case, they are not willing to quench evil of this sort as it flares up, either by preventing a person from doing whatever he likes with [5] his own property, or alternatively by passing this other law to do away with such abuses.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What law?

 

SOCRATES: The one that is next best and that compels the citizens to care [10] about virtue. You see, if someone prescribed that most voluntary contracts [b] be entered into at the lender’s own risk, money would be less shamelessly pursued in the city and fewer of those evils we were mentioning just now would develop in it.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Far fewer.

 

SOCRATES: But as it is, and for all these reasons, the rulers in the city treat their subjects in the way we described. And as for themselves and those belonging to them, don’t they bring up the young to be fond of luxury, incapable of effort either mental or physical, too soft to endure pleasures or pains, and lazy? [c]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And haven’t they themselves neglected everything except making money and been no more concerned about virtue than poor people are? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, they have.

 

SOCRATES: And when rulers and subjects, socialized in this way, meet on journeys or some other shared undertakings, whether in an embassy or a military campaign; or as shipmates or fellow soldiers; or when they watch [10] one another in dangerous situations—in these circumstances, don’t you [d] think the poor are in no way despised by the rich? On the contrary, don’t you think it is often the case that a poor man, lean and suntanned, is stationed in battle next to a rich one, reared in the shade and carrying a lot of excess flesh, and sees him panting and completely at a loss? And don’t you [5] think he believes that it is because of the cowardice of the poor that such people are rich and that one poor man says to another when they meet in private: “These men are ours for the taking; they are good for nothing” [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I know very well they do.

 

SOCRATES: Well, just as a sick body needs only a slight shock from outside to become ill and sometimes, even without external influence, becomes divided into factions, itself against itself, doesn’t a city in the same condition [5] need only a small pretext—such as one side bringing in allies from an oligarchy or the other from a democracy—to become ill and fight with itself? And doesn’t it sometimes become divided into factions even without any external influence?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, violently so. [557a]

 

SOCRATES: Then democracy comes about, I suppose, when the poor are victorious, kill or expel the others, and give the rest an equal share in the constitution and the ruling offices, and the majority of offices in it are assigned by lot. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is how a democratic political system gets established, whether it comes to exist by force of arms or because intimidation drives its opponents into exile.28

 

SOCRATES: In what way, then, do these people live? What sort of constitution do they have? For clearly the sort of man who is like it will turn out to [b] be democratic.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Well, in the first place, aren’t they free? And isn’t the city full [5] of freedom and freedom of speech? And isn’t there license in it to do whatever one wants?

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s what they say, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: And where there is license, clearly each person would arrange [10] his own life in whatever way pleases him.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

[c] SOCRATES: I imagine it is in this constitution, then, that multifarious people come to exist.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: It looks, then, as though it is the most beautiful of all the constitutions. For just like an embroidered cloak embroidered with every kind [5] of ornament, it is embroidered with every sort of character, and so would appear to be the most beautiful. And presumably, many people would behave like women and children looking at embroidered objects and actually judge it to be the most beautiful.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: They certainly would.

 

SOCRATES: What is more, bless you, it is also a handy place in which to [d] look for a constitution!

 

ADEIMANTUS: Why is that?

 

SOCRATES: Because it contains all kinds of constitutions, as a result of its license. So whoever wants to organize a city, as we were doing just now, probably has to go to a democracy and, as if he were in a supermarket of constitutions, pick out whatever pleases him and establish it.

 

[e] ADEIMANTUS: He probably wouldn’t be at a loss for examples, anyway!

 

SOCRATES: There is no compulsion to rule in this city, even if you are qualified to rule, or to be ruled if you do not want to be; or to be at war when the others are at war, or to keep the peace when the others are keeping [5] it, if you do not want peace; or, even if there happens to be a law preventing you from ruling or from serving on a jury, to be any the less free to [558a] rule or serve on a jury—isn’t that a heavenly and pleasant way to pass the time, while it lasts?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It probably is—while it lasts.

 

SOCRATES: And what about the calm of some of their condemned criminals? Isn’t that a sophisticated quality? Or have you never seen people [5] who have been condemned to death or exile in a constitution of this sort staying on all the same and living right in the middle of things, without anyone giving them a thought or staring at them, while they stroll around like a hero?29 ADEIMANTUS: Yes, I have seen it a lot.

 

SOCRATES: And what about the city’s tolerance, its complete lack of petty-mindedness, and its utter disregard for the things we took so seriously [b] when we were founding the city—that unless someone had transcendent natural gifts, he would never become a good man if he did not play fine games right from early childhood and engage in practices that are all of that same sort? Isn’t it magnificent how it tramples all that underfoot, gives no [5] thought to what sort of practices someone went in for before he entered politics, and honors him if only he tells them he wishes the majority well? [c]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s true nobility!

 

SOCRATES: These, then, and others akin to them are the characteristics a democracy would possess. And it would, it seems, be a pleasant constitution—lacking rulers but not complexity, and assigning a sort of equality to equals and unequals alike. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s well known!

 

SOCRATES: Look and see, then, what sort of private individual resembles it. Or should we first consider, as we did in the case of the constitution, how he comes to exist?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Well, doesn’t it happen this way? Mightn’t we suppose that our thrifty oligarchic man had a son brought up by his father with his father’s [d] traits of character?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Then he too would rule by force the pleasures that exist in him—the spendthrift ones that do not make money; the ones that are called unnecessary. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: In order not to have a discussion in the dark, would you like us first to define which appetites are necessary and which are not?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I would. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, wouldn’t those we cannot deny rightly be called necessary? And also those whose satisfaction benefits us? For we are by [e] nature compelled to try to satisfy them both. Isn’t that so?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

[559a] SOCRATES: So, we would be right to apply the term “necessary” to them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We would be right.

 

SOCRATES: What about those someone could get rid of if he started practicing from childhood, those whose presence does no good but may even do the opposite? If we said that all of them were unnecessary, would we be [5] right?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We would be right.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s pick an example of each, so that we have a pattern to follow.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, let’s.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t the desire to eat to the point of health and well-being,[b] and the desire for bread and relishes30 be necessary ones?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: The desire for bread is surely necessary on both counts, in that it is beneficial and that unless it is satisfied, we die.31

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And so is the one for relishes, insofar as it is beneficial and conduces to well-being.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed.

 

SOCRATES: What about an appetite that goes beyond these and seeks other sorts of foods; that, if it is restrained from childhood and educated, most [10] people can get rid of; and that is harmful to the body and harmful to the soul’s capacity for wisdom and temperance? Wouldn’t it be correct to call it [c] unnecessary?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Entirely correct.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t we also say that the latter desires are spendthrift, then, whereas the former are moneymaking because they are useful where work is concerned?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t we say the same about sexual appetites and the rest?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And didn’t we say that the person we just now called a drone is full of such pleasures and appetites and is ruled by the unnecessary ones, [d] while the one who is ruled by his necessary appetites is a thrifty oligarch?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course we did.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s go back, then, and say how the democrat develops from the oligarch. It seems to me as if it mostly happens this way. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: What way?

 

SOCRATES: When a young man who is reared in the uneducated and thrifty manner we described just now tastes the honey of the drones and associates with wild and terrible creatures who can provide multifarious pleasures of every degree of complexity and sort, that probably marks the [10] beginning of his transformation from having an oligarchic constitution [e] within him to having a democratic one.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It most certainly does.

 

SOCRATES: So, just as the city changed when one party received help from a like-minded alliance outside, doesn’t the young man change in turn when [5] external appetites of the same type and quality as it come to the aid of one of the parties within him?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And I suppose if a counter-alliance comes to the aid of the oligarchic party within him—whether from his father or from the rest of his [10] family, who exhort and reproach him—then there is a faction and an [560a] opposing faction within him, and he battles against himself.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And sometimes, I suppose, the democratic party yields to the oligarchic, some of its appetites are overcome while others are expelled, and [5] a kind of shame rises in the young man’s soul and order is restored.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That does sometimes happen.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, I suppose, as some appetites are expelled, others akin to them are being nurtured undetected because of the father’s ignorance of upbringing, and become numerous and strong. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: At any rate, that’s what usually happens.

 

SOCRATES: Then these desires draw him back to his old associates32 and, in secret intercourse, breed a multitude of others. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Finally, I suppose, they seize the citadel of the young man’s soul, since they realize that it is empty of the fine studies and practices and the true arguments that are the best watchmen and guardians in the minds of men loved by the gods. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: By far the best. [c]

 

SOCRATES: Then, I suppose, beliefs and arguments that are lying imposters rush up and occupy this same part of him in place of the others.

 

ADEIMANTUS: They do, indeed.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Won’t he then return to those Lotus-eaters and live with them openly? And if any help should come to the thrifty part of his soul from his relatives, don’t those imposter arguments, having barred the gates of the royal wall within him, prevent the allied force itself from entering and even refusing to admit arguments of older, private individuals as ambassadors? [d] Proving stronger in the battle, won’t they call reverence foolishness and drive it out as a dishonored fugitive? And calling temperance cowardliness, won’t they shower it with abuse and banish it? As for moderate and orderly [5] expenditure, won’t they persuade him that it is boorish and illiberal, and join with a multitude of useless appetites to drive it over the border?

 

ADEIMANTUS: They will indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And when they have somehow emptied and purged these [e] from the soul of the one they are seizing hold of and initiating with solemn rites, they then immediately proceed to return arrogance, anarchy, extravagance, and shamelessness from exile in a blaze of torchlight, accompanied with a vast chorus of followers and crowned with garlands. They praise them and give them fine names, calling arrogance “good breeding,” anarchy[5] “freedom,” extravagance “magnificence,” and shamelessness “courage.” Isn’t [561a] it in some such way as this that a young person exchanges an upbringing among necessary appetites for the freeing and release of useless and unnecessary pleasures?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s clearly the way it happens.

 

SOCRATES: Then in his subsequent life, I suppose, someone like that spends no less money, effort, and time on the necessary pleasures than on the unnecessary pleasures. But if he is lucky and does not go beyond the limits in his bacchic frenzy, and if, as a result of his growing somewhat older, the great tumult within him passes, he welcomes back some of the [b] exiles and ceases to surrender himself completely to the newcomers. Then, putting all his pleasures on an equal footing, he lives, always surrendering rule over himself to whichever desire comes along, as if it were chosen by lot,33 until it is satisfied; and after that to another, dishonoring none but satisfying [5] all equally.

 

ADEIMANTUS: He does, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And he does not accept or admit true argument into the guardhouse if someone tells him that some pleasures belong to fine and good [5] appetites and others to bad ones, and that he must practice and honor the former and restrain and enslave the latter. On the contrary, he denies all this and declares that they are all alike and must be honored on an equal basis.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s exactly what he feels and does. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And so he lives from day to day, gratifying the appetite of the moment. Sometimes he drinks heavily while listening to the flute, while at others he drinks only water and is on a diet. Sometimes he goes in for physical training, while there are others when he is idle and neglects everything. Sometimes he spends his time engaged in what he takes to be philosophy. [d] Often, though, he takes part in politics, leaping to his feet and saying and doing whatever happens to come into his mind. If he admires some military men, that is the direction in which he is carried; if some moneymakers, then in that different one. There is neither order nor necessity in [5] his life, yet he calls it pleasant, free, and blessedly happy, and follows it throughout his entire life.

 

ADEIMANTUS: You have perfectly described the life of a man devoted to legal equality.34 [e]

 

SOCRATES: I certainly think he is a multifarious man and full of all sorts of characters, beautiful and complex, like the democratic city. Many men and women would envy his life because of the great number of examples of [5] constitutions and characters it contains within it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, will we set this man alongside democracy as the [562a] one who would rightly be called democratic?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We will.

 

SOCRATES: The finest constitution and the finest man remain for us to discuss: tyranny and the tyrant. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then; tell me, my dear comrade, how does tyranny come to exist? That it evolves from democracy, you see, is fairly clear.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is clear.

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t the way democracy evolves from oligarchy much the [10] same as that in which tyranny evolves from democracy? [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The good they proposed for themselves, and because of which oligarchy was established, was wealth, wasn’t it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And its insatiable desire for wealth and its neglect of other things for the sake of moneymaking was what destroyed it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: True.

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t democracy’s insatiable desire for what it defines as the [10] good also what destroys it?

 

ADEIMANTUS: What do you think it does define as the good?

 

SOCRATES: Freedom. For surely, in a democratic city, that is what you [c] would hear described as its finest possession, and as what makes it the only place worth living in for someone who is naturally free.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, you often hear that said.

 

SOCRATES: As I was about to say, then, isn’t it the insatiable desire for this [5] good and the neglect of other things that changes this constitution and prepares it to need a dictatorship?

 

ADEIMANTUS: How does it do that?

 

SOCRATES: I suppose it is when a democratic city, athirst for freedom, [d] happens to get bad cupbearers for its leaders and gets drunk by drinking more than it should of unmixed wine.35 Then, if the rulers are not very gentle and do not provide plenty of freedom, it punishes them and accuses them of being filthy oligarchs.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is what it does.

 

SOCRATES: It showers with abuse those who obey the rulers as voluntary slaves and nonentities, but both in public and private it praises and honors rulers who are like subjects, and subjects who are like rulers. And isn’t it [e] inevitable in such a city that freedom should spread everywhere?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, my friend, and so it is bound to make its way into private [5] households until finally it breeds anarchy among the very animals.

 

ADEIMANTUS: What do you mean by that?

 

SOCRATES: For instance, a father gets into the habit of behaving like a child and fearing his son, and the son gets into the habit of behaving like a father, feeling neither shame nor fear in front of his parents—all in order to be free. A resident alien feels himself equal to a citizen and a citizen to him, [563a] and a foreigner likewise.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, those sorts of things do happen.

 

SOCRATES : They do—and so do other little things of the same sort. A teacher in such circumstances is afraid of his students and flatters them, while the students belittle their teachers and do the same to their tutors, too. In general, the young are the spitting images of their elders and compete [5] with them in words and deeds, while the old stoop to the level of the young and are full of wit and indulgence, imitating the young for fear of being thought disagreeable and masterful. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: The ultimate freedom for the majority, my friend, comes about in such a city, when males and females bought as slaves are no less [5] free than those who bought them. Then there is the case of women in relation to men, and men to women, and the extent of their legal equality and freedom—we almost forgot to mention that!

 

ADEIMANTUS: Are we not, with Aeschylus, going to “say whatever it was came to our lips just now?”36 [c]

 

SOCRATES: Certainly. At any rate, I am going to say it. I mean, no one who had not experienced it would believe how much freer domestic animals are here than in any other city. Bitches follow the proverb exactly and [5] become like their mistresses. Horses and donkeys are in the habit of proceeding with complete freedom and dignity, bumping into anyone they meet on the road who does not get out of their way. And everything else is full of freedom, too. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is my own dream you are telling me.37 That often happens to me when I go to the country.

 

SOCRATES: Summing up all these things together, then, do you notice how sensitive they make the citizens’ souls, so that if anyone tries to impose [5] the least degree of slavery, they get irritated and cannot bear it? In the end, as I am sure you are aware, they take no notice of the laws—written or unwritten—in order to avoid having any master at all. [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I certainly am aware.

 

SOCRATES: This, my friend, is the fine and impetuous beginning from which tyranny seems to me to grow.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is certainly impetuous. But what comes next? [5]

 

SOCRATES: The same disease that developed in oligarchy and destroyed it also develops here—only more widespread and virulent because of the general permissiveness—and eventually enslaves democracy. In fact, excessive action in one direction usually sets up a great reaction in the opposite direction. This happens in seasons, in plants, in bodies, and particularly in [10] constitutions. [564a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s probably right.

 

SOCRATES: For extreme freedom probably cannot lead to anything but a change to extreme slavery, whether in a private individual or a city.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: No, it probably can’t.

 

SOCRATES: Tyranny probably does not evolve from any constitution other than democracy, then—the most severe and cruel slavery evolving from what I suppose is the most eminent degree of freedom.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that’s reasonable.

 

[10] SOCRATES: But I think you were asking, not that, but rather what sort of [b] disease develops both in oligarchy and democracy alike, and enslaves the latter.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s true.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, I meant that class of idle and extravagant men, [5] with the bravest as leaders and the more cowardly as followers. We compared them to drones: the leaders to drones with stings, the followers to stingless ones.38

 

ADEIMANTUS: Rightly so.

 

SOCRATES: These two cause problems in any constitution in which they [10] arise, like phlegm and bile in the body.39 And it is against them that the [c] good doctor and lawgiver of a city must take no less advance precaution than a wise beekeeper. He should preferably prevent them from arising at all. But if they should happen to arise, he must cut them out, cells and all, as quickly as possible.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes, by Zeus, and as thoroughly as possible.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s take up the question in this way, in order to see what we want more distinctly.

 

ADEIMANTUS: In what way?

 

SOCRATES: Let’s in our discussion divide a democratic city into three parts—which is also how it is actually divided. One part is surely this class [d] of drones, which, because of the general permissiveness, grows in it no less than in an oligarchy.

 

ADEIMANTUS: So it does.

 

SOCRATES: But it is much fiercer in it than in the other.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: How so?

 

SOCRATES: There, because it is not honored but is excluded from the ranks of the rulers, it does not get any exercise and does not become vigorous. However, in a democracy, with few exceptions, it is surely the dominant class. Its fiercest part does all the talking and acting, while the other one settles near the speaker’s platform. It buzzes and does not tolerate any [10] dissent. As a result, this class is in charge of everything in such a constitution—with [e] a few exceptions.40

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Then, there is a second distinct class that is constantly emerging from the majority.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which one? [5]

 

SOCRATES: Surely, when everyone is trying to make money, the ones who are by nature most orderly generally become the wealthiest.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: Then that is where the most plentiful honey for the drones exists, I take it, and the easiest for them to extract. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: How could anyone extract it from those who have very little?

 

SOCRATES: I suppose, then, that these rich people, as they are called, are fodder for the drones.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Pretty much.

 

SOCRATES: The people—those who work their own land, take no part in [565a] politics, and own few possessions—would be the third class. This is the largest and most powerful class in a democracy when it meets in assembly.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, it is. But it is not willing to meet often, if it does not get a share of the honey. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So, it always does get a share—one that allows the leaders, in taking the wealth of the rich and distributing it to the people, to keep the greatest share for themselves.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that is the sort of share they get. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Then I suppose that those whose wealth is taken away are compelled to defend themselves by speaking in the popular assembly and doing whatever else they can.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: At which point—even if they have no appetite for revolution [5] at all—they get accused by the others of plotting against the people and of being oligarchs.

 

ADEIMANTUS: They do.

 

SOCRATES: Finally, when they see the people—not intentionally, but [10] through misapprehension and being misled by the accusers—trying to do [c] injustice to them, then, whether they wish it or not, they really do become oligarchs—not from choice, though, but because the drone, by stinging them, engenders this evil.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Then there are impeachments, judgments, and trials on both sides.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Right.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t the people always tend to set up one man as their [10] special leader, nurturing him and making him great?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes.

 

[d] SOCRATES: And it is clear that when a tyrant arises, the position of popular leader is the sole root from which he springs.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: What is the beginning, then, of the transformation from popular leader to tyrant? Isn’t it clear that it happens when the popular leader [5] begins to behave like the character in the story told about the temple of the Lycaean Zeus41 in Arcadia?

 

ADEIMANTUS: What story?

 

SOCRATES: That whoever tastes the one piece of human innards cut up [10] with those of all the other sacrificial victims inevitably becomes a wolf. [e] Haven’t you heard that story?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I have.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it the same, then, with a popular leader? Once he really takes over a docile mob, he does not restrain himself from shedding a fellow citizen’s blood. But by leveling the usual false charges and bringing people [5] into court, he commits murder. And by blotting out a man’s life, his impious tongue and lips taste kindred blood. Then he banishes and kills and [566a] drops hints about the cancellation of debts and the redistribution of land. And after that, isn’t such a man inevitably fated either to be killed by his enemies or to be a tyrant, transformed from a man into a wolf?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Yes. That is the inevitable outcome.

 

SOCRATES: He is the one, then, who stirs up faction against the rich.

 

ADEIMANTUS: He is.

 

SOCRATES: And if he happens to be exiled but, despite his enemies, manages to return, doesn’t he come back as a full-fledged tyrant?42 [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Obviously.

 

SOCRATES: And if they are unable to expel him or put him to death by [b] accusing him before the city, they plot a violent death for him by covert means.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s what tends to happen, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: And everyone who has reached this stage soon discovers the [5] famous tyrannical request—to ask the people to give him a bodyguard to keep their popular leader safe for them.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Right.

 

SOCRATES: And the people give it to him, I suppose, fearing for his safety but confident of their own. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Right. [c]

 

SOCRATES: So, when a wealthy man sees this and is charged with being an enemy of the people because of his wealth, then, comrade, in the words of the oracle to Croesus, he “flees without delay to the banks of the many-pebbled Hermus, and is not ashamed at all of his cowardice.”43 [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: He would certainly never get a second chance to be ashamed!

 

SOCRATES: If he is caught, I would imagine he is put to death.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: As for this popular leader of ours, he clearly does not lie on [10] the ground “mighty in his might,”44 but, having brought down all those [d] others, he stands in the chariot of the city as a complete tyrant instead of a popular leader.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s for sure.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we next describe the happiness of this man and of the [5] city in which such a creature arises?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, let’s.

 

SOCRATES: To start with, in the early days of his reign, won’t he greet everyone he meets with a smile, deny he is a tyrant, promise all sorts of [e] things in private and in public, free the people from debt, redistribute the land to them and to his followers, and pretend to be gracious and gentle to all?

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: But once he has dealt with his exiled enemies by making peace with some and destroying others, and all is calm on that front, his primary concern, I imagine, is to be constantly stirring up some war or other, so that the people will need a leader.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Very likely.

 

[567a] SOCRATES: And also, wouldn’t you say, so that impoverished by war taxes, they will be forced to concentrate on their daily needs and be less likely to plot against him?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And in addition, I suppose, so that if there are some freethinking [5] people he suspects of rejecting his rule, he can find pretexts for putting them at the mercy of the enemy and destroying them? For all these reasons, isn’t a tyrant bound to be always stirring up war?

 

ADEIMANTUS: He is.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Don’t all these actions tend to make him more hateful to the [b] citizens?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t some of those who helped establish his tyranny and hold positions of power within it, the ones who are bravest, speak freely to [5] him and to each other, criticizing what is happening?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably.

 

SOCRATES: Then the tyrant will have to do away with all of them if he intends to rule, until he is left with no friend or enemy who is worth anything [10] at all.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Obviously.

 

SOCRATES: He will have to keep a sharp lookout, then, for anyone who is brave, magnanimous, wise, or rich. He is so happy, you see, that he is [c] forced, whether he wants to or not, to be their enemy and plot against all of them until he has purged the city.

 

ADEIMANTUS: A fine purge that is!

 

[5] SOCRATES : Yes. The opposite of the one doctors perform on our bodies. They draw off the worst and leave the best, whereas he does just the opposite!

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yet that’s what he has to do, it seems, if he is to rule.

 

SOCRATES: It is a blessedly happy necessity he is bound by, then, which requires him to live with inferior masses even though hated by them, or not [d] live at all!

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: And the more he makes the citizens hate him by doing those [5] things, the larger and more trustworthy a bodyguard he will need, won’t he?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And who will these trustworthy people be? And from where will he get them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Lots of them will come swarming of their own accord, if he pays them. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Drones again, by the dog!45 That is what I think you are talking about. Foreign, multifarious ones! [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, you are right.

 

SOCRATES: What about the domestic ones? Wouldn’t he be willing to deprive citizens of their slaves somehow, set them free, and enlist them in [5] his bodyguard?

 

ADEIMANTUS: He certainly would, since they are the ones he can trust the most.

 

SOCRATES: What a blessedly happy thing this tyrant business is on your view, if these are the sorts of friends and trusted men he must employ after destroying his former ones! [568a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Nonetheless, they are the sorts he does employ.

 

SOCRATES: And these friends and new citizens admire and associate with him, whereas the good ones hate and avoid him? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: It is no wonder, then, that tragedy seems to be something wholly wise, or that Euripides is outstanding in it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Why is that? [10]

 

SOCRATES: Because, among other things, he expressed the following shrewd thought: “tyrants are wise by associating with the wise.” He meant [b] evidently that these associates of the tyrant are the wise ones.46

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes. And he also praises tyranny as godlike, and lots of other things besides—and the other poets do, too.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Then surely, since the tragic poets are so wise, they will forgive us and those with constitutions like ours if we do not admit them into our city, since they hymn the praises of tyranny.

 

ADEIMANTUS: For my part, I think they will forgive us—the more refined [c] of them, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: They can go around to all the other cities instead, I suppose, drawing large crowds and hiring actors with fine, loud, persuasive voices, [5] and lead their constitutions to become tyrannies and democracies.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: What’s more, they are paid and honored for it, primarily—as one might expect—by tyrants and secondly by democracy. But the higher they go on the ascending scale of constitutions, the more their honor [d] diminishes, as if unable to proceed for lack of breath.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: But all that is a digression. Let’s return to our tyrant’s camp—[5] the one that is beautiful, populous, complex, and never the same—and ask how he is going to maintain it.

 

ADEIMANTUS: If there are sacred treasuries in the city, he will obviously use them for as long as they last, as well as the property of those he has destroyed, so the taxes he will require from the people will be smaller.

 

[e] SOCRATES: What about when these resources give out?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Clearly, his father’s estate will have to support him, his drinking companions, and his boyfriends and girlfriends, too.

 

SOCRATES: I understand. You mean the people who fathered the tyrant [5] will have to support him and his friends.

 

ADEIMANTUS: They will have no choice.

 

SOCRATES: What if the people get irritated and say it is not just for a grown-up son to be supported by his father? On the contrary, the father should be supported by his son. They did not father him and establish [569a] him in power, they say, so that, when he had become strong, they would be enslaved to their own slave and have to support him, his slaves, and other assorted rabble as well; but so that, with him as their popular leader, they would get free from the rule of the rich and the so-called [5] fine and good people in the city. At that point, they order him and his friends to leave the city, as a father might drive a son and his troublesome drinking companions from his house. What do you think would happen then?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Then, by Zeus, the people will soon learn what kind of creature they have fathered, welcomed, and made strong, and that it is a case of the weaker trying to drive out the stronger. [b]

 

SOCRATES: What do you mean? Will the tyrant dare to use force against his father or hit him if he does not obey?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes—once he has taken away his weapons. [5]

 

SOCRATES : A tyrant is a parricide as you describe him, then, and a harsh nurse of old age; and we do now seem to have an acknowledged tyranny. And so the people, by trying to avoid the proverbial frying pan of enslavement to free men, have fallen into the fire of having slaves as their masters; and, in exchange for the excessive and inappropriate freedom they [c] had before, have put upon themselves the harshest and most bitter slavery to slaves.

 

ADEIMANTUS: That’s exactly what happens. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, wouldn’t we be justified in saying that we have adequately described how tyranny evolves from democracy, and what it is like once it has come to exist?

 

ADEIMANTUS: We would. Our description was entirely adequate.

 

1 415d6–420a7.

2 445c1–450c5.

3 449b1–2.

4 I.e., Spartan.

5 Homer, Odyssey 19.163.

6 See 368c7–369a3.

7 Most recently at 544a2–8.

8 Apparently an adaptation of Iliad 16.112–3.

9 The divine creature seems to be the world or universe. See Timaeus 30b–d, 32d, 34a–b. Plato does not specify what its number is.

10 The human geometrical number is the product of 3, 4, and 5 “thrice increased” : if (3 × 4 × 5) × (3 × 4 × 5) = (3 × 4 × 5)2 is one increase, (3 × 4 × 5) × (3 × 4 × 5) × (3 × 4 × 5) × (3 × 4 × 5) = (3 × 4 × 5)4 is three. This formula included “increases involving both roots and powers”: (3 × 4 × 5) is a root; its indices are powers. It “comprehends” three “intervals,” symbolized by ×, and four “terms”—namely, the roots. The resulting number, 12,960,000, can be represented geometrically as: (1) a square whose sides are 3,600, or (2) an “oblong” or rectangle whose sides are 4,800 and 2,700. (1) is “so many times 100”: 36 times. (2) is obtained as follows. The “rational diameter” of 5 is the nearest rational number to the real diameter of a square whose sides are 5. This diameter = √52 + 52 = √50 = 7. Since the square of 7 is 49, we get the longer side of the rectangle by diminishing 49 by 1 and multiplying the result by 100. This gives 4,800. The “irrational diameter” of 5 is √50. When squared (= 50), diminished by 2 (= 48), and multiplied by 100, this, too, is 4,800. The short side, “100 cubes of three,” = 2,700. The significance of the number is more controversial. The factors “that cause likeness and unlikeness, cause increase and decrease, and make all things mutually agreeable and rational in their relations to one another” are probably the numbers, since odd numbers were thought to cause likeness and even ones unlikeness (Aristotle, Physics203a13–5). Of the numbers significant in human life, one is surely the 100 years of its maximum span (615a8–b1). Another might be the number of days in the year (roughly 360), and a third might be the divisions of those days into smaller units determined by the sun’s place in the sky, since it is the sun that provides for “the coming-to-be, growth, and nourishment” of all visible things (509b2–4). Assuming that those units are the 360 degrees of the sun’s path around the earth (a suggestion due to Robin Waterfield), the number of moments in a human life that have a potential effect on its coming-to-be, growth, and nourishment would be 100 × 360 × 360, or 12,960,000—Plato’s human geometrical number.

11 414d1–415c7; Hesiod, Works and Days 109–202.

12 Homer, Iliad 6.211.

13 See 416e4–417a1.

14 See Phaedo 61a3–4.

15 The line does not occur in the extant plays, but it may be an adaptation of Seven against Thebes 451.

16 548a7–8.

17 544c4–5.

18 I.e., as being few in number. Oligos means few.

19 374b6–c2.

20 See Glossary of Terms s.v. sycophants.

21 For the Greeks, the king of Persia was emblematic of absolute rule.

22 I.e., Plutus, the god of wealth, who is often represented as being blind.

23 See 552e1–2.

24 See 443c9–444a2.

25 See 551e2 note.

26 Their heads are down because their appetite for money forces their souls to look downward. See 518c4–519b5.

27 See 507a5 and note.

28 See 551a12–b5.

29 Dead heroes were worshipped as minor deities in Greek religion, particularly in their birthplaces, where their spirits were thought to linger.

30 See 372c4 note.

31 Bread is used here to mean “the staff of life.”That is why one dies for want of it.

32 Described at 559d7–e2.

33 Many public officials in democratic Athens were elected by lot.

34 Isonomia: an important democratic value.

35 The Greeks drank their wine mixed with water.

36 At 562e4–5. We no longer possess the play from which this fragment comes.

37 I.e., you are telling me what I already know.

38 552c2–e3.

39Phlegm and bile were two of the so-called humors Greek medicine thought responsible for health and disease.

40 The exceptions in question are presumably the various offices—such as the chief military official—to which in the Athenian democracy were appointed on the basis of expertise.

41 Zeus the wolf-god.

42 Plato seems to be alluding to the tyrant Peisistratus. In 560 BCE, Peisistratus made himself tyrant with the help of a bodyguard granted to him by the Athenian people.

After five years, he was expelled. Eventually he returned to Athens and used mercenaries to establish himself firmly as tyrant. He died in 527. See Herodotus 1.59–64.

43 The story of the Delphic oracle to Croesus is found in Herodotus 1.55.

44 See Iliad 16.776.

45 See 399e5 note.

46 The fragment is from an unknown play. Euripides meant that tyrants gain wisdom from the wise people who, as Simonides said, “knock at the doors of the rich”

(489b7–8). Plato twists his words to mean that the drones and slaves, who are the tyrant’s last resort, are wise, since they associate with him.

Book 9

 

SOCRATES’ NARRATION CONTINUES:

[571a] SOCRATES: The tyrannical man himself remains to be investigated: how he evolves from a democratic one, what he is like once he has come to exist, and whether the way he lives is wretched or blessedly happy.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, he still remains.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Do you know what else I still miss?

 

ADEIMANTUS: What?

 

SOCRATES: I do not think we have adequately distinguished the nature and number of our appetites.1 And if that subject is not adequately dealt [b] with, our investigation will lack clarity.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Well, isn’t now as fine a time as any?

 

SOCRATES: It certainly is. So, consider what I want to look at in them. It is this: among unnecessary pleasures and appetites, there are some that seem [5] to me to be lawless. These are probably present in all of us, but they are held in check by the laws and by our better appetites allied with reason. In a few people they have been eliminated entirely or only a few weak ones remain, [c] while in others they are stronger and more numerous.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Which ones do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The ones that wake up when we are asleep, whenever the rest of the soul—the rational, gentle, and ruling element—slumbers. Then the [5] bestial and savage part, full of food or drink, comes alive, casts off sleep, and seeks to go and gratify its own characteristic instincts.You know it will dare to do anything in such a state, released and freed from all shame and wisdom. In fantasy, it does not shrink from trying to have sex with a mother or [d] with anyone else—man, god, or beast. It will commit any foul murder, and there is no food it refuses to eat. In a word, it does not refrain from anything, no matter how foolish or shameful.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES : On the other hand, I suppose someone who keeps himself healthy and temperate will awaken his rational element before going to sleep and feast it on fine arguments and investigations, which he has brought to an agreed conclusion within himself. As for the appetitive element, he neither starves nor overfeeds it, so it will slumber and not disturb [e] the best element with its pleasure or pain but will leave it alone, just by itself and pure, to investigate and reach out for the perception of something—whether [572a] past, present, or future—that it does not know. He soothes the spirited element in a similar way and does not get angry and fall asleep with his spirit still aroused. And when he has calmed these two elements [5] and stimulated the third, in which wisdom resides, he takes his rest. You know this is the state in which he most readily grasps the truth and in which the visions appearing in his dreams are least lawless. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I completely agree.

 

SOCRATES : Well, we have been led a bit astray and said a bit too much. What we want to pay attention to is this: there are appetites of a terrible, savage, and lawless kind in everyone—even in those of us who seem to be [5] entirely moderate. This surely becomes clear in sleep. Do you think I am talking sense? Do you agree with me?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, I do agree.

 

SOCRATES: Now, recall what we said the democratic man is like.2 He was [10] the result, we presumed, of a childhood upbringing by a thrifty father who [c] honored only appetites that made money and despised the unnecessary ones whose objects are amusement and showing off. Isn’t that right?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And by associating with more sophisticated men who are full of the appetites we just described, he starts to indulge in every kind of arrogance and adopt their kind of behavior, because of his hatred of his father’s thrift. But, since he has a better nature than his corrupters, he is pulled in both directions and settles in the middle between their two ways of life. And enjoying each in what he takes to be moderation, he lives a life that is neither [d] illiberal nor lawless, transformed now from an oligarch to a democrat.

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, that was—and still is—our belief about someone like that.

 

SOCRATES: Suppose, then, that this man has now in turn become older [5] and has a son who is also brought up in his father’s way of life.

 

ADEIMANTUS: I will.

 

SOCRATES: Suppose, too, that the same things happen to him as happened to his father: he is led into all the kinds of lawlessness that those leading him call total freedom. His father and the rest of his family come to the aid of [e] the appetites that are in the middle, while the others help the opposite ones. And when these terrible enchanters and tyrant-makers have no hope [5] of keeping hold of the young man in any other way, they contrive to implant a powerful passion in him as the popular leader of those idle and [573a] profligate appetites—a sort-of great, winged drone. Or do you think passion is ever anything else in such people?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I certainly do not think it is.

 

SOCRATES: And when the other appetites come buzzing around—filled [5] with incense, perfumes, wreaths, wine, and all the other pleasures found in such company, they feed the drone, make it grow as large as possible, and plant the sting of longing in it. Then this popular leader of the soul adopts [b] madness as its bodyguard and is stung to frenzy. If it finds any beliefs or appetites in the man that are regarded as good or are still moved by shame, it destroys them and throws them out, until it has purged him of temperance and filled him with imported madness.

 

ADEIMANTUS: You have perfectly described how a tyrannical man comes [5] to exist.

 

SOCRATES: Is that, then, why Passion has long been called a tyrant?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Probably so.

 

SOCRATES: And hasn’t a drunken man, my friend, something of a tyrannical [c] cast of mind, too?

 

ADEIMANTUS: He has.

 

SOCRATES: And of course someone who is mad and deranged attempts to rule not only human beings, but gods as well, and expects to be able to rule them.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: A man becomes tyrannical in the precise sense, then, you marvelous fellow, when his nature or his practices or both together lead him to drunkenness, passion, and melancholia.

 

[10] ADEIMANTUS: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES : So, that, it seems, is how a tyrannical man comes to exist. Now, what is his life like?

 

[d] ADEIMANTUS: Why don’t you tell me, as askers of riddles usually do?

 

SOCRATES: I will tell you.You see, I think someone in whom the tyrant of Passion dwells, and in whom it serves as captain of everything in the soul, next goes in for festivals, revelries, luxuries, girlfriends, and all that sort of thing.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: Inevitably.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t lots of terrible appetites sprout up each day and night beside it, creating needs for all sorts of things?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Indeed, they do.

 

SOCRATES: So, any income someone like that has is soon spent. [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And the next thing, surely, is borrowing and expenditure of capital. [e]

 

ADEIMANTUS: What else?

 

SOCRATES: And when everything is gone, won’t the violent crowd of appetites that have nested within him inevitably shout in protest? And when people of this sort are driven by the stings of these other appetites, but particularly [5] of Passion itself, which leads all the others as if they were its bodyguard, stung to frenzy, don’t they look to see who possesses anything that can be taken from him by deceit or force? [574a]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: He must take it from every source, then, or live in great suffering and pain.

 

ADEIMANTUS: He must. [5]

 

SOCRATES : And just as the late-coming pleasures within him do better than the older ones and steal away their satisfactions, won’t he himself, young as he is, think he deserves to do better3 than his father and mother? And if he has spent his own share, won’t he try to take some of his father’s wealth by converting it to his own use? [10]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And if his parents resist him, won’t he first try to steal it and [b] deceive them?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And if he cannot, won’t he next try to seize it by force? [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: I suppose so.

 

SOCRATES: And if, you amazing man, the old man and woman stand their ground and put up a fight, would he take care and be reluctant to act like a tyrant?

 

ADEIMANTUS: I am not very optimistic about the parents of someone like [10] that!

 

SOCRATES : But in the name of Zeus, Adeimantus, do you really think that for the sake of his latest love, an unnecessary girlfriend, he would strike his mother, who is his oldest and necessary friend? Or that for the sake of his [c] latest and unnecessary boyfriend, who is in the bloom of youth, he would strike his aged and necessary father, the oldest of his friends, who is no longer in the bloom of youth? Or that he would enslave his parents to [5] them, if he brought them into the same house?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, by Zeus, he would.

 

SOCRATES: It seems to be a great blessing to produce a tyrannical son!

 

ADEIMANTUS: It certainly does!

 

SOCRATES: What happens to someone like that when the possessions of [d] his father and mother give out and the swarm of pleasures now inside him has grown dense? Won’t he first try to break into someone’s house or snatch the cloak of someone walking late at night? Next, won’t he try to clean out [5] some temple? And in the course of all that, his old childhood beliefs about fine or shameful things—beliefs that are accounted just—are mastered by the new ones that have been released from slavery and, as the bodyguard of Passion, hold sway along with it. These are the ones that used to be freed in sleep as a dream, when he himself, since he was still subject to the laws and [e] his father, had a democratic constitution within him. But under the tyranny of Passion, what he used to become occasionally in his dreams he has now become permanently while awake, and so there is no terrible murder, no food, and no act from which he will refrain. On the contrary, Passion [575a] lives like a tyrant within him in complete anarchy and lawlessness, as his sole ruler, and drives him, as if he were a city, to dare anything that will provide sustenance for itself and the unruly mob around it—some of which have come in from the outside as a result of his bad associates, while others have come from within, freed and let loose by his own bad habits. Isn’t this the life such a man leads?

 

ADEIMANTUS: It is.

 

SOCRATES: And if there are only a few men like that in a city, and the [b] majority of the others are temperate, they emigrate in order to become the bodyguard of some other tyrant or serve as paid auxiliaries if there happens to be a war somewhere. But if they chance to live in a time of peace and calm, they stay right there in the city and cause lots of little evils.

 

[5] ADEIMANTUS: What sort of evils do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: They steal, break into houses, snatch purses, steal clothes, rob temples, and kidnap people. Sometimes, if they are capable speakers, they become sycophants and bear false witness and accept bribes.4

 

ADEIMANTUS: You mean they are small evils—provided there are only a [c] few such people.

 

SOCRATES : Yes. After all, small evils are small by comparison to great ones. And when it comes to producing corruption and misery in a city, all these evils together do not—as the saying goes—come within a mile of a tyrant. But when you get a great number of these people and their followers in a city, and they become aware of their numbers, they are the ones who—[5] together with the foolishness of the people—create the tyrant out of the one among them who has in his soul the greatest and strongest tyrant of all. [d]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Naturally, since he would be the most tyrannical.

 

SOCRATES: That’s if they submit willingly. But if the city doesn’t put itself in his hands, then just as he once chastised his mother and father, he will now punish his fatherland in the same way, if he can, bringing in new [5] friends and making and keeping his once beloved motherland—as the Cretans call it—or fatherland their slaves. And that is surely the end at which the appetites of a man like that aim.

 

ADEIMANTUS: It most certainly is. [e]

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t this what such men are like in private life, before they start to rule? In the first place, don’t they associate with flatterers who are ready to do anything to serve them? Or, if they need something from someone themselves, won’t they grovel and willingly engage in any sort of posturing, the way slaves do? But once they get what they need, isn’t it a [576a] different story altogether?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Yes, completely different.

 

SOCRATES: So, those with a tyrannical nature live their entire lives without ever being friends with anyone, always masters to one man or slaves to another, but never getting a taste of freedom or true friendship. [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t we be right to call people like that untrustworthy?

 

ADEIMANTUS: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And as unjust as anyone can be—assuming we were right in [10] our earlier conclusions about what justice is like. [b]

 

ADEIMANTUS: And we certainly were right.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s sum up the worst type of man, then. He is surely the one who, when awake, is like the dreaming person we described earlier.5 [5]

 

ADEIMANTUS: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: And he evolves from someone who, since he is by nature most tyrannical, achieves sole rule. And the longer he lives as tyrant, the more like that he becomes. [10] “Inevitably,” said Glaucon, taking over the argument.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, won’t the one who is plainly worst also be plainly [c] most wretched? And the one who for the longest time is most a tyrant, won’t he also be most wretched for the longest time, if truth be told? Though the views of the masses6 on the subject are naturally also many.

 

[5] GLAUCON: All that, at any rate, must be true.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t a tyrannical man correspond to and most resemble a city ruled by a tyrant, a democratic man a democratically ruled city, and similarly with the others?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And the comparison between city and city, as regards their virtue [10] and happiness, isn’t it the same as the comparison between man and man?

 

[d] GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: As regards virtue, then, how does a city ruled by a tyrant compare to a city of the sort we described first that is ruled by a king?

 

GLAUCON: They are absolute opposites: one is the best, and the other is [5] the worst.

 

SOCRATES: I won’t ask you which is which, since it is obvious. But as regards happiness and wretchedness, is your judgment the same or different? And let’s not become dazzled by looking at the tyrant—since he is just one man—or at the few who surround him. Instead, as is necessary, let’s go in and study the city as a whole and, when we have gone down and looked [e] into every corner, only then present what we believe.

 

GLAUCON: That’s a good suggestion. And it is clear to everyone that there is no city more wretched than a tyrannical one and none happier than one [5] ruled by a king.

 

SOCRATES: Would it also be right, then, to suggest the same thing about [577a] the men—that the only fit judge of them is someone who can, in thought, go down into a man’s character and discern it—not someone who sees it from the outside, the way a child does, and is dazzled by the façade that tyrants adopt for the outside world, but someone who discerns it adequately? [5] And what if I were to assume that the person we must all listen to is the one who has this capacity to judge; who has lived in the same house as a tyrant and witnessed his behavior at home; who has seen how he deals with each member of his household, when he can best be observed [b] stripped of his tragic costume;7 and who has also seen how he deals with public dangers? Shouldn’t we ask the one who has seen all that to tell us how the tyrant compares to the others with respect to happiness and wretchedness?

 

GLAUCON: That’s also a very good suggestion. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then, in order to have someone to answer our questions, do you want us to pretend that we are among the ones who can make such a judgment, and that we have met tyrannical people already?8

 

GLAUCON: I certainly do.

 

SOCRATES : Come on, then, and examine the matter like this for me. Bearing in mind the resemblance between the city and the man, examine [c] each in turn and describe its condition.

 

GLAUCON: What kinds of things do you want me to describe?

 

SOCRATES: Describe the city first. Would you say that a tyrannical city is free or enslaved? [5]

 

GLAUCON: As enslaved as it is possible to be.

 

SOCRATES: Yet you can surely see masters and free people in it.

 

GLAUCON: I can certainly see a small group of people like that. But pretty much the whole population, and the best part of it, is shamefully and wretchedly enslaved. [10]

 

SOCRATES: If a man and his city are similar, then, mustn’t the same structure [d] exist in him, too? Mustn’t his soul be full of slavery and illiberality, with those same parts of it enslaved, while a small part, the most wicked and most insane, is master? [5]

 

GLAUCON: It must.

 

SOCRATES: Will you describe such a soul as enslaved, then, or as free?

 

GLAUCON: Enslaved, of course.

 

SOCRATES: And, to go back, isn’t the enslaved, tyrannical city least able to do what it wishes?

 

GLAUCON: By far the least.

 

SOCRATES: So, a tyrannical soul will also least do what it wishes—I am [e] talking about the soul as a whole—and will be full of disorder and regret, since it is always forcibly driven by a gadfly.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Rich or poor? Which must a tyrannical city be? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Poor.

 

[578a] SOCRATES: So, a tyrannical soul, too, must always be poor and insatiable.

 

GLAUCON: It must.

 

SOCRATES: What about fear? Mustn’t a city of this sort and a man of this [5] sort be filled with it?

 

GLAUCON: They certainly must.

 

SOCRATES: And do you think you will find more wailing, groaning, lamenting, or painful suffering in any other city?

 

GLAUCON: No.

 

SOCRATES: What about in a man? Do you think such things are more [10] common in anyone than in this tyrannical man, maddened by his appetites and passions?

 

GLAUCON: How could I?

 

SOCRATES: I imagine it is in view of all these things, then, as well as others [b] like them, that you judged this city to be the most wretched of cities.

 

GLAUCON: And wasn’t I right?

 

SOCRATES: Yes, of course. But how, again, do you describe the tyrannical [5] man in view of these same things?

 

GLAUCON: He is by far the most wretched of them all.

 

SOCRATES: There your description is no longer right.

 

GLAUCON: How so?

 

SOCRATES: This man, I think, is not yet the most wretched.

 

[10] GLAUCON: Then who is?

 

SOCRATES: Presumably, you will regard this next one as even more wretched.

 

GLAUCON: What one?

 

SOCRATES: The tyrannical man who does not live out his life as a private [c] individual, but is unlucky, in that some misfortune gives him the opportunity of becoming an actual tyrant.

 

GLAUCON: On the basis of what we have already said, I infer that what you are saying is true.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Yes. But it is not good enough to believe these claims; one must carefully examine someone like that by means of argument. After all, the investigation concerns the greatest thing—a good life and a bad one.9

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: So, consider, then, whether there is anything in what I say. You see, I think we should investigate him on the basis of the following. [d]

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: On the basis of each and every one of the wealthy private citizens in our cities who own many slaves. For they resemble a tyrant in ruling over many, although the number ruled by the tyrant is different. [5]

 

GLAUCON: It is different.

 

SOCRATES: You know, then, that these people feel secure and do not fear their slaves.

 

GLAUCON: Of what have they to be afraid, after all?

 

SOCRATES: Nothing. But do you know why?

 

GLAUCON: Yes. Because the whole city is ready to defend each of its private citizens.

 

SOCRATES: That’s right. But now, suppose some god were to lift one of these men, who has fifty or more slaves, out of the city, and put him [e] down—with his wife, his children, his slaves, and his other property—in a deserted place, where no free men could come to his assistance? Can you imagine the sort and amount of fear he would feel that he and his wife and [5] children would be killed by his slaves?

 

GLAUCON: It would be huge, if you ask me.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t he at that point be compelled to start fawning on some of his slaves, promising them all sorts of things and setting them [579a] free—even though there was nothing he wanted to do less—and wouldn’t he turn out to be a flatterer of slaves?

 

GLAUCON: He would have to be. Otherwise, he would be killed.

 

SOCRATES: Now, suppose the god were to settle many other neighbors around him who would not tolerate anyone claiming to be master of [5] another, but if they caught such a person, would inflict the most extreme punishments on him?

 

GLAUCON: I suppose he would be in even worse trouble, since he would be surrounded by nothing but enemies. [b]

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t this, then, the kind of prison in which the tyrant is held—the one whose nature we have described, filled with multifarious fears and passions? Though his soul is really greedy, he is the only one in the [5] city who cannot go abroad or look at the sights at which other free people yearn to look. Instead, he is mostly stuck in house, living like a woman,10 envying any other citizen who goes abroad and sees some good thing. [c]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t such a harvest of evils, then, a measure of the difference between a tyrannical man who is badly governed politically on the inside—[5] whom you judged just now to be most wretched—and one who does not live out his life as a private individual, but is compelled by some chance to become an actual tyrant and try to rule others, when he cannot even master himself? It is as if someone with a body that is sick and cannot master itself were compelled, not to spend his life in private pursuits, but to compete [d] and fight with other bodies.

 

GLAUCON: That’s exactly what he is like. Your description is absolutely true, Socrates.

 

[5] SOCRATES: And so, my dear Glaucon, isn’t his condition completely wretched, and isn’t the life of a tyrant even harsher than the one you judged to be harshest?

 

GLAUCON: It certainly is.

 

SOCRATES: So, in truth, then, and whatever some people may think, a real [10] tyrant is really a slave to the worst sorts of fawning and slavery, and a flatterer [e] of the worst kind of people. He is so far from satisfying his appetites in any way that he is in the greatest need of most things and truly poor—as is apparent if one knows how to look at a whole soul. He is full of fear throughout his life and overflowing with convulsions and pains, if in fact [5] his condition is like that of the city he rules. And it is like it, isn’t it?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, of course.

 

SOCRATES: And, in addition, shouldn’t we also attribute to the man the [580a] qualities we mentioned earlier? We said that he is inevitably envious, untrustworthy, unjust, friendless, impious, and a host and nurse to every kind of vice; that ruling makes him even more so than before; and that, as a [5] consequence, he is extremely unfortunate and goes on to make those near him so.

 

GLAUCON: No one with any sense could possibly contradict that.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, and tell me now at last, like the judge who [b] makes the final decision,11 who you believe is first in happiness and who second, and judge the others similarly, making five altogether—kingly, timocratic, oligarchic, democratic, tyrannical.

 

GLAUCON: That’s an easy judgment. You see, I rank them in the order of [5] their appearance, just as if they were choruses, both in virtue and vice and in happiness and its opposite.

 

SOCRATES: Shall we, then, hire a herald, or shall I myself announce that the son of Ariston12 has given as his verdict that the best and most just is the most happy, and that he is the one who is most kingly and rules like a king [c] over himself; whereas the worst and most unjust is the most wretched, and he, again, is the one who, because he is most tyrannical, is the greatest tyrant over himself and his city?

 

GLAUCON: You have announced it! [5]

 

SOCRATES: And shall I add that it holds whether or not their characters remain hidden from all human beings and gods?13

 

GLAUCON: Do add it.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that is one of our demonstrations. But look at this second one and see if you think there is anything in it. [d]

 

GLAUCON: What is it?

 

SOCRATES: In just the way a city is divided into three classes, the soul of each person is also divided in three. That is the reason I think there is another demonstration. [5]

 

GLAUCON: What is it?

 

SOCRATES: The following. It seems to me that the three also have three kinds of pleasure, one peculiar to each. The same holds of appetites and kinds of rule.

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: One element, we say, is that with which a person learns; another, that with which he feels anger. As for the third, because it is multiform, [10] we had no one special name for it but named it after the greatest and strongest thing it has in it. I mean we called it the appetitive element [e] because of the intensity of its appetites for food, drink, sex, and all the things that go along with them. We also called it the money-loving element,14 because such appetites are most easily satisfied by means of money. [581a]

 

GLAUCON: And we were right.

 

SOCRATES: So, if we said its pleasure and love are for profit, wouldn’t that best bring it together under one heading for the purposes of our argument and make clear to us what we mean when we speak of this part of the soul? [5] And would we be right in calling it money-loving and profit-loving?

 

GLAUCON: I think so, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: What about the spirited element? Don’t we say that its whole [10] aim is always mastery, victory, and high repute?

 

[b] GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then wouldn’t it strike the right note for us to call it victory-loving and honor-loving?

 

GLAUCON: The absolutely right one.

 

SOCRATES: But surely it is clear to everyone that the element we learn [5] with is always wholly straining to know where the truth lies, and that of the three it cares least for money and reputation.

 

GLAUCON: By far the least.

 

SOCRATES: Wouldn’t it be appropriate, then, for us to call it learning-loving[10] and philosophic?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And doesn’t it rule in some people’s souls, while one of the [c] others—whichever it happens to be—rules in other people’s?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t that why we say there are three primary types of people, philosophic, victory-loving, and profit-loving?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: And also three kinds of pleasure, one assigned to each of them?

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: You realize, then, that if you chose to ask each of these three types of people in turn to tell you which of their lives is most pleasant, each [10] would give the highest praise to his own? Won’t the moneymaker say that, compared to that of making a profit, the pleasures of being honored or of [d] learning are worthless unless there is something in them that makes money?

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

[5] SOCRATES: What about the honor-lover? Doesn’t he think the pleasure of making money is vulgar, while the pleasure of learning—except to the extent that learning brings honor—is smoke and nonsense?

 

GLAUCON: He does.

 

[10] SOCRATES: As for the philosopher, what do you suppose he thinks of the [e] other pleasures in comparison to that of knowing where the truth lies and always enjoying some variety of it while he is learning? Won’t he think they are far behind? And won’t he call them really necessary,15 since he would have no need for them if they were not necessary for life?

 

GLAUCON: He will. We can be sure of that. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Since the pleasures of each kind and the lives themselves dispute with one another—not about which life is finer or more shameful or better or worse—but about which is more pleasant and less painful, how are we to know which of them is speaking the absolute truth? [582a]

 

GLAUCON: I have no idea how to answer that.

 

SOCRATES: Consider the matter this way: how should we judge things if we want to judge them well? Isn’t it by experience, knowledge, and argument? [5] Or could someone have better criteria than these?

 

GLAUCON: No, of course not.

 

SOCRATES: Consider, then. Of the three types of men, which has most experience of the pleasures we mentioned? Do you think the profit-lover learns what the truth itself is like, or has more experience of the pleasure of [10] knowing, than the philosopher does of making a profit?[b]

 

GLAUCON: There is a great difference between them. You see, the latter has to have tasted the other kinds of pleasure beginning from childhood. But it is not necessary for the profit-lover to taste or experience how sweet is the pleasure of learning the nature of the things that are—and even if he were [5] eager to, he could not easily do so.

 

SOCRATES: So, the philosopher is far superior to the profit-lover in his experience of both kinds of pleasures.

 

GLAUCON: Very far superior. [c]

 

SOCRATES: What about compared to the honor-lover? Is he more inexperienced in the pleasure of being honored than the latter is in the pleasure of knowing?

 

GLAUCON: No. Honor comes to all of them, provided they accomplish their several aims. For the rich man, too, is honored by many people, as [5] well as are the courageous and the wise ones. So, all have experienced what the pleasure of being honored is like. But the pleasure pertaining to the sight of what is cannot be tasted by anyone except the philosopher.

 

SOCRATES: So, as far as experience goes, then, he is the finest judge among the three types of men. [d]

 

GLAUCON: By far.

 

SOCRATES: And he alone will have gained his experience with the help of knowledge. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Moreover, the tool that should be used to judge is not the tool of the profit-lover or the honor-lover, but of the philosopher.

 

[10] GLAUCON: What one is that?

 

SOCRATES: Surely we said that judgment should be made by means of arguments. Didn’t we?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And arguments are, above all, his tool.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: If the things being judged were best judged by means of [15] wealth and profit, the praise and criticism of the profit-lover would necessarily[e] be closest to the truth.

 

GLAUCON: It would indeed.

 

SOCRATES: And if by means of honor, victory, and courage, wouldn’t it be [5] those of the honor-lover and victory-lover?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: But since it is by means of experience, knowledge, and argument?

 

GLAUCON: The praise of the philosopher and argument-lover must be closest to the truth.

 

SOCRATES: So, of the three pleasures, then, the most pleasant would be [583a] that of the part of the soul with which we learn, and the one of us in whom it rules has the most pleasant life.

 

GLAUCON: How could it be otherwise? The knowledgeable person at least [5] praises with authority when he praises his own life.

 

SOCRATES: What life and pleasure does the judge say are in second place?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly, those of the warrior and honor-lover, since they are closer to his own than those of the moneymaker.

 

SOCRATES: Then those of the profit-lover come last, apparently.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, that makes two in a row. And twice the just person [b] has defeated the unjust one. Now comes the third, which is dedicated in Olympic fashion to our savior, Olympian Zeus.16 Observe, then, that the other pleasures—apart from that of the knowledgeable person—are neither entirely true nor pure. On the contrary, they are like some sort of illusionist [5] painting, as I think I have heard some wise person say. Yet, if that were true, it would be the greatest and most decisive of the overthrows.

 

GLAUCON: By far the greatest. But what exactly do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: I will find out, if you answer the questions while I ask them. [c]

 

GLAUCON: Start asking, then.

 

SOCRATES: Tell me, then, don’t we say that pain is the opposite of pleasure?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t there also a state of feeling neither enjoyment nor pain? [5]

 

GLAUCON: There is.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it in the middle between these two, a sort of quiet state of the soul where they are concerned? Or wouldn’t you describe it that way?

 

GLAUCON: I would.

 

SOCRATES: So then do you recall the sorts of things ill people say when[10] they are ill?

 

GLAUCON: Which ones?

 

SOCRATES: That nothing is more pleasant than being healthy, but they had not realized it was most pleasant until they fell ill. [d]

 

GLAUCON: I do remember that.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you also hear people who are in great pain saying that nothing is more pleasant than the cessation of one’s suffering?

 

GLAUCON: I do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And there are many similar circumstances, I presume, in which you see people in pain praising not enjoyment, but freedom from pain, and respite from that sort of thing, as most pleasant.

 

GLAUCON: Yes. For at such times, the respite presumably becomes pleasant enough to content them. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And when someone ceases to enjoy something, this respite from pleasure will be painful. [e]

 

GLAUCON: Presumably.

 

SOCRATES: So, the quiet state we just now described as being in between the two will sometimes be both pain and pleasure. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: And is it possible for what is neither to become both?

 

GLAUCON: Not in my view.

 

SOCRATES: Furthermore, when what is pleasant and what is painful arise in the soul, they are both a sort of motion, aren’t they? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And didn’t we see just now that what is neither painful nor [584a] pleasant is a respite and in the middle between the two?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we did.

 

SOCRATES: How can it be right, then, to think that the absence of pain is [5] pleasant or the absence of enjoyment painful?

 

GLAUCON: There’s no way it can be.

 

SOCRATES: So, it is not right. But when the quiet state is next to what is painful, it appears pleasant; and when it is next to what is pleasant, it appears painful. And there is nothing sound in these illusions as far as the truth about pleasure is concerned. On the contrary, they are a sort of sorcery. [10]

 

GLAUCON: That’s what the argument suggests, at any rate.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, take a look at pleasures that do not derive from [b] pains, so that you won’t be likely to think that, in their case, it is the nature of pleasure to be just the cessation of pain or of pain to be just the cessation of pleasure.

 

GLAUCON: Where am I to look? What pleasures do you mean?

 

[5] SOCRATES: There are lots of others, but you might especially want to think about the pleasures of smell. You see, without being preceded by pain, they suddenly become incredibly intense. And when they cease, they leave no pain behind.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: So, let’s not be persuaded that pure pleasure is relief from pain, [c] or pure pain relief from pleasure.

 

GLAUCON: No, let’s not.

 

SOCRATES: However, of the things called pleasures that reach the soul through [5] the body, pretty much the greatest number—and the most intense ones, too—are of that kind: they are some sort of relief from pains.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they are.

 

SOCRATES: And aren’t those pleasures and pains of anticipation, which [10] arise from the expectation of future pleasures or pains, of the same kind?

 

GLAUCON: They are.

 

[d] SOCRATES: Do you know what they are like and what they most resemble?

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: Do you think there is such a thing in the natural world as an up, a down, and a middle?

 

[5] GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you imagine, then, that if someone were brought from down below to the middle, he would think anything other than that he was moving upward? And if he stood at the middle and saw where he had come from, could he possibly think he was anywhere other than the upper region, since he hadn’t seen the one that is truly up above?

 

GLAUCON: By Zeus, I do not see how he could think anything else.

 

SOCRATES: But if he were brought back again, wouldn’t he think he was [e] being brought down? And wouldn’t he be thinking the truth?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t all this happen to him because he is inexperienced in what is truly and really up, middle, and down? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Would it surprise you, then, if those who are inexperienced in the truth have unsound beliefs about lots of other things as well—that they are so disposed toward pleasure, pain, and the middle state that, whenever they descend to the painful, they think the truth and really are in pain; but [585a] that, when they ascend from the painful to the middle state, they firmly think they have reached fulfillment and pleasure? Like people who compare black to gray without having experienced white, don’t they compare pain to painlessness while being inexperienced in pleasure, and so get deceived? [5]

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, it would not surprise me! In fact, I would be very surprised if it were not like that.

 

SOCRATES: Think of it this way, then: Aren’t hunger, thirst, and the like some sort of emptiness related to the state of the body? [b]

 

GLAUCON: They are.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t foolishness and lack of knowledge, in turn, some sort of emptiness related to the state of the soul?

 

GLAUCON: It certainly is. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Aren’t people filled when they take in nourishment or gain understanding?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Does the truer filling belong to what is less or to what is more? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Clearly, it belongs to what is more.

 

SOCRATES : Which of the two types, then, partakes more of pure being? The sorts belonging to bread, drink, relishes, and nourishment in general? Or the kind belonging to true belief, knowledge, understanding, and, in sum, to all of virtue? Judge it this way: what belongs to what is always the [c] same, immortal, and true, is itself of that sort, and comes to be in something of that sort—it is more, don’t you think, than what belongs to what is never the same and mortal, is itself of that kind, and comes to be in something of [5] that kind?

 

GLAUCON: Far more. What belongs to what is always the same is far superior.

 

SOCRATES: And does the being of what is always the same partake any more of being than of knowledge?17

 

GLAUCON: Not at all.

 

[10] SOCRATES: What about of truth?

 

GLAUCON: Not of it, either.

 

SOCRATES: And if less of truth, less of being, too?

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it generally true that the types concerned with the care of [d] the body partake less in truth and being than do those concerned with the care of the soul?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, much less.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t you think the same holds of the body in comparison to [5] the soul?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: Then isn’t what is filled with things that are more, and is itself more, more really filled than what is filled with things that are less, and is itself less?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So, then, if being filled with what is appropriate to our nature is pleasant, what is more filled with things that are more is more really and [e] truly caused to enjoy a more true pleasure; whereas what partakes of things that are less is less truly and surely filled and partakes of a less trustworthy and less true pleasure.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s absolutely inevitable.

 

[586a] SOCRATES: So, those who lack experience of knowledge or virtue, but are always occupied with feasts and the like, are brought down, apparently, and then back up to the middle state; and wander in this way throughout their lives, never reaching beyond this to what is truly higher up, never looking [5] up at it or brought up to it, never filled with what really is, and never tasting any stable or pure pleasure. On the contrary, they are always looking downward like cattle and, with their heads bent over the earth or the dinner table, they feed, fatten, and fornicate. And, in order to do better than others in these things, they kick and butt with iron horns and hooves, killing [b] each other, because their desires are insatiable.18 For they aren’t using things that are to fill the part of themselves that is a thing that is, and a leak-proof vessel.19

 

GLAUCON: You have described the life of “the many,” Socrates, just like an [5] oracle!

 

SOCRATES: So, isn’t it necessary, then, for these people to live with pleasures that are mixed with pains, mere phantoms and illusionist paintings of true pleasures? And aren’t they so colored by their juxtaposition with one another that they appear intense, beget mad passions for themselves in the [c] foolish, and are fought over—as Stesichorus tells us the phantom of Helen was fought over at Troy—through ignorance of the truth?20 [5]

 

GLAUCON: Something like that must be what happens.

 

SOCRATES: Mustn’t similar things happen to someone who succeeds in satisfying the spirited element? Mustn’t his love of honor be so colored by envy, his love of victory by violence, and his spiritedness by peevishness,21 that he pursues the satisfactions of honor, victory, and spiritedness without [d] rational calculation or understanding?

 

GLAUCON: The same sorts of things must happen with regard to that element, too.

 

SOCRATES: Can’t we confidently assert, then, that, even where the desires of the profit-loving and honor-loving parts are concerned, those that follow [5] knowledge and argument, and pursue with their help the pleasures that wisdom prescribes, will attain—to the degree that they can attain true pleasure at all—the truest pleasures, because they follow truth, and those that are most their own; if, indeed, what is the best for each thing is also what is [e] most its own?

 

GLAUCON: But that, of course, is what is most its own.

 

SOCRATES: So, when the entire soul follows the philosophic element and does not engage in faction, the result is that each element does its own work and is just; and, in particular, each enjoys its own pleasures, the best pleasures and—to the degree possible—the truest. [587a]

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: So, when one of the other parts gains mastery, the result is that it cannot discover its own pleasure and compels the other parts to pursue an [5] alien, and not a true pleasure.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And wouldn’t what is most distant from philosophy and reason be most likely to produce that result?

 

GLAUCON: By far.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t what is most distant from reason the very thing that [10] is most distant from law and order?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And wasn’t it made evident that the passionate and tyrannical [b] appetites are most distant?

 

GLAUCON: By far the most.

 

SOCRATES: And the kingly and orderly ones least distant?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then the tyrant, I suppose, will be most distant from a true [5] pleasure that is his own, while the king will be least distant.

 

GLAUCON: It is inevitable.

 

SOCRATES: And so, the tyrant will live most unpleasantly and the king most pleasantly.

 

[10] GLAUCON: It is absolutely inevitable.

 

SOCRATES: Do you know, then, how much more unpleasant the tyrant’s life is than the king’s?

 

GLAUCON: Not unless you tell me.

 

SOCRATES: There are, it seems, three pleasures: one genuine and two illegitimate. [c] The tyrant is at the extreme end of the illegitimate ones, since he flees both law and reason and lives with a bodyguard of slavish pleasures. But it is not at all easy to say just how inferior he is—except perhaps as follows.

 

[5] GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: The tyrant is somehow at a third remove from the oligarch, since the democrat was in the middle between them.22

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t he also live with a phantom of pleasure, then, that, as regards truth, is at a third remove from that other—if what we said before is true? [10]

 

GLAUCON: He will.

 

SOCRATES: But the oligarch, in turn, is at a third remove from the king,23 if we assume king and aristocrat to be the same. [d]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, third.

 

SOCRATES: So a tyrant is removed from true pleasure by a numerical value of three times three.

 

GLAUCON: Apparently. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So, on the basis of the size of this numerical value, it seems the phantom of the tyrant’s pleasure is a plane figure.

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: On the basis of its square and cube, in that case, it becomes clear how far removed it is. [10]

 

GLAUCON: Clear to someone skilled in calculation, anyway!

 

SOCRATES: Turning it the other way around, then, if someone wants to say how far the king is removed from the tyrant in terms of true pleasure, [e] he will find, if he completes the calculation, that he lives 729 times more pleasantly, while the tyrant lives the same number of times more painfully.24

 

GLAUCON: That’s an extraordinary calculation of the difference between [5] the two men—the just one and the unjust one—in terms of their pleasure [588a] and pain!

 

SOCRATES: And yet it is a number that is both true and appropriate to human lives—if indeed days, nights, months, and years are appropriate to [5] them.

 

GLAUCON: And of course they are appropriate.

 

SOCRATES: If the victory of the good and just person over the bad and unjust one in terms of pleasure is as great as that, won’t his victory in terms [10] of its grace, beauty, and virtue be extraordinarily greater?

 

GLAUCON: Extraordinarily greater, indeed, by Zeus!

 

SOCRATES: All right, then. Since we have reached this point in the argument, [b] let’s return to the first things we mentioned that led us here. I think someone said that doing injustice profits a completely unjust person who is believed to be just. Wasn’t that the claim?25

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, it was.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s discuss it with its proponent, then, since we have now agreed on the respective effects of doing unjust and doing just things.26

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: By fashioning an image of the soul in words, so that the one [10] who said that will know what he was saying.

 

[c] GLAUCON: What sort of image?

 

SOCRATES : One of those creatures that ancient legends say used to exist. The Chimera, Scylla, Cerberus, and the numerous other cases where many [5] different kinds are said to have grown together into one.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, they do describe such things.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, fashion a single species of complex, many-headed beast, with a ring of tame and savage animal heads that it can grow and change at will.

 

GLAUCON: That’s a task for a clever fashioner of images!27 Still, since language [d] is easier to fashion than wax and the like, consider the fashioning done.

 

SOCRATES: Now, fashion another single species—of lion—and a single one of human being. But make the first much the greatest and the second, [5] second in size.

 

GLAUCON: That’s easier—the fashioning is done.

 

SOCRATES: Now, join the three in one, so that they somehow grow together naturally.

 

GLAUCON: They are joined.

 

SOCRATES: Then fashion around the outside the image of one of them, that of the human being, so that to anyone who cannot see what is inside, [10] but sees only the outer shell, it will look like a single creature, a human being. [e]

 

GLAUCON: The surrounding shell has been fashioned.

 

SOCRATES: When someone claims, then, that it profits this human being to do injustice, but that doing what is just brings no advantage, let’s tell him that he is saying nothing other than that it profits him to feed well and strengthen the multifarious beast, as well as the lion and everything that [5] pertains to the lion; to starve and weaken the human being, so that he is dragged along wherever either of the other two leads; and not to accustom [589a] the two to one another or make them friends, but leave them to bite and fight and devour one another.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s exactly what someone who praises doing injustice is saying. [5]

 

SOCRATES: On the other hand, wouldn’t someone who claims that what is just is profitable be saying we should do and say what will give the inner human being the greatest mastery over the human being, to get him to take [b] care of the many-headed beast like a farmer, feeding and domesticating the gentle heads and preventing the savage ones from growing; to make the lion’s nature his ally; and to care for all in common, bringing them up in such a way that they will be friends with each other and with himself? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s exactly what someone who praises justice is saying.

 

SOCRATES: From every point of view, then, the one who praises what is just speaks truly while the one who praises what is unjust speaks falsely. For whether we consider pleasure or good reputation or advantage, the one who [c] praises the just tells the truth while the one who condemns it has nothing sound to say and condemns with no knowledge of what he is condemning.

 

GLAUCON: None at all, in my opinion. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s persuade him gently—after all, he is not getting it wrong intentionally—by questioning him as follows: “Bless you, but shouldn’t we claim that this is also the basis of the conventional norms concerning what is fine and what is shameful: what is fine is what subordinates the beastlike elements in our nature to the human one—or better, perhaps, to the divine, whereas what is shameful is what enslaves the tame element to [d] the savage“? Will he agree, or what?

 

GLAUCON: He will if he takes my advice.

 

SOCRATES: Is there anyone, then, in light of this argument, who profits by [5] acquiring gold unjustly, if the result is something like this: in taking the gold, he simultaneously enslaves the best element in himself to the most [e] wicked? If he got the gold by enslaving his son or daughter to savage and evil men, it would not profit him, no matter how much he got for doing it. So, if he ruthlessly enslaves the most divine element in himself to the most godless and polluted, how could he fail to be wretched, when he accepts [5] golden gifts in return for a far more terrible destruction than that of Eriphyle, [590a] who took the necklace in return for her husband’s soul?28

 

GLAUCON: A much more terrible one. I will answer for him.

 

SOCRATES: And don’t you think intemperance has long been condemned [5] for reasons of this sort; that it is because of vices like it that that terrible creature, the great and multiform beast, is given more freedom than it should be?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: And aren’t stubbornness and peevishness condemned because they inharmoniously increase and stretch the lionlike and snakelike29[5] element?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: And aren’t luxury and softness condemned for slackening and loosening this same part, because that produces cowardice in it?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: And aren’t flattery and illiberality condemned because they subject this same spirited element to the moblike beast, allow it to be showered with abuse for the sake of money and the latter’s insatiability, and habituate it from youth to be an ape instead of a lion?

 

[c] GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Why do you think someone is reproached for menial work or handicraft? Or shall we say that it is for no other reason than because the best element is naturally weak in him, so that it cannot rule the beasts [5] within him, but can only serve them and learn what flatters them?

 

GLAUCON: Apparently.

 

SOCRATES: In order to ensure, then, that someone like that is also ruled by something similar to what rules the best person, we say that he should be the slave of that best person who has the divine ruler within himself. It is not to harm the slave that we say he should be ruled, as Thrasymachus supposed [d] was true of all subjects, but because it is better for everyone to be ruled by a divine and wise ruler—preferably one that is his own and that he has inside himself; otherwise one imposed on him from outside, so that we may all be as alike and as friendly as possible, because we are all captained [5] by the same thing.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s right.

 

SOCRATES: This is clearly the aim of the law as well, which is the ally of [e] everyone in the city. It is also our aim in ruling our children. We do not allow them to be free until we establish a constitution in them as in a city. That is to say, we take care of their best part with the similar one in ourselves and equip them with a guardian and ruler similar to our own to take [591a] our place. Only then do we set them free.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s clearly so.

 

SOCRATES: How, then, will we claim, Glaucon, and on the basis of what argument, that it profits someone to do injustice, or what is intemperate, or [5] some shameful thing that will make him worse, even if it brings more money or power of some other sort?

 

GLAUCON: There’s no way we can.

 

SOCRATES: Or how can we claim that it profits him to be undetected in his injustice and not pay the penalty? I mean, doesn’t the one who remains [10] undetected become even worse, while in the one who is discovered and [b] punished, the bestial element is calmed and tamed and the gentle one freed? Doesn’t his entire soul, when it returns to its best nature and acquires temperance and justice along with wisdom, achieve a condition that is as [5] more honorable than that of a body when it acquires strength and beauty along with health, as a soul is more honorable than a body?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t anyone with any sense, then, give everything he has to achieve it as long as he lives? First, won’t he honor the studies that produce [c] it and not honor the others?

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: Second, as regards the condition and nurture of his body, not only will he not give himself over to bestial and irrational pleasure, and live turned in that direction; but he won’t make health his aim nor give precedence [5] to the ways of becoming strong or healthy or beautiful, unless he is also going to become temperate as a result of them. On the contrary, it is [d] clear that he will always be tuning the harmony of his body for the sake of the concord of his soul.

 

[5] GLAUCON: He certainly will, if indeed he is going to be truly musical.

 

SOCRATES: Won’t he also keep order and concord in his acquisition of money? He won’t be dazzled, will he, by what the masses regard as blessed happiness, and—by increasing the size of his wealth without limit—acquire an unlimited number of evils?

 

GLAUCON: Not in my view.

 

SOCRATES: On the contrary, he will keep his eye fixed on the constitution [e] within him and guard against disturbing anything there either with too much money or with too little. Captaining himself in that way, he will increase and spend his wealth, as far as possible by reference to it.

 

[5] GLAUCON: That’s exactly what he will do.

 

SOCRATES: Where honors are concerned, too, he will keep his eye on the [592a] same thing. He will willingly share in and taste those he believes will make him better. But those that might overthrow the established condition of his soul, he will avoid, both in private and in public.

 

[5] GLAUCON: So, he won’t be willing to take part in politics, then, if that is what he cares about.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, by the dog,30 in his own city, he certainly will. But he may not be willing to do so in his fatherland, unless some divine good luck chances to be his.

 

GLAUCON: I understand.You mean in the city we have just been founding [10] and describing; the one that exists in words, since I do not think it exists [b] anywhere on earth.

 

SOCRATES: But there may perhaps be a model of it in the heavens for anyone who wishes to look at it and to found himself on the basis of what he sees. It makes no difference at all whether it exists anywhere or ever will.[5] You see, he would take part in the politics of it alone, and of no other.

 

GLAUCON: That’s probably right.

 

1 A topic briefly discussed at 558d4–559d2.

2 558c–562a2.

3 See Glossary of Terms s.v. do better.

4 See Glossary of Terms s.v. sycophants.

5 See 571c–d.

6 Literally, the many.

7 I.e., the façade referred to earlier. Greek tragedies often had tyrants as characters.

8 Plato spent time with Dionysius I, tyrant of Sicily.

9 See 344e1–3.

10 See 451d7 note.

11 The reference is to the way plays were judged at dramatic festivals in Athens. A herald announced the results.

12 Glaucon, but also, perhaps, his brother Plato.

13 See 367e1–5, 612a8–b5.

14 At 553c5.

15 See 559a1–b7.

16 The first toast at a banquet was to the Olympian Zeus, the third to our savior, Zeus. By combining both in a single form of address, Plato seems to be emphasizing the importance of this final proof.

17 See 477a2–4.

18 See 372e2–373e7.

19 Stegnon: contrasted in the Gorgias (493a1–b3) with the “leaking jar” in which the appetites are located.

20 According to the story, Stesichorus wrote a poem defaming Helen and was punished by being struck with blindness. His sight was restored when he added a verse to the poem in which he claimed that it was a phantom of Helen and not Helen herself who was at Troy. See Phaedrus 243a.

21 Envy, violence, and peevishness are all painful conditions that enhance the honor-lover’s pleasures through contrast.

22 Third because the Greeks always counted the first as well as the last member of a series.The day after tomorrow was the third day.

23 Because the timocrat is between them.

24 Socrates’ mathematics is difficult to follow. He seems to have something like this in mind: the tyrant’s pleasure is a two-dimensional image (a plane figure) of the true, three-dimensional pleasure of the philosopher. Hence, if a one-unit square represents the degree of closeness to true pleasure of an image nine times removed from it, true pleasure should be represented by a nine-unit cube. It follows that the king lives 729 times more pleasantly than the tyrant. However, in order to reach the significant number 729—there are 729 days and nights in a year of 364 twenty-four– hour days and 729 months in the “great year” recognized by the Pythagorean philosopher Philolaus—Socrates has had to make two rather fast moves. First, he illegitimately capitalizes on the Greek manner of counting series in order to count the oligarch twice, once as the last term in his first series (tyrant, democrat, oligarch) and again as the first term in his second series (oligarch, timocrat, king). Second, he multiplies the number of times the tyrant is removed from the oligarch by the number of times the oligarch is removed from the king, when he should have added them. In fact, the tyrant is only five times removed from the king, and so lives only 125 times less pleasantly!

25 See 348b9–10, 360c8–361d3, 392c2–4.

26 See 358b4–7, 367e1–5.

27 See 596b12–e4.

28 Eriphyle was bribed by Polynices to persuade her husband, Amphiaraus, to take part in an attack on Thebes. He was killed, and she was murdered by her son in revenge. See Odyssey 11.326–7.

29 The snakelike element hasn’t been previously mentioned, although it may be included in “all that pertains to” the lion (588e6). It symbolizes some of the meaner components of the spirited part, such as peevishness, which it would be unnatural to attribute to the noble lion. Snakes were thought to guard shrines and other sacred places. Including a snakelike element in the part of the soul dominant in guardians is, therefore, somewhat natural.

30 See 399e5 note.

Book 10

 

SOCRATESNARRATION CONTINUES:

SOCRATES: You know that there are many other things about our city that [595a] make me think we were entirely right in founding it as we did, but I am particularly thinking of poetry when I say that.

 

GLAUCON: What about it?

 

SOCRATES: Our refusal to admit any of it that is imitative. Indeed, the [5] need not to admit it seems even more evident, in my view, now that we have distinguished the elements in the soul from one another. [b]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: Between ourselves—for you won’t denounce me to the tragic poets or any of the other imitative ones—I think all such poetry is likely to [5] corrupt the mind of those of its hearers who do not have the knowledge of what it is really like as a drug to counteract it.

 

GLAUCON: What do you have in mind in saying that?

 

SOCRATES: I will have to tell you, even though a sort of reverential love I have had for Homer since childhood makes me hesitate to speak. You see, he seems to have been the first teacher and leader of all these fine tragedians. [c] All the same, a man should not be honored more than the truth. So, as I say, I will have to tell you.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Listen, then—or rather, answer my questions. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Ask away.

 

SOCRATES: Could you tell me what imitation in general is? You see, I do not entirely understand what it is supposed to be.

 

GLAUCON: So is it likely that I will?

 

SOCRATES: There would be nothing strange in that, since there are many [10] things the shortsighted see before the sharp-eyed! [596a]

 

GLAUCON: That’s right. But with you present, I could not possibly be very eager to speak out even if there were something I saw. So, you will have to do the looking yourself.

 

[5] SOCRATES : Do you want us to begin our investigation with the following point, then, in accordance with our usual method? I mean, as you know, we usually posit some one particular form in connection with each set of many things to which we apply the same name.1 Or don’t you understand?

 

GLAUCON : I do.

 

[10] SOCRATES Then in the present case, too, let’s take any set of many things [b] you like. For example, there are, if you like, many couches and tables.

 

GLAUCON : Of course.

 

SOCRATES : But the forms connected to these manufactured items are surely just two, one of a couch and one of a table.

 

[5] GLAUCON : Yes.

 

SOCRATES : Don’t we usually say, too, that the craftsman who makes each manufactured item looks toward the form when he makes the couches or the tables we use, and similarly with other things? For surely no craftsman [10] makes the form itself—

 

GLAUCON : How could he?

 

SOCRATES : Well, now, see what you would call this craftsman?

 

[c] GLAUCON : Which?

 

SOCRATES : The one who makes everything each individual handicraftsman makes.

 

GLAUCON : That’s an amazingly clever man you are talking about!

 

SOCRATES : Wait a minute and you will have even more reason to say that! You see, this same handicraftsman is able to make not only every manufactured [5] item, but he also makes all the plants that grow from the earth, and produces all the animals, including himself; and, in addition, he produces earth and sky and gods and everything in the sky, and everything in Hades beneath the earth.

 

[d] GLAUCON : You are talking about a wholly amazing sophist!

 

SOCRATES : You do not believe me? Tell me, do you think such a craftsman is completely impossible? Or do you think there is a way in which a maker of all these things could exist, and a way in which he could not? Don’t you see there is a certain way in which even you yourself could [5] make all of them?

 

GLAUCON : What way is that?

 

SOCRATES : It is not difficult. On the contrary, it is a sort of craftsmanship that is widely available and quick—and quickest of all, I suppose, if you are willing to take a mirror and turn it around in all directions. That way you will quickly make the sun and the things in the sky; you will quickly make [e] the earth, yourself and the other animals, manufactured items, plants, and everything else that was mentioned just now.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, their appearances, but certainly not the things themselves as they truly are.

 

SOCRATES: Right! You attack the argument at just the right place. For I [5] think the painter is also one of these craftsmen, isn’t he?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: But you will say, I think, that he does not make the things he makes as they truly are—even though there is a certain way in which the painter also makes a couch. Isn’t that right? [10]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, he also makes the appearance of one.

 

SOCRATES: What about the couch-maker? Didn’t you just say that he does not make the form—which we say is what a couch is2—but only a particular [597a] couch?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, I did say that.

 

SOCRATES: Now, if he does not make what it is, he is not making what is, but something that is like what is, but is not. So, if someone were to say [5] that the product of a couch-maker or any other handicraftsman completely is, he probably would not be speaking the truth?

 

GLAUCON: That, at any rate, is what those who occupy themselves with such arguments would think.

 

SOCRATES: So we should not be surprised if it also turns out to be somewhat dim in comparison to the truth. [10]

 

GLAUCON: No, we should not. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Would you like us, then, to use these same examples to search for that imitator of ours and what he really is?

 

GLAUCON: I would, if you would.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, we have these three sorts of couches. One, that is [5] in nature,3 which I think we would say a god makes. Or is it someone else?

 

GLAUCON: No one, I suppose.

 

SOCRATES: One the carpenter makes.

 

GLAUCON: Yes. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And one the painter makes. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: It is.

 

SOCRATES: So painter, carpenter, and god—these three oversee three kinds of couches?

 

[15] GLAUCON: Yes, three.

 

SOCRATES: Now, the god, either because he did not want to, or because it [c] was somehow necessary for him not to make more than one that is in its nature a couch, made only the one that is what a couch itself is.4 Two or more of these have not been naturally developed by the god and never will [5] be naturally developed.

 

GLAUCON: Why is that?

 

SOCRATES: Because, if he were to make only two, one would again come to light whose form they in turn would both possess, and it would be what a couch itself is, not the two.

 

[10] GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: The god knew this, I suppose, and, wishing to be the real [d] maker of the real couch and not just some particular maker of some particular couch, naturally developed the one that is in its nature unique.

 

GLAUCON: Probably so.

 

[5] SOCRATES: Would you like us to call him its natural maker, then, or something like that?

 

GLAUCON: It would be right to do so, at any rate, since it is by nature that he has made it and all the others.

 

SOCRATES: What about the carpenter? Shouldn’t we call him the craftsman who makes a couch?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And should we call a painter, too, a craftsman and maker of such a thing?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly not.

 

SOCRATES: In that case, what is it you say he is, of a couch?

 

[e] GLAUCON: In my view, the most reasonable thing to call him is this: he is an imitator of what the others are craftsmen of.

 

SOCRATES: All right. So the one whose product is three removed from the natural one, you call an imitator?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: So the tragedian too, if indeed he is an imitator, will be someone who is by his nature third from king and truth,5 and so will all the other imitators.

 

GLAUCON: It looks that way.

 

SOCRATES: We are agreed about the imitator, then. Now, tell me this about the painter: in each case, do you think it is what each thing itself is in [10] its nature that he is trying to imitate, or the products of the craftsmen? [598a]

 

GLAUCON: Those of the craftsmen.

 

SOCRATES: As they are, or as they appear to be? You have still to make that distinction. [5]

 

GLAUCON: How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: This: if you look at a couch from the side or the front or from anywhere else, does it differ in any way from itself? Or, while not differing at all, does it appear different? And similarly with the others?

 

GLAUCON: The latter. It appears different, but is not different at all. [10]

 

SOCRATES: Then consider this very point: at what does painting aim in [b] each case? To imitate what is as it is? Or what appears as it appears? Is it an imitation of an illusion, or of truth?

 

GLAUCON: Of an illusion. [5]

 

SOCRATES: So, imitation is surely far removed from the truth. And the reason that it produces everything, it seems, is that it grasps only a small part of each thing—and that is an illusion. For example, the painter, we say, can paint us a cobbler, a carpenter, or any other craftsman, even though he knows nothing about these crafts. All the same, if he is a good painter, by [c] painting a carpenter and displaying him at a distance, he might deceive children and foolish adults into thinking it truly is a carpenter.

 

GLAUCON: Of course. [5]

 

SOCRATES: In fact, my friend, I imagine that what we must bear in mind in all these cases is this: when someone tells us he has met a human being who knows every craft as well as everything else anyone knows, and that there is nothing of which he does not have a more exact knowledge than anyone else, we should assume we are talking to a naïve fellow. He has [d] been deceived, it seems, by an encounter with some sort of sorcerer or imitator, whom he therefore considers to be all-wise. But that is because of his own inability to distinguish between knowledge, lack of knowledge, and imitation. [5]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, we must next consider tragedy and its leader, Homer, since we hear from some that these men know every craft, everything [e] relevant to human virtue and vice, and even all about divine matters. They claim, you see, that if a good poet is to write beautiful poetry about the things he writes about, he must have knowledge of them when he [5] writes, or else he would be unable to. We should consider, then, whether those who tell us this have been deceived by their encounters with these imitators and do not realize, when they see their works, that they are three [599a] removes from what is, and are easy to produce without knowledge of the truth. For they produce illusions, not things that are. Or whether there is something in what they say, and good poets really do have knowledge of the things about which the masses think they speak so well.

 

[5] GLAUCON: We certainly must consider that.

 

SOCRATES: Do you think, then, that if someone could make both what is imitated and its image, he would allow himself to take making images seriously, [b] and put it at the forefront of his life as the best ability he had?

 

GLAUCON: No, I do not.

 

SOCRATES: But if he truly had knowledge of what he imitates, I suppose he would take deeds much more seriously than their imitations, would try [5] to leave behind many beautiful deeds as his own memorials, and would be much more eager to be the subject of a eulogy than the author of one.

 

GLAUCON: I suppose so. I mean, these things certainly are not equal either in honor or in benefit.

 

SOCRATES: Let’s not demand an account, then, of the other things from [c] Homer or any other poet. Let’s not ask if any of them is a doctor or only an imitator of what doctors say; or which people any of the poets, old or new, has reportedly made healthy, as Asclepius did; or which students of medicine [5] he left behind, as Asclepius did his sons. And let’s not ask them about the other crafts either, but leave them aside. When it comes, however, to the greatest and most beautiful things of which Homer undertakes to speak—warfare, generalship, city government, and a person’s education—surely, it is fair to question him as follows: “My dear Homer, if you [d] are not third removed from the truth about virtue, and are not the sort of craftsman of an image, which is what we defined an imitator to be, but if you are even in second place and capable of knowing what practices make [5] people better or worse in private or in public life, tell us which cities are better governed because of you, as the Lacedaemonians are because of Lycurgus, and as many others—great and small—are because of many other [e] men. What city gives you credit for having proved to be a good lawgiver who benefited it? Italy and Sicily give it to Charondas, and we give it to Solon. Who gives it to you?” Will he be able to name one?

 

GLAUCON: I suppose not. At any rate, none is mentioned even by the [5] Homeridae themselves.6

 

SOCRATES: Then is any war in Homer’s time remembered that was well fought because of his leadership or advice? [600a]

 

GLAUCON: None at all.

 

SOCRATES: Then as you would expect in the case of a man wise in deeds, are we told of his many ingenious inventions in the crafts or other activities, [5] as we are about Thales of Miletus and Anacharsis the Scythian?

 

GLAUCON: There’s nothing of that sort.

 

SOCRATES: Then if there is nothing of a public nature, is Homer said to have been a leader, during his own lifetime, in the education of people who loved associating with him and passed on a Homeric way of life to those [10] who came later? Is he like Pythagoras, who was himself particularly loved [b] for this reason, and whose followers even today still seem to be conspicuous for a way of life they call Pythagorean?

 

GLAUCON: Again, we are told nothing of this kind. Indeed, Socrates, Creophylus, the companion of Homer, would presumably seem even more ridiculous than his name7 suggests as an example of such education, if the story told about Homer is true. You see, we are told that while he was alive, Creophylus completely neglected him. [c]

 

SOCRATES: Yes, we are told that. But, Glaucon, if Homer had really been able to educate people and make them better, if he had been able, not to imitate such matters but to know about them, wouldn’t he have had many companions who honored and loved him? Protagoras of Abdera, Prodicus [5] of Ceos, and a great many others are able to convince anyone who associates with them in private that he wouldn’t be able to manage his household or city unless they themselves supervised his education, and they are so [d] intensely loved because of this wisdom of theirs that their disciples do everything except carry them around on their shoulders. Are we to believe, then, that if Homer had been able to help people become virtuous, his [5] companions would have allowed either him or Hesiod to wander around as rhapsodes, and wouldn’t have clung far tighter to them than to gold and compelled them to come home and live with them? And if persuasion failed, wouldn’t they have followed them wherever they went until they [e] had received sufficient education?

 

GLAUCON: I think what you say is entirely true, Socrates.

 

SOCRATES: Are we to conclude, then, that all poets, beginning with Homer, imitate images of virtue and of all the other things they write about, and have no grasp of the truth? Although, as we were saying just now, a painter will make what seems to be a shoemaker to those who know [601a] as little about shoemaking as he does himself, but who look at things in terms of their colors and shapes.8

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: Similarly, I suppose, we will say that the poet uses words and [5] phrases to paint colored pictures of each of the crafts, even though he knows only how to imitate them; so that others like himself, who look at things in terms of words, will think he speaks extremely well about shoemaking or generalship or anything else, provided he speaks with meter, [b] rhythm, and harmony. That is how great a natural spell these things cast. For if a poet’s works are stripped of their musical colorings and spoken just by themselves, I think you know what they look like. You have surely seen them.

 

[5] GLAUCON: I certainly have.

 

SOCRATES: Don’t they resemble the faces of those who are young but not really beautiful, after the bloom of youth has left them?

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, consider this: the maker of an image—the [10] imitator—knows nothing, we say, about what is, but only about what [c] appears. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s not leave the story half-told. Let’s look at the whole thing.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Go on.

 

SOCRATES: A painter, we say, will paint reins and a bit?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: But it is the saddler and the blacksmith who make them?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Does the painter know what the reins and bit should be like, [10] then? Or do not even their makers—the saddler and the blacksmith—know this, but only the one who knows how to use them, the horseman?

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: So, won’t we say that the same holds for everything?

 

GLAUCON: What?

 

SOCRATES: That for each thing there are these three crafts: one that will use, one that will make, one that will imitate? [d]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Then aren’t the virtue, goodness, and correctness of each manufactured item, living creature, and activity related to nothing but the use for which each is made or naturally developed? [5]

 

GLAUCON: They are.

 

SOCRATES: So it is entirely necessary, then, that the user of each thing has the most experience of it, and that he inform the maker about what the good and bad points are in the actual use of the thing he uses. For example, it is the flute player, I take it, who informs the flute-maker about which [10] flutes respond well in actual playing, and prescribes how they should be [e] made, while the maker obeys him.

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t the one who knows give information, then, about good and bad flutes, whereas the other, by relying on him, makes them? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: So, as regards the same manufactured item, its maker—through associating with the one who knows and having to listen to the one who knows—has correct belief about its good and bad qualities, while its user has knowledge. [602a]

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: What about the imitator? Will he, on the basis of using the things he paints, have knowledge of whether they are good and correct or not? Or will he have correct belief through having to associate with the one who knows and being told how he should paint them? [5]

 

GLAUCON: Neither.

 

SOCRATES: So an imitator has neither knowledge nor correct belief about whether the things he makes are good or bad.

 

GLAUCON: Apparently not. [10]

 

SOCRATES: How well situated the poetic imitator is, then, in relation to wisdom about the subjects of his poems!

 

GLAUCON: He isn’t really.

 

SOCRATES: And yet he will go on imitating all the same, even though he does not know in what way each thing is good or bad. On the contrary, [b] whatever appears good to the masses who know nothing—that, it seems, is what he will imitate.

 

[5] GLAUCON: What else?

 

SOCRATES : Apparently, then, we are fairly well agreed on the following: that the imitator knows nothing worth mentioning about the things he imitates, but that imitation is a kind of game, not something to be taken seriously; and that tragic poets, whether in iambic or epic verse, are as imitative [10] as they could possibly be.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely.

 

SOCRATES: In the name of Zeus, then, this business of imitation is concerned [c] with what is third removed from the truth. Isn’t that right?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Now, then, on which of the elements in a human being does [5] it have its effect?

 

GLAUCON: What sort of element do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: This sort: the same object, viewed from nearby, does not appear the same size, I presume, as when viewed from a distance.

 

GLAUCON: No, it does not.

 

SOCRATES: And the same things appear bent and straight when seen in [10] water or out of it, or concave and convex because sight is misled by colors; [d] and every other similar sort of confusion is clearly present in our soul. It is because it exploits this weakness in our nature that illusionist painting is nothing short of sorcery, and neither are jugglery or many other similar sorts of trickery.

 

[5] GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: And haven’t measuring, counting, and weighing proved to be most welcome assistants in these cases, ensuring that what appears greater or smaller or more numerous or heavier does not rule within us, but rather what has calculated or measured or even weighed?

 

[10] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

[e] SOCRATES: And that is the task of the soul’s rational element?

 

GLAUCON: Yes, of it.

 

SOCRATES: But quite often, when it has measured and indicates that some things are greater or smaller than others, or the same size, the opposite [5] simultaneously appears to hold of these same things.

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: And didn’t we say that it is impossible for the same thing to believe opposites about the same thing at the same time?9

 

GLAUCON: Yes, and we were right to say it. [10]

 

SOCRATES: So, the element in the soul that believes contrary to the measurements and the one that believes in accord with the measurements could not be the same. [603a]

 

GLAUCON: No, they could not.

 

SOCRATES: But the one that puts its trust in measurement and calculation would be the best element in the soul. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So the one that opposes it would be one of the inferior parts in us.

 

GLAUCON: Necessarily.

 

SOCRATES: That, then, was what I wanted to get agreement about when I said that painting—and imitation as a whole—are far from the truth when [10] they produce their work; and moreover that imitation really consorts with an element in us that is far from wisdom, and that nothing healthy or true can come from their relationship or friendship. [b]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: So, imitation is an inferior thing that consorts with another inferior thing to produce inferior offspring.

 

GLAUCON: So it seems. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Does this apply only to the imitation that is visible, or also to the one that is audible—the one we call poetry?

 

GLAUCON: It probably applies to that as well.

 

SOCRATES: Well, let’s not rely solely on a probable analogy with painting. [10] Instead, let’s also go directly again to the very element in our mind with which poetic imitation consorts and see whether it is inferior or excellent. [c]

 

GLAUCON: Yes, we should.

 

SOCRATES: Then let’s put it as follows. Imitative poetry, we say, imitates human beings acting under compulsion or voluntarily, who, as a result of these actions, believe they are doing either well or badly, and so experience [5] either pain or enjoyment in all these situations. Does it imitate anything apart from these?

 

GLAUCON: Not a thing.

 

SOCRATES: So, is a human being of one mind in all these circumstances then? Or, just as in the case of visible representation, where he was split into factions and had opposite beliefs in him about the same things at the [d] same time, is he also split into factions and at war with himself in matters of action? But I am reminded that there is really no need now for us to reach agreement on this question. You see, in our earlier arguments, we were sufficiently[5] agreed about all that when we said that our soul is filled with myriad opposites of that sort at the same time.10

 

GLAUCON: And rightly so.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, it was right. But we omitted something then that I now [e] think we must discuss.

 

GLAUCON: What’s that?

 

SOCRATES: When a good man suffers some stroke of bad luck, such as the loss of a son or something else he values very highly, we also said in our earlier [5] arguments, as you know, that he will bear it more easily than others. 11

 

GLAUCON: We certainly did.

 

SOCRATES: Now, let’s consider this: will he not grieve at all? Or, since that is impossible, will he be somehow measured in the face of pain?

 

GLAUCON: The latter is probably closer to the truth.

 

SOCRATES: Now, tell me this about him: do you think he will be more [604a] likely to fight and resist pain when he is seen by his equals, or when he is just by himself in a solitary place?

 

[5] GLAUCON: He’s sure to fight it far more when he is being seen.

 

SOCRATES: But when he is alone, I imagine, he will venture to say many things he would be ashamed if someone else heard, and to do many things he would not want anyone else to see him doing.

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And isn’t it reason and law that tell him to resist, while what [b] urges him to give in to the pains is the feeling itself?

 

GLAUCON: True.

 

SOCRATES: And when there are opposite impulses in a human being in relation to the same thing at the same time, we say that there must be two elements in him.

 

[5] GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t one part ready to be persuaded to follow the law, wherever the law leads?

 

GLAUCON: Can you explain how?

 

SOCRATES: The law says, as you know, that it is best to keep as quiet as possible in misfortunes and not get irritated, since what is really good or [10] bad in such things is not clear. There is nothing to be gained by taking them hard, nor is any aspect of human affairs worth getting very serious about. And the very thing whose aid we need as quickly as possible in such circumstances is the one our grieving hinders. [c]

 

GLAUCON: Which do you mean?

 

SOCRATES: The capacity to deliberate about what has happened and, as [5] with the fall of the dice, to arrange our affairs, given what has befallen us, in whatever way reason determines would be best. Instead of acting like children who have fallen over, and who hold on to the hurt part and spend their time wailing, we should always accustom our souls to turn as quickly as possible to curing and raising up the part that has suffered a fall and is [d] sick, so as to banish lamentation by means of medicine.

 

GLAUCON: That would be the most correct way to deal with bad luck, anyway.

 

SOCRATES: So it is the best element, we say, that is willing to follow this [5] rational calculation.

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: As for the part that leads us to recollections of our suffering and to lamentations, and is insatiable for these things, won’t we say that it is the element that lacks reason, is idle, and is a friend of cowardice? [10]

 

GLAUCON: We certainly will.

 

SOCRATES: Now, this element—the one that gets irritated—admits of much complex imitation; whereas the wise and quiet character, which [e] always remains pretty much selfsame, is neither easy to imitate nor easy to understand when imitated—especially not at a festival where multifarious people are gathered together in theaters. For the experience being imitated [5] is alien to them.

 

GLAUCON: Absolutely. [605a]

 

SOCRATES: The imitative poet, then, clearly does not naturally relate to this best element in the soul, and his wisdom is not directed to pleasing it—not if he is going to attain a good reputation with the masses—but to the irritable and complex character, because it is easy to imitate. [5]

 

GLAUCON: Clearly.

 

SOCRATES: So, it would at last be right to take him and place him beside the painter as his counterpart. For he is like the latter in producing things that are inferior as regards truth, and is also similar to him in associating [10] with the other element in souls, not with the best one. So, we would also at [b] last be justified in not admitting him into a city that is to be well governed. You see, he arouses and nourishes this element in the soul and, by making it strong, destroys the rational one—just as someone in a city who makes [5] wicked people strong, by handing the city over to them, ruins the better ones. Similarly, we will say an imitative poet produces a bad constitution in the soul of each individual by making images that are very far removed [c] from the truth and by gratifying the element in it that lacks understanding and cannot distinguish greater from smaller, but believes the same things to be now large, now small.12

 

[5] GLAUCON: He does, indeed.

 

SOCRATES : But we haven’t yet brought our chief charge against imitation. For its power to corrupt all but a very few good people is surely an altogether terrible one.

 

GLAUCON: It certainly is, if it really can do that.

 

[10] SOCRATES: Listen and consider. When even the best of us hear Homer, or some other tragic poet, imitating one of the heroes in a state of grief and [d] making a long speech of lamentation, or even chanting and beating his breast, you know we enjoy it and give ourselves over to it. We suffer along with the hero and take his sufferings seriously. And we praise the one who [5] affects us most in this way as a good poet.

 

GLAUCON: Of course I know.

 

SOCRATES: But when one of us suffers a personal loss, you also realize we do the opposite: we pride ourselves if we are able to keep quiet and endure [e] it, in the belief that that is what a man does, whereas what we praised before is what a woman does.

 

GLAUCON: I do realize that.

 

SOCRATES: Is praise of that sort rightly bestowed, then? Is it right to look at the sort of man we would be, not honored, but rather ashamed to resemble, [5] and instead of being disgusted by what we see to enjoy and praise it?

 

GLAUCON: No, by Zeus, that does not seem reasonable.

 

SOCRATES: Yes, it does. At least, it does if you look at it in the following [606a] way.

 

GLAUCON: How?

 

SOCRATES: If you reflect as follows: what is forcibly kept in check in our personal misfortunes and has an insatiable hunger for weeping and lamenting—since [5] that is what it has a natural appetite for—is the very factor that gets satisfaction and enjoyment from the poets. Second, our naturally best element, since it has not been adequately educated by reason or habit, relaxes its guard over the lamenting one, since it is watching the sufferings [b] of somebody else and thinks there is no shame involved for it in praising and pitying another purportedly good man who grieves excessively. On the contrary, it thinks that to be a clear profit—I mean the pleasure it gets. And it would not want to be deprived of it by despising the whole poem. You see, I think only a few people are able to calculate that the enjoyment of [5] other people’s sufferings is inevitably transferred to one’s own, since, when pity is nourished and strengthened by the former, it is not easily suppressed in the case of one’s own sufferings.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true. [c]

 

SOCRATES: Doesn’t the same argument also apply to humor? You see, if there are jokes you would be ashamed to tell yourself, but that you very much enjoy when you hear them imitated in a comedy or even in private, and that you don’t hate as something bad, aren’t you doing the same as with the things you pity? For the element in you that wanted to tell the jokes, but [5] which you held back by means of reason because you were afraid of being reputed a buffoon, you now release; and having made it strong in that way, you have been led unawares into becoming a comedian in your own life.

 

GLAUCON: Exactly.

 

SOCRATES: And in the case of sexual desires, anger, and all the appetites, [d] pains, and pleasures in the soul, which we say accompany every action of ours, the effect of poetic imitation on us is the same. I mean, it nurtures and waters them when they should be dried up, and establishes them as rulers in us when—if we are to be become better and happier rather than [5] worse and more wretched—they should be ruled.

 

GLAUCON: I cannot disagree with you.

 

SOCRATES: In that case, Glaucon, when you meet admirers of Homer—[e] who tell us that this is the poet who educated Greece, and that for the management of human affairs and education in them, one should take up his works and learn them and live guided by this poet in the arrangement of one’s whole life—you should befriend and welcome them, since they are [5] the best they are capable of being. And you should agree that Homer is the [607a] most poetic of the tragedians and the first among them. Nonetheless, be aware that hymns to the gods and eulogies of good people are the only poetry we can admit into our city. For if you admit the honeyed Muse, whether in lyric or epic poetry, pleasure and pain will be kings in your city [5] instead of law and the thing that has always been generally believed to be best—reason.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true.

 

SOCRATES: Let that, then, be our defense for our return to the topic of [b] poetry, which shows that, given her nature, we were right to banish her from the city earlier, since our argument compelled us. But let’s also tell her—in case we are charged with some harshness and boorishness—that there is an ancient quarrel between poetry and philosophy. For such expressions as “the [5] bitch yelping at its master” and “howling,” and “great in the empty eloquence [c] of fools,” and “control by a mob of the omni-wise,” and “the subtle thinkers who are beggars all,” and countless others are signs of this old opposition.13 All the same, let it be said that, if the imitative poetry that aims at pleasure has any argument to show it should have a place in a well-governed [5] city, we would gladly welcome it back, since we are well aware of being charmed by it ourselves. Still, it is not pious to betray what one believes to be the truth. What about you, my friend; aren’t you also charmed by it, especially [d] when it is through Homer that you look at it?

 

GLAUCON: Very.

 

SOCRATES: Isn’t it just, then, for her to reenter in that way, when she has defended herself in lyric or some other meter?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Yes, indeed.

 

SOCRATES: Then we will surely allow her defenders—the ones who are not poets themselves, but lovers of poetry—to argue without meter on her behalf, showing that she gives not only pleasure but also benefit both to constitutions and to human life. Indeed, we will listen to them graciously, since we would certainly profit if poetry were shown to be not only pleasant [e] but also beneficial.

 

GLAUCON: How could we fail to profit?

 

SOCRATES: But if it is not, my dear comrade, we will behave like men [5] who have fallen in love. If they do not believe their passion is beneficial, hard though it is, they nonetheless stay away. And we too, because of the passion for this sort of poetry implanted in us by our upbringing in those [608a] fine constitutions, are well disposed to have her appear in the best and truest light. But as long as she is not able to produce such a defense, then whenever we listen to her, we will chant to ourselves the argument we just now put forward as a counter-charm to prevent us from slipping back into [5] the childish passion that the masses have. For we have come to see that such poetry is not to be taken seriously, as a serious undertaking that grasps truth; but that anyone who listens to it should be careful, if he is concerned [b] about the constitution within him, and should believe what we have said about poetry.

 

GLAUCON: I completely agree.

 

SOCRATES: It is a great struggle, my dear Glaucon, greater than people [5] think, to become good rather than bad. So, we must not be tempted by honor, money, or any sort of office whatever—not even by poetry!—into thinking that it is worthwhile to neglect justice and the rest of virtue.

 

GLAUCON: I agree with you on the basis of what we have said. And so, I think, would anyone else. [10]

 

SOCRATES: And yet the greatest rewards of virtue, and the prizes proposed [c] for it, have not been discussed.

 

GLAUCON: You must have something incredibly great in mind, if it is greater than those already mentioned!

 

SOCRATES: In a short period of time, could anything really great come to pass? I mean, the entire period from childhood to old age is surely short [5] when compared to the whole of time.

 

GLAUCON: It’s a mere nothing.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, do you think an immortal thing should be seriously concerned with that period rather than the whole of time? [d]

 

GLAUCON: I suppose not, but what exactly do you have in mind by that?

 

SOCRATES: Haven’t you realized that our souls are immortal and never destroyed?

 

He looked at me and said in amazement:

 

No, by Zeus, I have not. But are you really in a position to assert that? [5]

 

SOCRATES: I certainly ought to be, and I think you are, too. There is nothing difficult about it.

 

GLAUCON: There is for me. So I would be glad to hear from you about this non-difficult topic! [10]

 

SOCRATES: Listen then.

 

GLAUCON: All you have to do is speak!

 

SOCRATES: Do you think there is a good and a bad?

 

GLAUCON: I do.

 

SOCRATES: And do you think about them the same way I do? [e]

 

GLAUCON: What way?

 

SOCRATES: What destroys and corrupts coincides entirely with the bad, while what preserves and benefits coincides entirely with the good.

 

GLAUCON: I do. [5]

 

SOCRATES: And do you think there is a good and a bad for each thing, such as ophthalmia for the eyes, sickness for the whole body, blight for grain, rot for wood, rust for iron and bronze, and, as I say, a natural badness [609a] and sickness for nearly everything?

 

[5] GLAUCON: I certainly do.

 

SOCRATES: And when one of them attaches itself to something, doesn’t it make the thing to which it attaches itself deficient? And in the end, doesn’t it break it down completely and destroy it?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: So the badness natural to each thing—the deficiency peculiar to each—destroys it, but if that does not destroy it, there is nothing else left [b] to destroy it. For obviously the good will never destroy anything, and again what is neither good nor bad won’t either.

 

GLAUCON: How could it?

 

SOCRATES: So if we discover something, the badness of which causes it to [5] deteriorate but cannot break it down and destroy it, won’t we immediately know that something with such a nature cannot be destroyed after all?

 

GLAUCON: That seems reasonable.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, what about the soul? Isn’t there something that [10] makes it bad?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly. All the things we were discussing earlier: injustice, [c] intemperance, cowardice, and ignorance.

 

SOCRATES: Do any of these break it down and destroy it? Think about it, so we are not deceived into believing that when an unjust and foolish person is caught, he is destroyed by injustice, which is a deficiency in a soul. [5] Instead, let’s proceed this way: just as the body’s deficiency, which is disease, wastes and destroys a body, and brings it to the point of not being a body at all, so all the things we mentioned just now reach the point of not being [d] when their own peculiar badness attaches itself to them, is present in them, and destroys them. Isn’t that so?

 

GLAUCON: Yes.

 

SOCRATES: Come on, then, and look at the soul in the same way. When [5] injustice and the rest of vices are present in it, does their presence in it and attachment to it corrupt and wither it until they bring it to the point of death and separate it from the body?

 

GLAUCON: No, they never do that.

 

SOCRATES: But surely it is unreasonable to suppose that a thing is [10] destroyed by something else’s deficiency and not by its own?

 

GLAUCON: It is unreasonable.

 

SOCRATES: Think about it, Glaucon. We do not even believe that a body [e] would be destroyed by the deficiency belonging to foods, whether it is staleness, rottenness, or anything else. But if the foods’ own deficiency induces bodily deterioration, we will say the body was destroyed through [5] them by its own badness, which is disease. But we will never admit that the body is destroyed by the deficiency belonging to foods—since they and the body are different things—except when external badness induces the natural [610a] badness.

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely right.

 

SOCRATES: By the same argument, then, if the body’s deficiency does not [5] induce a soul’s own deficiency in a soul, we will never admit that a soul is destroyed by external badness in the absence of its own peculiar deficiency—one thing by another’s badness.

 

GLAUCON: Yes, that’s reasonable.

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, let’s refute these arguments and show that what we said was not right. Or, so long as they remain unrefuted, let’s never say that [10] the soul even comes close to being destroyed by a fever or any other disease, [b] or by killing for that matter—not even if one were to cut the entire body up into the very smallest pieces—until someone demonstrates to us that these conditions of the body make the soul itself more unjust and more [5] impious. But when an external badness is present, while its own particular badness is absent, let’s not allow anyone to say that a soul or anything else whatever is destroyed. [c]

 

GLAUCON: But you may be sure no one will ever prove that the souls of the dying are made more unjust by death! [5]

 

SOCRATES: But suppose someone dares to come to grips with our argument and—simply in order to avoid having to agree that our souls are immortal—dares to say that a dying man does become worse and more unjust. We are sure to reply that if what he says is true, injustice must be as deadly as a disease to those who have it, and that those who catch it must [10] die because of its own deadly nature—with the worst cases dying quickly [d] and the less serious ones more slowly—and not as now in fact happens, where the unjust are put to death because of their injustice by others who inflict the penalty.

 

GLAUCON: By Zeus, injustice won’t seem so altogether terrible if it will be [5] deadly to the person who contracts it, since then it would be an escape from evils! But I am more inclined to think that it will be shown to be entirely the opposite—something that kills others if it can, but makes its possessor [e] very lively indeed—and not just lively, but positively sleepless! That’s how far it is, in my view, from being deadly.

 

SOCRATES: You are right. After all, if its own deficiency—its own badness—is [5] not enough to kill and destroy the soul, an evil designed for the destruction of something else will hardly destroy the soul, or anything else except what it is designed to destroy.

 

GLAUCON : “Hardly” is right, it seems.

 

[10] SOCRATES : Then when something is not destroyed by a single bad thing— [611a] whether its own or an external one—clearly it must always exist. And if it always exists, it is immortal.

 

GLAUCON : It must be.

 

SOCRATES : Well, then, let’s assume it to be so. And if it is so, you realize that the same ones will always exist. I mean, they surely could not become [5] fewer in number if none is destroyed, or more numerous either. For if anything immortal is increased, you know that the increase would have to come from the mortal, and then everything would end up being immortal.

 

GLAUCON : True.

 

SOCRATES : Then we must not think such a thing—for our argument does [10] not allow it. And we must not think, either, that the soul in its truest nature [b] is full of multicolored variety and dissimilarity and conflict with itself.

 

GLAUCON : How do you mean?

 

SOCRATES : It is not easy for something to be immortal when it is composed [5] of many elements and is not composed in the most beautiful way—which is how the soul now seemed to us.

 

GLAUCON : It probably isn’t.

 

SOCRATES : Yet both our recent argument and others as well require us to accept that the soul is immortal. But what it is like in truth, seen as it should be, not maimed by its partnership with the body and other bad [c] things, which is how we see it now, what it is like when it has become pure—that we can adequately see only by means of rational calculation. And you will find it to be a much more beautiful thing than we thought and get a much clearer view of all the cases of justice and injustice and of all [5] the other things that we have so far discussed. So far, what we have said about the soul is true of it as it appears at present. But the condition we [d] have seen it in is like that of all the sea god Glaucus,14 whose original nature cannot easily be made out by those who catch glimpses of him, because some of the original parts of his body have been broken off, others have been worn away and altogether mutilated by the waves, and other things—shells, seaweeds, and rocks—have grown into him, so that he looks more [5] like any wild beast than what he naturally was. Such, too, is the condition of the soul when we see it beset by myriad bad things. But, Glaucon, we should be looking in another direction.

 

GLAUCON : Where?

 

SOCRATES: To its love of wisdom.15 We must keep in mind what it grasps and the kinds of things with which it longs to associate, because it is akin to [e] what is divine and immortal and what always exists, and what it would become if it followed this longing with its whole being and if that impulse lifted it out of the sea in which it now is, and struck off the rocks and shells [612a] that, because it now feasts on earth, have grown around it in a wild, earthy, and stony profusion as a result of those so-called happy feastings.16 And then you would see its true nature, whether multiform or uniform,17 or somehow some other way. But we have given a pretty good account now, I think, of what its condition is and what form it takes in human life. [5]

 

GLAUCON: We certainly have.

 

SOCRATES: In the course of our discussion, then, did we respond to the other points, without having to invoke the rewards and reputations of justice, as you all said Homer and Hesiod did?18 Instead, haven’t we found [b] that justice itself is the best thing for the soul itself, and that the soul should do what is just, whether it has Gyges’ ring or not, or even the cap of Hades as well.19 [5]

 

GLAUCON: That’s absolutely true. We have.

 

SOCRATES: So, Glaucon, isn’t it now at last unobjectionable, in addition, also to give back to justice and the rest of virtue both the kind and quantity of wages they bring to the soul, both from human beings and from gods, [c] both during life and after death?

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Then will you give me back what you borrowed from me in the course of the discussion? [5]

 

GLAUCON: What in particular?

 

SOCRATES: I granted you that the just man should seem unjust and the unjust one just. For you thought that even if it would be impossible for these things to remain hidden from both gods and human beings, all the same, it had to be granted for the sake of argument, so that justice itself [10] could be judged in relation to injustice itself.20 Don’t you remember? [d]

 

GLAUCON: I would be unjust if I didn’t!

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, since they have now been judged, I ask on behalf of justice for a return of the reputation it in fact has among gods and [5] human beings; and that we agree that it does indeed have such a reputation, and so may carry off the prizes it gains for someone by making him seem just; since we have already seen that it does give the good things that come from being just, and does not deceive those who really possess it.

 

[e] GLAUCON: That’s a just request.

 

SOCRATES: Then won’t you first give this back, that it certainly does not remain hidden from the gods what each of the two is like?

 

GLAUCON: We will.

 

SOCRATES: But if it does not remain hidden, one would be loved by the [5] gods and one hated, as we agreed at the beginning.21

 

GLAUCON: That’s right.

 

SOCRATES: And won’t we also agree that everything that comes to the one who is loved by gods—insofar as it comes from the gods themselves—is the [613a] best possible, unless it is some unavoidable bad thing due to him for an earlier mistake?22

 

GLAUCON: Certainly.

 

SOCRATES: Similarly, we must suppose that if a just man falls into poverty [5] or disease or some of the other things that seem bad, it will end well for him during his lifetime or even in death. For surely the gods at least will never neglect anyone who eagerly wishes to become just and, by practicing [b] virtue, to make himself as much like a god as a human being can.

 

GLAUCON: It is certainly reasonable to think that a man of that sort won’t be neglected by one who is like him.

 

SOCRATES: And mustn’t we think the opposite of the unjust one?

 

[5] GLAUCON: Definitely.

 

SOCRATES: Those, then, are the sorts of prizes that come from the gods to the just man.

 

GLAUCON: That’s certainly what I believe.

 

SOCRATES: What about from human beings? What does a just man get from them? If we are to assert what is really the case, isn’t it this? Aren’t [10] clever but unjust men precisely like runners who run well on the first leg but not on the return one?23 They leap away sharply at first, but in the end they become ridiculous and, heads drooping, run off the field uncrowned. True runners, on the other hand, make it to the end, collect the prizes, and [c] are crowned as victors. And isn’t it also generally what happens to just people? Toward the end of each course of action and association and of life as a whole, don’t they enjoy a good reputation and collect the prizes that come from human beings?

 

GLAUCON: Of course.

 

SOCRATES: Will you then allow me to say about them what you said about the unjust?24 For I will claim that it is the just who, when they are old [d] enough, hold the ruling offices in their city if they choose, marry from whatever family they choose, and give their children in marriage to whomever they please. Indeed, all the things that you said about the others, I now say about these. As for the unjust, the majority of them, even if they remain [5] hidden when they are young, are caught by the end of the race and ridiculed, and, by the time they get old, have become wretched and are showered with abuse by foreigners and citizens, beaten with whips, and made to suffer those punishments you rightly described as crude, such as racking [e] and burning. Imagine I have claimed that they suffer all such things. Well, as I say, see if you will stand for it.

 

GLAUCON: Of course I will. What you say is right. [5]

 

SOCRATES: Well, then, while the just man is alive, these are the sorts of prizes, wages, and gifts he receives from gods and human beings, in addition [614a] to those good things that justice itself provides.

 

GLAUCON: Fine and secure ones they are, too!

 

SOCRATES: Well, they are nothing in number or size compared to those [5] that await each man after death. We must hear about them, too, so that, by hearing them, each of these men may get back in full what he is owed by the argument.

 

GLAUCON: Please describe them, then, since there are not many things it would be more pleasant to hear. [b]

 

SOCRATES: Well, it is not an Alcinous-story I am going to tell you, but that of a brave man called Er, the son of Armenias, by race a Pamphylian.25 Once upon a time, he was killed in battle. On the tenth day, when the rest [5] of the dead were picked up, they were already putrefying, but he was picked up still quite sound. When he had been taken home and was lying on the pyre before his funeral on the twelfth day, he revived and, after reviving, told what he had seen in the other world.

 

He said that when his soul had departed, it traveled together with many [c] others and came to a daimonic26 place, where there were two adjacent openings in the earth and two in the heavens above and opposite them. Judges were seated between these. And, when they had made their judgments, [5] they told the just to go to the right up through the heavens, with signs of the judgments attached to their fronts. But the unjust they told to travel to the left and down. And they too had on their backs signs of all [d] their deeds. When he himself came forward, they said that he was to be a messenger to human beings to tell them about the things happening there, and they told him to listen to and look at everything in the place.

Through one of the openings in the heavens and one in the earth, he saw souls departing after judgment had been passed on them. Through the other [5] two, they were arriving. From the one in the earth they came up parched and dusty, while from the one in the heavens they came down pure. And the [e] ones that had just arrived seemed to have come from a long journey, and went off gladly to the meadow, like a crowd going to a festival, and set up camp there. Those that knew one another exchanged greetings and those coming up from the earth asked the others about the things up there, while those from the heavens asked about the others’ experiences. They told their [615a] stories to one another, the former weeping and lamenting as they recollected all they had suffered and seen on their journey below the earth—which lasted a thousand years—and the ones from heaven telling, in turn, about their happy experiences and the inconceivably beautiful sights they had seen.

[5] To tell it all, Glaucon, would take a long time. But the gist, he said, was this: for all the unjust things they had done and for all the people they had wronged, they had paid the penalty for every one in turn, ten times over for each. That is to say, they paid for each injustice once in every hundred years of their journey, so that, on the assumption that a hundred years is [b] roughly the length of a human life, they paid a tenfold penalty for each injustice. For example, if some of them had caused many deaths or had betrayed cities or armies and reduced them to slavery, or had taken part in [5] other evildoing, they would receive ten times the pain for each of them. On the other hand, if they had done good deeds and become just and pious, they received commensurate awards.

He said some other things about the stillborn and those who lived for [c] only a short time, but they are not worth recounting. And he told of even greater wages for impiety or piety toward gods or parents, and for murder. He said he was there, you see, when someone asked where the great Ardiaius[5] was. This Ardiaius had been a tyrant in a city in Pamphylia just a thousand years before that, and was said to have killed his aged father and older brother and committed many other impious deeds as well. He said the one [d] who was asked responded: “He has not come here and never will. For in fact this, too, was one of the terrible sights we saw. When we were near the mouth, about to come up after all our sufferings were over, we suddenly [5] saw Ardiaius together with some others, almost all of whom were tyrants—although there were also some private individuals among them who had committed great crimes. They thought that they were about to go up, but [e] the mouth would not let them through. Instead, it roared whenever one of these incurably bad people, or anyone else who had not paid a sufficient penalty, tried to go up. At that location, there were savage men, all fiery to look at, standing by, paying attention to the sound, who grabbed some of these people and led them away. But in the case of Ardiaius and others, they bound their feet, hands, and neck and threw them down and flayed them. [616a] They dragged them along the road outside, lacerating them on thorn bushes. They explained to those who were passing by at the time why they were being dragged away, and said that they were to be thrown into Tartarus. He said that of the many and multifarious fears they experienced there, the greatest each of them had was that the sound would be heard as [5] he came up, and that each was very pleased when it was silent as he went up. Such then were the penalties and punishments, and the rewards that were their counterparts. [b]

When each group had spent seven days in the meadow, on the eighth they had to move on from there and continue their journey. In four days, they came to a place where they could see stretching from above, through the whole heaven and earth, a straight beam of light, like a column, very closely resembling a rainbow, but brighter and more pure. They reached [5] the beam after traveling another day’s journey. And there, in the middle of the light, they saw stretching from the heavens the ends of its bonds—for [c] this light is what binds the heavens, like the cables underneath a trireme, thus holding the entire revolving thing together. From those ends hangs the spindle of Necessity, by means of which all the revolving things are turned. [5] Its shaft and hook were adamant, while its whorl27 was adamant mixed with materials of other kinds. The nature of the whorl was as follows. Its shape was like the ones here on Earth, but from Er’s description, we must think [d] of it as being like this: in one great whorl, hollow and scooped out, lay another just like it, only smaller, that fitted into it exactly, the way nested bowls fit together; and similarly a third and a fourth, and four others. For [5] there were eight whorls altogether, lying inside one another, with their rims appearing as circles from above, while from the back they formed one [e] continuous whorl around the shaft, which is driven right through the center of the eighth.

Now, the first or outermost whorl had the broadest circular rim, that of [5] the sixth was second, third was that of the fourth, fourth that of the eighth, fifth that of the seventh, sixth that of the fifth, seventh that of the third, and eighth that of the second. That of the greatest was spangled; that of the seventh was brightest; that of the eighth took its color from the seventh’s shining [617a] on it; that of the second and fifth were very similar to one another, being yellower than the rest; the third was the whitest in color; the fourth was reddish; and the sixth was second in whiteness.

[5] The spindle as a whole revolved at the same speed, but within the revolving whole the seven inner circles gently revolved in the opposite direction to the whole. Of these, the eighth moved fastest; second, and at [b] the same speed as one another, were the seventh, sixth, and fifth; third, it seemed to them, in the speed of its counter-revolution, was the fourth; fourth was the third; and fifth the second.28

The spindle revolved on the lap of Necessity. On top of each of its circles [5] stood a Siren, who was carried around by its rotation, emitting a single sound, one single note. And from all eight in concord, a single harmony was produced. And there were three other women seated around it equidistant [c] from one another, each on a throne. They were the daughters of Necessity, the Fates, dressed in white with garlands on their heads—Lachesis, Clotho, and Atropos—and they sang to the accompaniment of the Sirens’ harmony, Lachesis singing of the past, Clotho of the present, [5] and Atropos of the future. Clotho, using her right hand, touched the outer circumference of the spindle and helped it turn, pausing from time to time; Atropos, with her left, did the same to the inner ones; and Lachesis used each hand in turn to touch both. [d]

When the souls arrived, they had to go straight to Lachesis. A sort of spokesman29 first arranged them in ranks; then, taking lots and models of lives from the lap of Lachesis, he mounted a high platform, and said: [5]

“The word of Lachesis, maiden daughter of Necessity! Ephemeral souls. The beginning of another death-bringing cycle for mortal-kind! Your daimon will not be assigned to you by lot; you will choose him. The one who has the [e] first lot will be the first to choose a life to which he will be bound by necessity. Virtue has no master: as he honors or dishonors it, so shall each of you have more or less of it. Responsibility lies with the chooser; the god is blameless.” [5]

After saying that, the spokesman threw the lots out among them all, and each picked up the one that fell next to him—except for Er, who was not allowed. And to the one who picked it up, it was clear what number he had drawn. After that again the spokesman placed the models of lives on the [618a] ground before them—many more of them than those who were present. They were multifarious: all animal lives were there, as well as all human lives. There were tyrannies among them, some life-long, others ending halfway through in poverty, exile, and beggary. There were lives of famous [5] men—some famous for the beauty of their appearance or for their other strengths or athletic prowess, others for their nobility and the virtues of their ancestors, and also some infamous in these respects—and similarly for [b] women. But the structure of the soul was not included, because with the choice of a different life it would inevitably become different. But all the other qualities were mixed with each other and with wealth or poverty, sickness or health, or the states in between. [5]

Here, it seems, my dear Glaucon, a human being faces the greatest danger of all, and because of that each must, to the neglect of all other subjects, take care above all else to be a seeker and student of that subject which will [c] enable him to learn and discover who will give him the ability and the knowledge to distinguish a good life from a bad, so that he will always and in any circumstances choose the better one from among those that are possible. He must calculate the effect of all the things we have mentioned just [5] now, both jointly and severally, on the virtue of a life, so as to know what the good and bad effects of beauty are when it is mixed with wealth or poverty and this or that state of the soul; what the effects are of high and [d] low birth, private lives and ruling offices, physical strength and weaknesses, ease and difficulties in learning, and all the things that are either naturally part of the soul or can be acquired by it, when they are mixed with one another. On the basis of all that he will be able, by considering the nature [5] of the soul, to reason out which life is better and which worse and choose [e] accordingly, calling worse the one that will lead the soul to become more unjust, and better the one that leads it to become more just. Everything else he will ignore. For we have seen that this is the best way to choose, whether in life or death.

Holding this belief with adamantine determination, he must go down to [619a] Hades, so that even there he won’t be dazzled30 by wealth and other such evils, and won’t rush into tyrannies or other similar practices and so commit irreparable evils, and suffer even greater ones; but instead will know to [5] choose the middle life in such circumstances, and avoid either of the extremes, both in this life, so far as is possible, and in the whole of the life [b] to come. For this is how a human being becomes happiest.

At that point our messenger from the other world also reported that the spokesman said this: “Even for the one who comes last, if he chooses wisely and lives earnestly, there is a satisfactory life available, not a bad one. Let not [5] the first to choose be careless, nor the last discouraged.”

When the spokesman had told them that, Er said, the one who drew the first lot came up and immediately chose the greatest tyranny. In his foolishness and greed, you see, he chose it without adequately examining everything, and did not notice that it involved being fated to eat his own [c] children, among other evils. When he examined the life at leisure, however, he beat his breast and bemoaned his choice, ignoring the warning of the spokesman. For he did not blame himself for these evils, but chance, daimons,[5] and everything except himself. He was one of those who had come down from heaven, having lived his previous life in an orderly constitution,31 sharing in virtue through habit but without philosophy.

[d] Generally speaking, not the least number of the people caught out in this way were souls who came from heaven, and so were untrained in sufferings. The majority of those from the earth, on the other hand, because they had suffered themselves and had seen others doing so, were in no rush [5] to make their choices. Because of that, and also because of the chance of the lottery, there was an exchange of evils and goods for most of the souls. Yet, if a person, whenever he came to the life that is here, always practiced philosophy in a sound manner, and if the fall of the lot did not put his [e] choice of life among the last, it is likely, from what was reported by Er about the next world, that not only will he be happy here, but also that his journey from here to there and back again will not be underground and [5] rough,32 but smooth and through the heavens.

He said it was a sight worth seeing how the various souls chose their lives, since seeing it caused pity, ridicule, and surprise. For the most part, [620a] their choice reflected the character of their former life. He saw the soul that had once belonged to Orpheus, he said, choosing a swan’s life: he hated the female sex because of his death at their hands, and so was unwilling to be [5] conceived in a woman and born.33 He saw the soul of Thamyris choosing a nightingale’s life, a swan changing to the choice of a human life, and other musical animals doing the same. The twentieth soul chose the life of a lion. [b] It was that of Ajax, son of Telamon, who avoided human life because he remembered the judgment about the armor.34 The next was that of Agamemnon, which also hated the human race on account of what it suffered, and so changed to the life of an eagle. Allotted a place in the middle, [5] the soul of Atalanta, when it saw the great honors of a male athlete, unable to pass them by, chose his life. After her, he saw the soul of Epeius, son of Panopeus, taking on the nature of a craftswoman. Further on, among the [c] last, he saw the soul of the ridiculous Thersites clothing itself as an ape.

Now it chanced that Odysseus’ soul drew the last lot of all, and came to make its choice. Remembering its former sufferings, it rejected love of honor, and went around for a long time looking for the life of a private [5] individual who did his own work, and with difficulty it found one lying off somewhere neglected by the others. When it saw it, it said that it would have done the same even if it had drawn the first-place lot, and chose it [d] gladly. Similarly, souls went from the other animals into human beings, or into one another; the unjust changing into savage animals, the just into tame ones; and every sort of mixture occurred. [5]

When all the souls had chosen lives, in the same allotted order they went forward to Lachesis. She assigned to each the daimon it had chosen, as guardian of its life and fulfiller of its choices. This daimon first led the soul [e] under the hand of Clotho as it turned the revolving spindle, thus ratifying the allotted fate it had chosen. After receiving her touch, he led the soul to the spinning of Atropos, to make the spun fate irreversible. Then, without [5] turning around, it went under the throne of Necessity. When it had passed through that, and when the others had also passed through, they all traveled [621a] to the plain of Lethe, through burning and choking and terrible heat, for it was empty of trees and earthly vegetation. They camped, since evening was coming on, beside the river of forgetfulness, whose water no vessel can [5] hold. All of them had to drink a certain measure of this water. But those not saved by wisdom drank more than the measure. And as each of them drank, he forgot everything. When they were asleep and midnight came, [b] there was a clap of thunder and an earthquake, and they were suddenly carried away from there, this way and that, up to their births, like shooting stars. But Er himself was prevented from drinking the water. Yet how or [5] where he had come back to his body, he did not know, but suddenly recovering his sight he now saw himself lying on the pyre at dawn.

And so, Glaucon, his story was saved and not lost; and it would save us, too, [c] if we were persuaded by it, since we would safely cross the river Lethe with our souls undefiled. But if we are persuaded by me, we will believe that the soul is immortal and able to endure every evil and also every good, and [5] always hold to the upward path, practicing justice with wisdom every way we can, so that we will be friends to ourselves and to the gods, both while we remain here on Earth and when we receive the rewards of justice, and go around like victors in the games collecting prizes; and so both in this life and on the thousand-year journey we have described, we will fare well.

 

1 See 478e7–480a13, 507b2–7.

2 See Glossary of Terms s.v. what it is.

3 I.e., that is in its nature a couch. See 597c2 and 490b3.

4 See 490b3, 532b1.

5 God is called king at Laws 10.904a6.

6 The rhapsodes and poets who recited and expounded Homer throughout the Greek world.

7 It derives from two words, kreas (meat) and phylon (race or kind). A modern equivalent might be “meathead.”

8 See 476b4–8.

9 436b8–c1.

10 439c2–441c7.

11 387d4–e4.

12 See 523b9–524a5.

13 Philosophers, such as Xenophanes and Heraclitus, attacked Homer and Hesiod for their immoral tales about the gods. Poets, such as Aristophanes in his Clouds, attacked philosophers for subverting traditional ethical and religious values. The sources of these particular quotations, however, are unknown.

14 Ancient paintings may have represented Glaucus in the way Plato describes him here. His name appears in the accusative (Glaukon ), suggesting a play on Glaucon Glaukôn ). (

15 Philosophia.

16 See 519a8–b5.

17 Eite polueidês eite monoeidês: having many elements or only one.

18 The reference is to the challenge posed by Glaucon and Adeimantus at 357a1– 367e5. But they, of course, are renewing the challenge posed by Thrasymachus in Book 1 (see 358b1–c1).

19 The ring of Gyges is discussed at 359c6–360c5. The cap of Hades also made its wearer invisible.

20 See 360e1–361d3, 367b2–e5.

21 352a10–b2, 363a5–e4.

22 A foreshadowing of the doctrine of reincarnation introduced below.

23 The race is a sprint from one end of the stadium to the other and back.

24 361d7–362c8.

25 Books 9–11 of the Odyssey were traditionally referred to as Alkinou apologoi, the tales of Alcinous. Included among them is the story in Book 11 of Odysseus’ descent into Hades. Since the word translated by “brave” is alkimou, which is very similar to Alkinou, some sort of pun seems to be involved. The following is one attractive way to interpret it. Alkinou might be taken as a compound of alkê (strength) + nous (understanding) and alkimou as a compound of alkê + Mousa (a Muse). Socrates would then be saying something like: it isn’t a tale that shows strength of understanding that I’m going to tell but one that shows the strength of the Muse of storytelling.

26 See Glossary of Terms s.v. daimon.

27Sphondulon: the circular weight that twirls a spindle in weaving.

28 Plato’s description of the beam of light and the spindle is difficult. He compares the light to hypozomata, or the ropes that bind a trireme together. These ropes seem to have girded the trireme from stem to stern and to have entered it at both places. Within the trireme, they were connected to some sort of twisting device that allowed them to be tightened when the water caused them to stretch and become slack. The spindle of Necessity seems to be just such a twisting device. Hence, the extremities of the light’s bonds must enter into the universe just as the hypozomata enter the trireme, and the spindle must be attached to these extremities, so that its spinning tightens the light and holds the universe together. The light is thus like two rainbows around the universe (or the whorl of the spindle), whose ends enter the universe and are attached to the spindle.The upper half of the whorl of the spindle consists of concentric hemispheres that fit into one another, with their lips or rims fitting together in a single plane. The outer hemisphere is that of the fixed stars; the second is the orbit of Saturn; the third of Jupiter; the fourth of Mars; the fifth of Mercury; the sixth of Venus; the seventh of the sun; and the eighth of the moon. The earth is in the center.The hemispheres are transparent and the width of their rims is the distance of the heavenly bodies from one another. A convincing discussion is J. S. Morrison, “Parmenides and Er.”The Journal of Hellenic Studies (1955) 75: 59–68.

29Prophêtês: a prophet. Here in the sense of someone who speaks on behalf of a god.

30 See 364d3, 576d8.

31Tetagmenê politeia: see 500c2 where the forms the philosopher looks to in designing the constitution of Kallipolis are also said to be orderly.

32 See 364d3, 516e7.

33 According to one myth, Orpheus was killed and dismembered by Thracian women, or Maenads.

34 Ajax thought that he deserved to be awarded the armor of the dead Achilles, but instead it was awarded to Odysseus. Ajax was maddened by this injustice and later killed himself because of the terrible things he had done while mad.

Glossary of Terms

 

being (ousia) Abstract noun derived from einai (to be). The being of (e.g.,) justice is what justice really is.

 

captain (kubernêtês) A combination of our ship’s captain, helmsman, and navigator.

 

city (polis) A canonical Greek polis is a unique political organization. Unlike a modern city, it enjoyed the political sovereignty characteristic of a modern state: it could possess its own army and navy, enter into alliances, make war and peace, and so on. Unlike a typical modern state, however, it was culturally and religiously homogenous and quite small in scale. The territory of a typical polis included a single (usually) walled town (astu), with a citadel (akropolis) and a marketplace (agora), which, as the political and administrative center, is itself often referred to as a polis . But a polis also included the surrounding agricultural land, and the citizens lived both there and in the town proper.

 

cloak (himation) The draped mantle worn by Greek men—and eventually by women as well—throughout the eastern Mediterranean. It was a rectangle of cloth (approximately 9 × 6 feet), which was draped so as to be supported by the left arm, leaving the right one free. Originally worn without a tunic (a sleeveless garment made of two pieces of cloth joined at the sides and shoulders), it was usually worn with one by the fourth century. Men usually wore a triangular loincloth underneath it.

 

craft (technê) “Technê” has the sort of connotation for Socrates and Plato that “science” has for us. Thus fifth-century doctors tried to show that medicine is a technê.

 

daimon, daimonic (to daimonion) Daimons are either gods or children of gods and mortals (Apology 27d–e). They serve as intermediaries between gods and human beings (Symposium 202e). Socrates’ famous daimonion is the voice or sign of a daimon, and so of either a god (Apollo, in this case) or his offspring (Apology 26b– 28a, 31c–d).

 

disputation (antilogikê) Literally, antilogic. Also called eristic.

 

dithyramb Choral song to the god Dionysus.

 

do better (pleonektein) An important notion in the Republic. Connected to pleonexia—wanting to get and have more and more. Pleonexia is the chief cause of injustice (359c), since it leads one to try to get what belongs to other people, what isn’t one’s own. Contrasted with doing or having one’s own, which is, or is the cause of, justice (434a, 441e).

 

eristic Argument that aims at scoring points against an opponent, rather than at discovering the truth (see 537e1–539c3). Contrasted with dialectic, which does aim at the truth (537c9–d8, 539d3–540c2).Also called disputation.

 

excellence See virtue.

 

flute (aulos) Unlike the flute, the aulos is a reed instrument, like an oboe. The aulos was thought to be especially good at conveying emotion.

 

illusionistic painting (skiagraphos) Literally, shadow-painting. Painting in black and white in which shading creates an illusion of volume, as in the cave analogy.

 

irony (eirôneia) Unlike irony as we understand it, eirôneia is correctly attributed only to someone who intends to deceive.

 

judge (dikastês) Literally, a member of a jury. However, Athenian juries combined the functions of deciding guilt or innocence and imposing a penalty that we divide between judge and jury.

 

justice (dikaiosunê) The topic of the Republic. Often broader in scope than our notion of justice and more nearly equivalent to ethical rightness in general. Its opposite, adikia, then has the sense of general wrongdoing.

 

masses, the (hoi polloi) Literally, the many. Ordinary, relatively poor people, who typically made up the majority of a city’s inhabitants. Often contrasted in Greek political thought with “the few,” who were typically rich and often aristocratic.

 

musical training (mousikê) Includes poetry and stories, as well as music proper. Effects characterized at 401d5–402d9, 410b10–412b1, 522a3–b1.

 

pancration A mixture of boxing and wrestling, combined with kicking and strangling. Biting and gouging were forbidden, but nearly everything else, including breaking and dislocating limbs, was permitted.

 

physical training (gymnastikê) Includes dance and training in warfare, as well as what we call physical training. Effects characterized at 401d5–402d9, 410b10– 412b1, 522a3–b1.

 

relish (opson) Anything eaten with the staples, such as the barley and wheat breads.

 

rhapsode Someone who memorized epic poems and gave dramatic recitations of them.

 

sophists Itinerant teachers who charged sometimes substantial fees for popular lectures and specialized instruction in a wide variety of fields, including natural science, rhetoric, grammar, ethics, and politics. They did not constitute a single school or movement and were neither doctrinally nor organizationally united.

 

sycophants Athens had nothing corresponding to our public prosecutors. Private citizens prosecuted cases themselves. By the middle of the fifth century, some Athenians began to make a profession of bringing nuisance suits against others, which they dropped in exchange for a bribe. These people were called sycophants. A vivid sense of their power and importance is conveyed in L. B. Carter, The Quiet Athenian (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).

 

temperance (sôphrosunê) Also self-mastery, self-discipline, good sense, reasonableness, moderation, and (in some contexts) chastity. Someone who keeps his head under pressure or temptation possesses sôphrosunê.

 

thing that is (to on) Because of the ambiguity of the verb einai (“to be”), a thing that is could be: (1) a thing that exists (existential “is”); (2) a thing that is, for example, beautiful (predicative “is”); (3) a thing that is true or something that is (veridical “is”).

 

virtue (arête) If something is a knife or a man, its virtue, as knife or man, is that state or property of it that makes it good (Charmides 161a8–9; Euthyphro 6d9–e1; Gorgias 506d2–4; Protagoras 332b4–6; Republic 353d9–354a2). The aretê of a knife might include having a sharp blade; the aretê of a man might include being intelligent, well born, just, or courageous. Aretê is thus broader than our notion of moral virtue, which tends to be applied only to human beings, and restricted to good sexual behavior or helpfulness to others. Aretê, by contrast, applies to things (such as knives) that are not moral agents, and to aspects of moral agents (such as intelligence or family status) that have nothing to do with sex or with behavior toward others.

 

what it is (ho estin) If we ask what justice is, the correct answer will specify (the) what it is. What we might mean in speaking of the essence of justice.

 

Glossary and Index of Names

 

All dates are BCE.

 

Abdera Greek city on the coast of Thrace. 600c7

 

Achaeans Greek forces in the Trojan War. 389e8, 390e6, 393a1, 4, d5, 394a6

 

Achilles Hero of Homer’s Iliad. Champion of the Greeks in the Trojan War. 388a6, 390e4, 7, 391a4, c1

 

Adeimantus Plato’s older brother. With Glaucon, Socrates’ chief interlocutor after Book 1.

 

Adrasteia Personification of fate or necessity and punisher of pride and proud words. The “bow to Adrasteia” is an apology for an act or statement that might otherwise spur her to take action. 451a4

 

Aeschylus of Eleusis (c. 525/4–456/5) Author of the Oresteia, Seven against Thebes, and other plays. 361b7, 362a3, 380a1, 383a9, 550c4, 563c1

 

Agamemnon King of Mycenae. Husband of Clytemnestra (who killed him) and father of Orestes (who killed Clytemnestra), Iphigenia (whom he killed), and Electra. He led the Greek forces in the Trojan War. 383a8, 390e9, 392e3, 393e4, 522d1, 6, 620b4

 

Aglaeon Father of Leontius. 439e7

 

Ajax One of the Greek heroes who fought at Troy. 468d, 620b2

 

Alcinous King of the Phaeacians in Homer’s Odyssey. 614b2

 

Anacharsis of Scythia (6th cent.) A legendary sage. 600a6

 

Aphrodite Goddess of (sexual) love. 390c6

 

Apollo God of music, medicine, prophecy, and so on. 383a9, 391a5, 394a3, 399e2, 408b8, 427b2, 509c1

 

Arcadia Area in the central Peloponnese. 565d6

 

Archilochus of Paros (c. 756–716) Iambic and elegiac poet who composed the famous fable about the fox and the hedgehog. 365c5

 

Ardiaeus Probably fictional tyrant of Pamphylia (now coastal Turkey) in the myth of Er. 615c6, e6

 

Ares God of war. 390c6

 

Argos City of Agamemnon. 381d8, 393e7

 

Ariston Father of Adeimantus, Glaucon, and Plato. 327a1, 368a4, 427d1, 580b9

 

Aristonymus Father of Clitophon. 328b7

 

Armenius Father of Er. 614b3

 

Asclepius A mythical figure regarded as the first doctor. 405d4, 7, 406a6, c1, 407c7, e3, 408b6, 8, 599c4

 

Atalanta Mythical huntress who would marry only a man who could beat her at running. In most versions of the myth, losers were killed. Melanion received three golden apples from Aphrodite, which he dropped during his race with Atalanta. She stopped to pick them up, and he won the race. 620b6

 

Athena Virgin goddess of the arts and technical expertise of every kind. Patron goddess of Athens. 379e4

 

Athenian 330a3

 

Atreus Father of Agamemnon and Menelaus. 393a5

 

Atropos One of the Fates. 617c3, 5, 8, 620e5

 

Attic Pertaining to Attica, the area in which Athens is situated. 404d8

 

Autolycus Maternal grandfather of Odysseus. 334b1

 

Bendis A Thracian goddess about whose cult, which may have been orgiastic, little is known. Greek artists represent her as a booted huntress rather like Artemis. An Athenian decree of c. 413/2 assigned her a priestess and founded the festival in Piraeus mentioned at the beginning of Book 1. 354a11

 

Bias of Priene (6th cent.) One of the legendary seven sages of Greece. Priene is in Ionia. 335e8

 

Ceos Island in the northwest Cyclades. Home of the sophist Prodicus. 600c7

 

Cephalus A wealthy resident alien in Athens. Father of Polemarchus, Euthydemus, and Lysias.

 

Cerberus Three-headed dog with a snake’s tail that guarded the gates to Hades. 588c3

 

Chalcedon On the Black Sea. Home of the sophist Thrasymachus. 328b6

 

Charmantides of Paeania (c. 500–420) Remains silent throughout the Republic. 328b7

 

Charondas of Catana (6th cent.) Created laws for his native Catane and other cities in Italy and Sicily. 599e3

 

Cheiron A centaur (half man, half horse), famous as tutor of Achilles. 391c3

 

Chimera Mythical beast, “lion in the front, serpent in the back, and she-goat in the middle” (Iliad 6.181). 588c3

 

Chryses Priest of Apollo in the Iliad. 392e3, 393a8, d4, 6

 

Clitophon Young Athenian who gives his name to a (pseudo-) Platonic dialogue. Supporter of Thrasymachus.

 

Clotho One of the three Fates. 617c3, 5, 6, 620e2

 

Cocytus River of Hades. 387b9

 

Corinthian Pertaining to the city of Corinth near the isthmus joining central Greece to the Peloponnese. 404d5

 

Creophylus Epic poet. Follower of Homer. 600b6

 

Cretans People of Crete, an island in the southern Aegean. 452c9

 

Croesus King of Lydia (560–546). 566c4

 

Cronus Greek god. Father of Zeus. 377e8, 378a1

 

Daedalus A legendary sculptor of great skill. His statues were so lifelike that they moved around by themselves just like living things. 529e1

 

Damon of Athens (5th cent.) Pioneering musicologist who had views on the psychological and political significance of music. The few surviving fragments of his writings are translated in Kathleen Freeman, Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1977). 400b1, c4, 424c6

 

Delphi On the slopes of Mount Parnassus above the Gulf of Corinth. Site of the Delphic Oracle. 427b3

 

Diomedes, Diomedean Greek hero of the Trojan War. A type of necessity named after him. 389e5, 493d5

 

Dionysiac Pertaining to Dionysus, the god of wine, intoxication, madness, drama, and so on. 475d6

 

Dorian With the Ionians, one of the two Greek “tribes.” Also the musical mode associated with them. 399a3

 

Egyptians 436a2

 

Epeius Mentioned at Odyssey 8.493 as the man who helped Athena make the Trojan Horse. 620c1

 

Er The son of Armenius. May be a Platonic creation. 614b3

 

Eriphyle Wife of Amphiaraus. Bribed with a gold necklace, she sent her husband to his death in Aeschylus’ Seven against Thebes. 590a1

 

Erôs God of love. 573b7, d4, e6, 574d8, e2, 575a1

 

Euripides of Athens (c. 480–406) Author of the Bacchae, Medea, and many other tragedies. 568a9

 

Eurypylus Greek warrior at Troy whose wounds are treated by Patroclus in Homer’s Iliad. 405e1, 408a7

 

Euthydemus Son of Cephalus and brother of Polemarchus. His role in the Republic is non-speaking. Not to be confused with Euthydemus, son of Diocles, after whom Plato named a dialogue. 328b5

 

Fates 617c2

 

Glaucon Plato’s older brother. With Adeimantus, Socrates’ chief interlocutor after Book 1.

 

Glaucus A human being transformed into a minor sea god by eating a magic herb. 611d1

 

Greece 606e2

 

Greeks 423a9, 452c7, 469b8, c4, 5, e8, 470a1, c5, 7, 8, 9, e9, 471a1, 9, b8, 494c8, 544d4

 

Gyges (c. 685–657) King of Lydia. The story of how he became king is described in Herodotus 1.8–13. 359d1, 612b4

 

Hades God of the underworld, ruler of the dead. Also the underworld itself. 330d8, 363c4, d7, 366a5, 386b4, 10, d9, 392a6, 521c3, 534c7, 596c8, (cap of Hades) 612b5, 619a1

 

Helen of Troy Wife of Menelaus, lover of Paris, and cause of the Trojan War. 586c4

 

Hellespont Narrow strait dividing Europe from Asia. 404c1

 

Hephaestus God of fire, blacksmiths, and craftsmen more generally. 378d3, 389a6, 390c7

 

Hera Wife of Zeus. Queen of the gods. 378d3, 381d6, 390c2

 

Heraclitus of Ephesus (c. 500) One of the greatest of the Presocratic philosophers. He believed that everything is in flux, and that apparent opposites (day and night, alive and dead, up and down) are in some sense unities. As a result, he seems to have denied the law of non-contradiction. 498b1

 

Hermus River on the west coast of Asia Minor. 566c5

 

Herodicus of Selymbria Physical trainer and medical theorist from Thrace, credited with the invention of dietetics. 406a7

 

Hesiod (c. 700) Early epic poet from Boeotia. Author of Theogony and Works and Days. 363a8, 377d4, e8, 466c2, 468e8, 546e1, 600d6, 612b2

 

Homer (c. 8th cent.) Greatest of the Greek epic poets. Author of the Iliad and Odyssey. 334a11, b4, 363a8, 364d4, 377d4, 378d5, 379c9, 383a7, 387b1, 388a5, 389a3, e5, 391a3, 393b1, d3, 6, 396e5, 404b10, c6, 441b4, c1, 468c10, d1, 7, 501b6, 516d4, 545d8, 595b10, 598d8, 599b9, c7, 600a1, 10, b7, 9, c4, d5, e4, 605c11, 606e1, 607a2, d1, 612b2

 

Homeridae Followers of Homer. 599e6

 

Hydra Mythical monster with many heads; when one was cut off, two grew in its place. 426e8

 

Ida Mountain in Crete. 391e8

 

Iliad 392e2

 

Ilium Troy. 393b4, 522d4

 

Inachus River god whose daughter, Io, was turned into a cow by Hera because of Zeus’ lust for her. 381d8

 

Ionian With Dorians, one of the two Greek “tribes.” Also the musical mode associated with them. 398e10

 

Isles of the Blessed A place where good people are said to live in eternal happiness, normally after death. 519c5, 540b6

 

Ismenias of Thebes (active 404–382) A democratic leader who aided the exiled Athenian democrats in 404. He is also mentioned at Meno 90a4–5. 336a6

 

Italy 599e3

 

Ithaca Island home of Odysseus. 393b4

 

Lacedaemonians Spartans. 452c9, 599d7

 

Lachesis One of the three Fates. 617c3, 4, 8, d2, 4, 6, 620d7

 

Laconian Spartan. 544c3, 545a3

 

Leontius Son of Aglaeon. 439e7

 

Lethe River in Hades. 621a2, c1

 

Lotus-eaters Mythical people visited by Odysseus on his ten-year voyage back to Ithaca after the Trojan War. 560c5

 

Lycaean (Zeus). 565d6

 

Lycurgus Tradition lawgiver to the Spartans. 599d7

 

Lydian Lydia was a territory in the west of Asia Minor. 359d1, 2, 398e10

 

Lysanias Father of Cephalus. 330b5

 

Lysias of Thurii and Athens (459–c. 380) Well-known writer of legal speeches and brother of Polemarchus. Socrates discusses a speech attributed to him in the Phaedrus.

 

Marsyas One of the mythical satyrs, part human, part animal. He was flayed alive by Apollo for challenging him to a musical contest and losing. 399e2

 

Megara City between Athens and Corinth. The battle of Megara took place in 409 BCE. 368a3

 

Menelaus Brother of Agamemnon. Husband of Helen. 408a3

 

Midas Legendary king of Phrygia (now central Turkey). As the result of a foolish wish, everything he touched turn to gold. 408b4

 

Milesian Pertaining to Miletus, an Ionian city in Asia Minor. 600a6

 

Momus The god of criticism, blame, and censure. 487a6

 

Musaeus A legendary poet closely associated with the mystery religion of Orphism. 363c3, 364e3

 

Muse(s) Patron goddesses of the various arts, including Calliope (epic), Erato (lyric), Euterpe (flute-playing), Melpomene (tragedy), Terpsichore (dancing), Thalia (comedy). 364e4, 411c9, 499d3, 545d8, 547a7, b1, 548b8, 607a5

 

Necessity 616c4, 617b4, c2, d6, 621a1

 

Niceratus of Cydantidae Son of Nicias. Like Polemarchus, a victim of the oligarchic coup of the Thirty Tyrants in 404 BCE. He remains silent throughout the Republic. 327c2

 

Nicias Athenian general during the Peloponnesian War with Sparta. 327c2

 

Niobe In mythology, daughter of Tantalus. She boasted that she was superior to Leto, mother of Apollo and Artemis, who, in revenge, killed her children. 380a6

 

Odysseus Greek hero of the Trojan War. Hero of Homer’s Odyssey. 334b1, 620c4

 

Olympian (Zeus). 583b3

 

Olympic Olympia in Elis was a panhellenic sanctuary of Zeus. Site of the ancient Olympic games. 465d3, 466a9

 

Orpheus It is not clear whether Orpheus was a real person or a mythical figure. His fame in Greek myth rests on the poems in which the doctrines of Orphic religion are set forth. These are discussed in W. Burkert, Greek Religion (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985). 364e3, 620a4

 

Paeania A rural deme (parish) of Athens. 328b7

 

Palamedes Greek hero of the Trojan War credited with the invention of numbers, writing, and law. Odysseus hid gold in his tent, forged a letter that compromised him, accused him of treason, and had him stoned to death. Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides wrote tragedies about his fate. 522d2

 

Pamphylian Pertaining to Pamphylia, a region in the southern coastal plain of what is now Turkey. 614b4, 615c7

 

Pandarus Trojan warrior, son of Lycaon. 379e3, 408a3

 

Panopeus Father of Epeius. 620c1

 

Patroclus Closest friend of Achilles in the Iliad. 388d1, 391b5

 

Peleus Father of Achilles. 391c2

 

Pelops Father of Atreus. Grandfather of Agamemnon and Menelaus. 380a6

 

Perdiccas Probably Perdiccas II, King of Macedon (c. 450–413). Also mentioned in the Gorgias 471a–e. 336a5

 

Periander (650–570) Tyrannical ruler of the city of Corinth. 336a5

 

Perithous Son of Zeus. 391c9

 

Phocylides of Miletus (6th cent.) Elegiac and hexameter poet best known for his epigrams. 407a7, b3

 

Phoebus Apollo. 383b5

 

Phoenician(s) Pertaining to Phoenicia, a region of the eastern Mediterranean. 414c4, 436a2

 

Phoenix Guardian of Achilles in the Iliad. 390e4

 

Phrygian A musical mode. Phrygia was a large region in Asia Minor. 399a4

 

Pindar of Cynoscephalae (518–438) Lyric poet from Boeotia, most famous for his poems celebrating the victors in the Olympian, Pythian, and other games. 331a3, 365b2, 408b8

 

Piraeus Harbor town of Athens. 327a1, 328c7, 439e7

 

Pittacus of Mytilene (6th cent.) One of the legendary seven sages of Greece. 335e8

 

Polemarchus Son of Cephalus. Brother of Lysias and Euthydemus. Executed by the Thirty Tyrants in 404. Mentioned at Phaedrus 257b.

 

Polydamas Famous athlete from Thessaly in northern Greece. 338c7

 

Pramneian Type of wine. 405e2

 

Priam King of Troy during the Trojan War. 388b4

 

Prodicus of Ceos (5th cent.) Teacher of rhetoric, with an interest in fine distinctions of meaning (Protagoras 337a1–c4, Laches 197d3–5) and the correctness of names (Euthydemus277e4, Cratylus 384a8–c2). Socrates is described as attending some of his lectures Cratylus 384b2–c1, Charmides 163d3–4) and as being educated by him (Meno 96d7). 600c7

 

Protagoras of Abdera (c. 490–420) Famous sophist who held that “man is the measure of all things.” His views are criticized in the dialogue named for him and in the Theaetetus. 600c6

 

Proteus Minor sea god, able to change his shape at will. 381d5

 

Pythagoras of Samos (6th cent.) Developed a way of life in which natural science became a religion. He is credited with discovering the mathematical ratios determining the principal intervals of the musical scale. He seems to have been led by this to believe that all natural phenomena are explicable in terms of numbers. He may also have discovered some version of the famous theorem about right triangles that bears his name. 600b2

 

Pythagoreans 530d8

 

Pythia Priestess of Apollo at Delphi. 461e3, 540c1

 

Sarpedon Son of Zeus in the Iliad. 388c7

 

Scylla Mythical monster shaped like a woman with six heads and twelve feet (see Odyssey 12.85ff., 245ff.). 588c3

 

Scythia Lands to the north of Greece. 435e6, 600a7

 

Seriphian 330a2

 

Seriphus Small island in the Cyclades. 329e8

 

Selene The Moon. 364e4

 

Sicilian 404d1

 

Sicily Island off the toe of Italy. 599e3

 

Simonides of Ceos (c. 548–468) Lyric and elegiac poet. 331d5, e2, 5, 332a7, b3, 9, c6, 334b4, e4, 335e8

 

Siren One of eight Sirens responsible for “the harmony of the celestial spheres.” 617b5, c4

 

Socrates of Athens (469–399) Son of Sophroniscus and Phaenarete of the deme (parish) of Alopece. Chief protagonist of most of Plato’s dialogues and of those of other writers. See Introduction, pages xi–xii.

 

Solon of Athens (c. 640–560) Athenian statesman and poet and founder of the Athenian constitution. 536d1, 599e3

 

Sophocles of Colonus (c. 496–408) Athenian playwright, author of Antigone, Oedipus Tyrannus, and other tragedies. 329b7, c1, 8

 

Sparta Major city of the Peloponnese. Athens’ rival in the 5th and 4th centuries. Sparta was a militaristic and somewhat closed society, always prepared for war. Its citizens, male and female, lived in military camps and ate communally. Plato’s thinking about his guardians reflects Spartan influence.

 

Spercheius River (river god) in the Iliad. 391b2

 

Stesichorus of Himera (6th cent.) Lyric poet. 586c4

 

Styx River in Hades. 387b9

 

Syracusan Pertaining to Syracuse, a city on the east coast of Sicily. 404d1

 

Tartarus The deepest part of Hades. 616a4

 

Telamon Brother of Peleus. Father of Ajax. 620b2

 

Thales of Miletus (6th cent.) First philosopher we know of in ancient Greece. He seems to have regarded water as the fundamental principle of all things and is said to have predicted the solar eclipse of 585. 600a6

 

Thamyris A legendary poet and singer who boasted that he could defeat the Muses in a song contest. For this they blinded him and took away his voice. He is mentioned at Iliad 2.596–600. 620a6

 

Theages of Anagyrus Member of Socrates’ circle. A pseudo-Platonic dialogue dealing with the relationship between politics and philosophy is named after him. 496b7, c1

 

Thebes City on the south edge of the eastern plain of Boeotia. 336a6

 

Themis Daughter of Gaia and Uranus, associated with divine law and justice. 380a1

 

Themistocles of Phrearrhi (c. 524–459) Athenian statesman and chief architect of the Greek victory in the war against the Persians. By building up the navy, he secured Athens’ future as a naval power and paved the way for the increased political power of the poorer classes from which sailors were largely drawn. 329e7

 

Thersites Ordinary soldier who criticizes Agamemnon at Iliad 2.211–277. Odysseus beats him for his presumption and is widely approved for doing so. 620c3

 

Theseus Legendary king of Athens. 391c9

 

Thetis Sea nymph, wife of Peleus, and mother of Achilles. 381d5, 383a9

 

Thrace Area roughly corresponding to present-day northwestern Greece, Bulgaria, and northeastern Turkey. 327a5

 

Thracians 435e6

 

Thrasymachus of Chalcedon (5th cent.) Sophist and rhetorician of note. Some fragments of his writings are translated in Michael Gargarin and Paul Woodruff, Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995): 254–6.

 

Troy City in northwest Asia Minor. Site of Trojan War. 380a6, 393e2, 405e1, 408a1, 586c4

 

Uranus Divine personification of the sky, father of Cronus. 377e7

 

Xerxes (c. 486–465) King of Persia who invaded Greece in the second Persian war (begun in 480). 336a5

 

Zeus Chief among the Greek gods. 329a1, 332a9, c5, 334b7, 340a1, 345b7, e4, 350e8, 370a7, 374e10, 375b11, 376d6, 378b6, 379d3, 5, e1, 4, 380a1, 383a8, 386b3, 390b6, c8, 391c2, 9, e8, 9, 399e4, 400a4, c6, 403b3, 407b4, 423b3, 426b7, 440b8, 441b2, 443b6, 444a7, 445b8, 452b4, 453d4, 459a4, 462a1, 469e6, 472d8, 484d4, 493c7, 505b4, 506d2, 515b10, 521b3, 527c9, 531e2, 534d2, 536c6, 554d5, 564c5, 565d6, 568a8, 574b12, c6, 583b3, 585a6, 588a11, 602c1

 

9781603842761_0394_001

 

Leave a Comment